UK £ý.āā US $ā.āā
üth QUARTER úøùù Q
ISSUE ýý
tpm Best of luck
the philosophers’ magazine
Philosophy and chance
The silence of the lambdas Interview with Kit Fine
PLUS Q Raymond Tallis on mind Q Jesse Norman interview Q Altruistic machines Q Illness Q Cyberwar Q Portraits of philosophers Q Disgusting art Q News Q Columns Q Reviews
THOUGHT PROVOKING THOUGHTS
100
of the Most Important Arguments in Western Philosophy
JUST THE ARGUMENTS EEdited by Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone Cutting through dense philosophical prose, C 1100 famous and influential arguments are ppresented in their essence, with premises, cconclusions and logical form plainly iidentified. Key quotations and contextual bbackground provide a sense of style and aapproach.
NEW!
Designed to offer a quick and compact D rreference to everything from Aquinas's ""Five Ways" to prove the existence of God to tthe metaphysical possibilities of zombie minds, Just the Arguments is an invaluable m oone-stop argument shop. ISBN: 9781444336382 | September 2011 | c.424pp | ÂŁ14.99
For further information about this title and more, please visit
www.wiley.com/go/philosophy Wiley-Blackwell books are available from all good bookshops or direct from www.wiley.com
highlights Issue ýý • üth quarter úøùù
COVER STORY Take your chances Moral luck, knowledge, freedom and more
þø ùā Philosophy’s deep waters Kit Fine on objects and possibilities
Neuroneurosis Raymond Tallis knocks your brains out
ûù 4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
Contents Issue ýý • üth quarter úøùù
ACTIONS & EVENTS
4 5
From the editor News
66
Obituaries
72
Mediawatch
77
Threads Feature: Fighting closure Word of Mouse
82 87
Sci-Phi Nice robots finish first
31
93
Illness or moral failing? Rachel Cooper on disorders
48
Letter from … Joe Friggieri in Malta
52
Pop culture Is Superman un-American?
97
Snapshot: Thomas Reid James A Harris perceives things
TPM Essay Raymond Tallis on the brain
43
Suffering misfortune
THE LOWDOWN
Kit Fine’s cure for vagueness
28
You don’t believe in luck
Alexander Brown on social justice
THOUGHTS The Interview
Luck of the draw
Darren Domsky explains why
Waging cyberwar
19
Luck and happiness
Nafsika Athanassoulis on morality and jammed guns
Nina Power examines the strategies
17
The problem of lucky guesses
John Sellars takes the stoics’ tough line
Working-class heroes
14
An open future
Duncan Pritchard has a solution
Philosophy and philosophers in the mass media
12
61
Alfred Mele on chance and choice New protest, New College
8 10
FORUM
Pyke’s portraits Cynthia Freeland considers the faces of philosophers
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
ÿú
The Philosophers’ Magazine, ü Saddler Street, Durham, DHù ûNP, UK Tel: øùāù ûĀûù ĀĀā Fax: øùāù ûĀþú ýüú editor@philosophersmag.com www.philosophersmag.com Editor Editor-in-chief Reviews editor Obituaries
James Garvey Julian Baggini Jean Kazez Adam Ferner
Editorial Advisory Board Miranda Fricker, Simon Glendinning, Daniel D Hutto, Susan James, David Papineau, Nina Power, Anthony Price, Jonathan Rée, Richard Schoch, Barry C Smith, Jonathan Wolff
āÿ
Illustrations/Graphics Felix Bennett, Adam Ferner, Gareth Southwell
REVIEW
100
New books, etc Selves, poems, votes, beers and a film
114
Author Q & A Carolyn Korsmeyer on disgusting art
116
Contributors' Notes Contact the editor to submit proposals. Please do not send unsolicited manuscripts.
Imagine that Balloon world
119
Review of reviews What the critics said about Dworkin and Ramachandran
Printed by MPG Books Group
My philosophy Jesse Norman on big ideas in politics
127
UK distribution Central Books, 99 Wallis Road, London E9 5LN Tel: 020 8985 4854 North America distribution Source Interlink, 27500 Riverview Center Blvd., Bonita Springs, Florida 34134 Tel: (239) 949-4450
LAST WORD
120
Contributors Michael Antony, Nafsika Athanassoulis, Ophelia Benson, Alexander Brown, Rachel Cooper, Darren Domsky, Luciano Floridi, Cynthia Freeland, Joe Friggieri, Wendy M Grossman, Steven Hales, James A Harris, Alan Haworth, Robert J Howell, Mathew Iredale, Rodger Jackson, Troy Jollimore, Jane Clare Jones, Amy Kind, John Koethe, Carolyn Korsmeyer, Alfred Mele, James O’Connor, Duncan Pritchard, Nina Power, George Rowe, John Sellars, Raymond Tallis, Andrew Terjesen
The Skeptic When science is messy
Subscriptions UK: +44 (0) 1442 820580 North America: 1 800 444 2419 See page 11 for full details © 2011 Acumen Publishing Ltd and contributors ISSN 1354-814X
ùùþ
All views expressed in TPM represent those of the authors of each article and do not necessarily reflect those of the editors or publisher. Cover Original artwork by Felix Bennett
4TH QUARTER 2011 4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm tpm
editorial
from the editor
T
here’s this bit in The Clouds, one of Aristophanes’ digs at Socrates:
4
Meanwhile, at least some philosophers get tied up in knots over problems no one else is even able to see. Many ages harbour a mind
Student of Socrates: Socrates asked Chaerephon
who’s just too far ahead of the game. What must
how many of its own feet a flea could jump –
that be like, how would it feel to be a genius
one had bitten Chaerephon’s brow and then
accused of time wasting by the pointy-headed
jumped to Socrates’ head.
Aristophanes of your day? Think of Frege, who
Strepsiades: And how did he measure the jump?
died largely misunderstood and uncelebrated,
Student: Most ingeniously. He melted wax,
never knowing his place at the start of analytic
caught the flea, dipped its feet, and the hard-
philosophy. But at least he knew he had the
ened wax made Persian slippers. Unfastening
goods. He left his papers to his adopted son,
these, he found their size.
with this note:
Strepsiades: Royal Zeus! What an acute intellect! “Dear Alfred, It’s slightly disconcerting that the view of philos-
Do not scorn my handwritten material. Even if
ophers as oddballs drawn to their own pointless
all is not gold, there is gold in it nevertheless. I
problems is still alive in some quarters 2,000
believe that some of it will one day be held in
years later. The uncharitable will suggest that
much greater esteem than now. See to it that
maybe there’s something to it.
nothing gets lost.
Maybe there’s something to it. Aristophanes can make you wonder whether philosophical problems matter at all to anyone
With love, your father It is a large part of myself that I here bequeath to you.”
other than the person with the flea in his hair. Is that possibility such a bad thing?
There’s truth in that last line. When a phil-
The headlines might turn out to be all wrong.
osophical problem bothers you, you really do
Maybe philosophy isn’t the love of wisdom or the
put a part of yourself in your answer. If others
pursuit of truth. It might be nearer an effort to
aren’t connected to the problem in the same way,
think through your own conception of things, make
then they might hear only yammering about flea
things clearer for yourself, and render coherent
feet. It can make you wonder how sure anyone
your own outlook. If someone else is interested too,
pushing Aristophanes’ line can ever be about the
wonderful, but in stockpiling all of your premises
interests of philosophers. Unless you’re bound
and conclusions, the only person you will ever
up in philosophy, you’ll never get hold of what-
convince is yourself. And that’s if you’re lucky.
ever it is.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
actions & events/news
news Big society protest PHILOSOPHERS HAVE RESIGNED over plans to make research funding dependent on government objectives. The Observer reported that the Arts and Humanities Research Council (AHRC), the UK’s main research funding body, must spend a considerable percentage of its £100 million funding on research involving the prime minister’s vision of the “big society”. Disquiet among UK academics is growing. A petition against the requirement has over 4,000 signatories, and public letters of protest from academics and over thirty learned societies call for plans to be scrapped. On 21 June more than forty members of the AHRC’s peer review college announced that they intended to resign en masse if “no clear steps” were taken to remove references to the big society from the AHRC delivery plan for 2011–15. According to Thom Brooks, who is involved in the campaign, nearly fifty senior academics have so far resigned, including the philosophers Antony
Duff at Stirling, Emma Borg at Reading, and Leslie Green at the University of Oxford. Brooks, a reader in political and legal philosophy at Newcastle, told tpm that resignations are a matter “of principle, not politics”, arguing that “a political campaign slogan” has “no place in research council delivery plans”. Borg explained her resignation to tpm by emphasising the importance of keeping “research priorities … free of party political ideology”. The AHRC has not changed the wording of its delivery plan, despite what Brooks describes as “genuinely unprecedented opposition”. While being “very disappointed” by the Council’s response, Brooks told tpm that the campaign remains active, and he intends to explore a possible inconsistency between the plan and the AHRC’s code of practice. According to Brooks, this states that there must be no “grounds for criticism that public funds are being used for private, partisan or party political purposes.” Jane Clare Jones
Crispin Wright rambles ON úý JULY CRISPIN WRIGHT, professor of philos-
ophy at New York University and director of the Northern Institute of Philosophy, began walking the 268 miles of the Pennine Way in the company of his son. The sponsored ramble will raise funds to allow early career philosophers to visit the Institute, and is intended to support its mission of fostering
philosophical collaboration, building a “developmental environment” for PhD and post-doctoral researchers, which Wright regards as “brilliantly successful”. Over the course of twenty-one days Wright will answer the most popular twenty-one questions as voted for by sponsors on the Institute’s website (abdn.ac.uk/philosophy/nip). JCJ
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
5
The NCH was then accused of “syllabus plagiarism” days after publishing its own course specifications. Author, presenter and historian Amanda Vickery tweeted: “NCH seems to have ripped off London Univ’s international programme in history”. The NCH spokesperson explained that their “students will be following the published University of London syllabus, as part of what New College of the Humanities will be doing is preparing students for degrees awarded by the University of London through its International Programmes. This is the syllabus that is on our website.” In a response to an open letter of objection written by colleagues at Birkbeck College, Grayling wrote in the Guardian, “I cannot see why independent initiatives must be demonised or blocked because of our anxiety about what is happening in the public domain. What is the logic of that? In all the criticism – and from some quarters the painful personal hostility – I have seen only an emotional case for scapegoating our project.” The college’s first student intake is scheduled for September 2012.
ON ý JUNE THE PHILOSOPHER A C GRAYLING
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
George Rowe
Matthias Asgeirsson
announced plans to open a privately owned university in London, called the New College of the Humanities. Fourteen “celebrity academics” are on board, including Richard Dawkins, Stephen Pinker and Ronald Dworkin. But as Grayling told the Guardian a few days later, the move made him a “figure of vitriol” among students and academics. Questions first arose as to how much regular teaching the high-flying professoriate would actually do. Grayling explained in the Guardian, “All these people are partners in the enterprise. They are not the full-time academic staff who are delivering the curriculum”. Nevertheless, he said, “All of them have agreed to come and give lectures in the college.” tpm contacted the college’s media office, and when asked what made the courses worth fees double the national average, a spokesperson for “the NCH team” replied, “The added value of study at NCH lies in the intensity and quality of the teaching and learning, including increased contact hours, one-to-one-tutorials, lectures by highly distinguished professors, and an exceptional staff-student ratio.” Not everyone is convinced. Sally Hunt, general secretary of the University and College Union, told the BBC, “While many would love the opportunity to be taught by the likes of A C Grayling and Richard Dawkins, at £18,000 a go it seems it won’t be the very brightest but those with the deepest pockets who are afforded the chance.” Grayling has become the target of protests by students concerned about high fees in education generally. At an event called “The Arts in Britain – Death by a Thousand Cuts”, where he appeared just two days after announcing plans for the new college, he was loudly heckled during his talk. The room was evacuated when a protester let off a smoke bomb.
cc
actions & events/news 6
School of hard knocks
Richard Dawkins
SOCIAL AND COGNITIVE SCIENTISTS Dan Sperber and Hugo Mercier claim that the human ability to reason evolved primarily to allow us to persuade each other. Their “argumentative theory” of reasoning directly challenges the orthodox view that the main function of reasoning is to improve our knowledge and decision-making. An outline of the theory, with commentaries and a response from the authors, was published in Behavioral and Brain Sciences in March. Much of the subsequent coverage focused on the adversarial aspects of the argumentative view of reasoning: “Reason Seen More as Weapon Than Path to Truth”, as The New York Times headline had it in June. Some found Mercier’s and Sperber’s
approach excessively narrow, with psychologist Darcia Narvaez remarking in the same journal issue: “The research tasks used and interpretations employed seem to presume that humans are primarily self-interested, a notoriously implausible view outside the West.” In responding to critics, Mercier and Sperber contend that argumentative reasoning has not only rhetorical but also evaluative goals. To counter our susceptibility to being misinformed in the course of mutual persuasion, they suggest in other publications, that “epistemic vigilance” may have evolved biologically alongside the argumentative function of human communication. James O’Connor
Gaga not friends with Žižek shocker cc
THE BLOGOSPHERE HUMMED IN ANTICIPATION as
Stephen Carlile
Lady Gaga
Lady Gaga and Slavoj Žižek were expected to speak at a University College Union strike in London on 22 March. Rumours then circulated that the fashionable Marxist philosopher struck up an unlikely friendship with the Mother Monster. On 21 June The New York Post reported that the pair spent time together “discussing feminism and human creativity”, and cited a blog in which Žižek referred to Gaga as his “good friend”. The entry, entitled “Communism Knows No Monster”, praises Gaga’s meat dress for highlighting the “linking in … patriarchy of the female body and meat”. Those familiar with the philosopher’s work will perhaps be unsurprised to learn that Žižek has not developed an ardent concern with patriarchal objectification. Indeed, Žižek told the Post that the blog was a “fake” and that the “only thing I share with her is the support for the strike”. JCJ
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
actions & events/news
The origin of specious
7
actions & events/news 8
In memoriam ALASTAIR GUNN, associate professor of philosophy at the University of Waikato, died on 21 May 2011. Having studied at the University of Sussex, Gunn moved to New Zealand in 1969 to teach at Waikato. According to his colleague, David Lumsden, Gunn only intended to stay for two years, but the department became his home for the next forty-two. During that time he introduced a number of innovative new courses to the syllabus, perhaps most notably a course in environmental ethics in 1979, a first for Australasian universities. In addition to his work on the environment, Gunn published on business and health ethics, and wrote three books on
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
engineering ethics with Aarne Vesilind. He was renowned about the campus as a teacher whose courses inspired and challenged generations of students. In an interview in 2010, he describes how greatly he enjoyed teaching, researching and writing: “They feel more like hobbies”, he said, adding, with a dryness most academics will appreciate, “it’s the markings and meetings that feel like work”.
His Libertarianism: A Political Philosophy for Tomorrow became one of the movement’s foundational texts, and in 1972 he stood as the first Libertarian, and, indeed, first openly gay nominee for president. (In later life, his relationship with the party became fraught, over issues of immigration, and he left to help set up the Republican Liberty Caucus.) He is also known for his brief, but intense, friendship with the novelist Ayn Rand, and more recently his controversial defence of the Iraq War in a revised edition of Libertarianism.
JOHN HOSPERS, professor
of philosophy and the first presidential nominee for the US Libertarian party, died on 12 June 2011 at the age of 93. Born and raised in Pella, Iowa, Hospers studied at the University of Iowa before receiving a scholarship to Columbia University in 1941. There, he worked under G E Moore, and completed his PhD in 1944; his doctoral dissertation was published as Meaning and Truth in Arts. In addition to his research and writing on ethics and aesthetics (his book Human Conduct remains in wide use), Hospers is known for his involvement in the formation of the American Libertarian party.
GARETH B MATTHEWS,
professor of philosophy at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst, died on 17 April 2011. Matthews was awarded his BA at Franklin College in Indiana in 1951, and received his PhD from Harvard ten years later. Working mainly in the fields of ancient and medieval philosophy, and the philosophy of religion, his focus was on the ontological argument. (This remained a life-long interest, from his papers on Anselm in 1961, to his most recent work with Lynne Rudder Baker, “The Ontological Argument Simplified”.) Matthews also wrote and taught about philosophy and children,
actions & events/news
authoring three books on the subject: Philosophy and the Young Child (1980), Dialogues with Children (1984), and The Philosophy of Childhood (1994). As well as his prolific output of books, articles and essays, Matthews was a dedicated teacher, and, as described on the University of Massachusetts philosophy home page: “a gentle presence in the department [who] made it a better place”. He is survived by his wife Mary, two daughters and one son, and seven grandchildren.
DAVID ORTON, activist and deep green philosopher, died on 12 May 2011, at his home in Watervale, Nova Scotia. Orton
was born in Portsmouth in 1934,
fighting”. He is survived by his
where he apprenticed as a shipwright before winning a place at Durham University. He moved to Canada in 1957, attended Concordia, and went on to receive his MA from the New School for Social Research. Throughout his life, Orton campaigned with the Deep Ecology movement, and developed a theory of “Left Biocentrism”. The philosophical account he offered was one that emphasised the profound interdependence of organisms within eco-systems, and combined this “deep ecology” with arguments against consumerism, capitalism and industrialisation. Shortly before he died, Orton posted thanks on his blog to those who had encouraged his philosophical work, and wrote “we all eventually return to the Earth. Goodbye and keep
wife, Helga, and their daughter, Karen; by his son and daughter from his previous marriage, Karl and Johanna; by his brother Michael; and by his grandchild, Alex.
David Orton
ALAIN-PHILIPPE SEGONDS died on 2 May at the age of 68. As the Director of the Société d’Edition Les Belles Lettres, he published and translated a vast range of works of classical and Hellenist scholarship. Among others, he produced innovative new editions of the work of a number of Neoplatonic philosophers, from Porphyry, and Iamblichus to Marinus and Damascius. But his research interests were not limited to Greek philosophy. As a historian and philosophy of science he also edited and translated Renaissance works of astronomy, including those by Rheticus, Kepler, Tycho Brahe and Giordano Bruno. Segonds was one of the last members of the group of French Platonic and Neoplatonic historians who followed Henri Bergson and Pierre Hadot, and was greatly involved in the renewal of French scholarship in this area. He is survived by his wife, Myriam Fleischmann, and his children, Nicholas and Rachel.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
9
actions & events/mediawatch
mediawatch
Philosophy and philosophers in the mass media
10
B
I
Traditionally, these are questions for philosophy,
a high level of consideration and maybe some
but philosophy is dead.
Kantian reasoning thrown in. It turns out it is
ut almost all of us must sometimes wonder: Why are we here? Where do we come from?
Stephen Hawking, quoted in Telegraph, ùÿ May
thought that monogamous pair-bonding was something one determined for oneself, with
mediated by biology in a very real way. Patricia Churchland, quoted in Chronicle of Higher
R
ussell’s history was biased and idiosyncratic,
Education, ùú June
I suppose that’s what qualifies me too.
Anthony Kenny on his new history of philosophy, Spectator, ü June
I
n recent years, seemingly technical economic questions have crowded out questions of
justice and the common good. I think there is a
B
ut here is the thing: the room was full. Three hundred people craned forward, anxious to
join in the conversation, to engage in the philos-
growing sense … that G.D.P. and market values do not by themselves produce happiness. Michael Sandel, quoted in New York Times, ùü June
ophy, to laugh at the jokes. Sarah Crompton on a talk by Onora O’Neill at the Hay Festival, Telegraph, þ June
H
e told me that no medieval philosopher was worth reading and he was proud to be able
R
ecently, I overheard a fellow Amtraker back off a conversation on politics.”You know, it’s
because I’m a libertarian,” he said, sounding like a vegetarian politely declining offal. Stephen Metcalf, Slate, úø June
to say that he had not read one word of Thomas Aquinas. A N Wilson on A J Ayer, New Statesman, ā June
I
f it is our concern to find moral monsters, to
R
hesus monkeys appear to understand what René Descartes meant when he made the
famous statement: “I think, therefore I am.” Daily Mail, þ July
find war criminals, to find butchers, then we
than Gadafi … I am talking about killing and who
A
gets killed. The numbers count.
Hegel I should be writing.
Ted Honderich, Counterpunch, ùø June
Slavoj Žižek, Guardian, ùý July
have in Blair and Bush two stronger candidates
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
lot of what I write is blah, blah, bullshit, a diversion from the 700-page book on
actions & events/mediawatch
ptions • subscriptions • subscriptions • subscriptions • subs
tpm the philosophers’ magazine WAYS WAYSTO TOORDER ORDER ONLINE AT WWW.TPMAGORA.COM
ONLINE AT WWW.TPMAGORA.COM INComplete NORTH ONLY 1. the AMERICA order form using the appropriate $ prices IN NORTH AMERICA ONLY
1. Complete theto: order form using the appropriate $ prices 2. Send orders 2. Send orders to: The Philosophers’ Magazine The Philosophers Magazine, c/o The Philosophy Documentation Center c/o The POPhilosophy Box 7147 Documentation Center, PO Box 7147 Charlottesville, VA 22906-7147 Charlottesville, VA 22906-7147 USA USA Or phone 1-800-444-2419, or fax (434) 220 3301 Or phone 1-800-444-2419, or fax (434) 220 3301
11
IN OF OF THETHE WORLD IN THE THEUK UKAND ANDREST REST WORLD
1. Complete the order form using the appropriate £ prices for 1. Complete where youthe liveorder form using the appropriate £ prices for where you live to: 2. Send orders 2. Send orders tpm – Theto:Philosophers’ Magazine The Philosophers Unit 8, The Magazine, Old Silk Mill PO Box 464,Street Brook Berkhamsted, Tring Herts HP4 2UR Hertfordshire UnitedHP23 Kingdom 5EF, UK Or phone phone (01442) 879097, fax01442 (01442) 872279 Or 01442 820580, ororfax 827912 All prices include postage and packing All prices include postage and packing Please allow allow up up to to 28 days for for delivery Please 28 days delivery
Order form
Details may be sent on a piece of paper or photocopy.
Please startmy mysubscription subscriptiontotoTPM. TPM. Please start II enclose encloseaacheque/PO cheque/POfor for__________ __________ made payable made payable to to Acumen Publishing Ltd, or debit my credit card The Philosophy Press, or debit my credit card Visa Mastercard Switch Discover ❑ Visa ❑ Mastercard ❑ Switch ❑ Discover Card number: _______________________________________ Card number: _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ Expiry date: ____/____ Signature: _____________________ Expiry date: _ _ / _ _ Signature ____________________ Issue no. (Switch only): _______________________________ Issue No (Switch only): ___________________________ 3-digit card security number: __________________________ 3-digit card security number: ______________________ Name: __________________________________________ Name: _____________________________________________ Address: ___________________________________________ Address: _________________________________________ ___________________________________________________ T _________________________________________________ M
P
___________________________________________________ _________________________________________________ Post/Zip code: Post/Zip Code: ___________ ____________Country: Country: _________________ _______________
PRICE LIST SINGLE COPY UK SUBSCRIPTION 1 YR UK
£5.99 £19.99
SINGLE COPY US SUBSCRIPTION 1YR US
$9.99 $34.99
SUBSCRIPTION 1 YR EUROPE SUBSCRIPTION 1 YR ROW
£23.99 £27.99
INSTITUTION SUB UK INSTITUTION SUB EUROPE INSTITUTION SUB ROW
£59.99 £63.99 £67.99
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
actions & events/threads
Ophelia Benson
threads The new college try
12
T
he fuss over A C Grayling’s New
resources by the bankers and financiers they
College of the Humanities (see page 6)
educated, are not best served by a bunch of
gave a few people a joyous opportunity
prima donnas jumping ship and creaming off the
for Working-Class Hero posturing.
bright and loaded.”
The drama had its risible aspects, given that no
A year earlier, Grayling had reviewed
one can really have thought Grayling fit the part
Eagleton’s book On Evil in the New Humanist,
of Top Profiteering Elitist Enemy, and that some
not very favourably. Eagleton reviewed Grayling’s
of the working-class heroes are quite comfortably
planned new college with a good deal of …
prosperous themselves.
energy. “The intersection of class and liberal
Terry Eagleton, for instance, is Excellence in
secularism present in Grayling’s college should
English Distinguished Visitor in the Department
not be taken lightly,” he wrote. “The exclusion of
of English at the University of Notre Dame,
religious voices (and certain political voices) goes
where the undergraduate tuition is $41,417.
hand in hand with the exclusion of the persons
It was droll to see him ask at the Guardian’s
who utter them, persons who happen to come
Comment is Free (guardian.co.uk/commentis-
from the marginalized communities that make up
free), “why should anyone be surprised at the
the majority of the world’s population, and who
prospect of academics signing on for a cushy job
will not be justly represented in this institution.
at 25% more than the average university salary,
We can reasonably expect that Britain’s largest
with shares in the enterprise to boot?”
minority group, South Asians who are predom-
The Excellence in English Distinguished
inantly Muslim, to be conspicuously absent at
Visitor went on, “What would prevent most of
Grayling’s college, doubly excluded on the basis
us from doing so is the nausea which wells to
of ideology and social class. Is this double exclu-
the throat at the thought of this disgustingly
sion coincidental? I don’t think so.”
elitist outfit. British universities, plundered of
A more disinterested reviewer (especially one fêted for Excellence in English) might have paused to realise that his prediction of what we
Ophelia Benson is editor of butterfliesandwheels.com and co-author of Why Truth Matters (Continuum, úøøþ)
can “expect” will happen is not the same as what has in fact happened, and that it is a little unfair to moralise about this expected “double exclusion”
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Billlion cc
Terry Eagleton in Manchester, 2008
as if it were a known fact as opposed to a rather
simply has to set up a new show outside of all
snide guess.
that silliness.”
Eagleton however was suavity itself compared
Kat Gupta at mixosaurus (mixosaurus.co.uk)
to Ian Burzynski at State of Formation (stateof-
liked some of the plans. “The things I do find
formation.org). “I would like to propose that the
interesting are the focus on critical thinking and
coincidence between this privatized (read: classist)
scientific literacy, and the way these degrees
model of university and the hegemonic and exclu-
are aimed at those who don’t want to go into
sionary ‘humanism’ of Grayling and friends is not
academia. Critical thinking and scientific literacy
merely incidental,” Burzynski elegantly observed.
are important (although teaching critical thinking
“What the New College of the Humanities
to people who are paying twice the going rate for
amounts to is little more than the shameless use
a UoL degree could be … interesting).
of wealth and privilege to insulate a dominant
“I’m also intrigued by the focus of a degree
ideology from critique. Secured in the comfortable
that is aimed at passionate, engaged students but
bubble of a homogeneous faculty and student base,
isn’t an elaborate pyramid scheme and doesn’t
comprised of a wealthy and (it can be assumed)
just flail about going ‘um, transferable skills! yes!
predominantly white, secular, European popula-
those are useful!’. I didn’t apply to study English
tion, a particular worldview and reading of history
because I wanted to develop excellent commu-
can be propagated without contest by those who
nication and time management skills – I did it
are marginalized by it. This is precisely the intent
because I loved words and language and wanted
of Grayling in establishing this new ideological
to know how they worked.”
platform; the exclusion is built into it by design.”
William Cullerne Bown at Research Blogs
Back on planet Earth, others managed a sober
(exquisitelife.researchresearch.com) had mixed
awareness that the issue was a small college for
feelings. “On the one hand,” he wrote, “it’s easy
teaching humanities students, as opposed to the
(and very British) to knock people who try some-
opening of a major new front in the class war.
thing new. But I like new ideas and I admire the
The classicist Mary Beard at A Don’s Life (times-
enterprise. What chutzpah to start your own
online.typepad.com/dons_life) wrote, “I have to
university!” He also hinted that the reaction
confess to some sympathy with this: if there is to
had been slightly over the top. “More, I think a
be a sustained assault on the humanities, then
little of the spice of private sector competition
maybe someone has to get off their ass and take
is a useful ingredient in overwhelmingly public
the teaching into their own hands; and if there
soups such as higher education or the NHS. And
are to be more and more central demands from
to worry about the NCH is to succumb to a tiny
central government (many of them tick-box, but
distraction while the whole of our university
still hugely time-consuming), then maybe one
system goes through gigantic convulsions.”
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
actions & events/threads
AC Grayling signing books at 2010 Global Atheist Convention
13
actions & events/closures 14
Whenever departments do face threats, people rightly demand to know why. It is instructive to look at the different types of reason given by management, in answering campaigns against closure, to understand why a department has finally been forced to disband or not.
Anatomy of a closure NINA POWER INVESTIGATES DEPARTMENTS UNDER THREAT
t’s been an uneven and often trying time
I
losses or department closures, or both. Keele,
for UK philosophy departments in the past
Liverpool, Greenwich, London Metropolitan,
couple of years, although significant battles
King’s, and Middlesex have faced one sort of
have been fought and won. Philosophy
threat or another. But a significant pattern is
departments seem to be seen as easy targets by
emerging: of the departments saved, none have
management, not least because philosophy tends
been at post-92 institutions, that is, former poly-
to be a small subject with a few dedicated staff.
technics and colleges that were given university
Perhaps management also fall into the misguided
status in the Further and Higher Education Act
and money-driven trap of thinking that philos-
1992. While it’s true that Middlesex’s Centre
ophy is a “useless” subject – despite the fact that
for Research in Modern European Philosophy,
philosophy graduates have a much better chance
housed in a post-92 institution, was moved to
of being employed after their degree than many
Kingston, the undergraduate department there is
other arts and humanities graduates.
still set to close in a year’s time, with minimal staff
There have been threats to a significant number
teaching out the programme. Other institutions,
of institutions in recent months, whether it be staff
such as Roehampton, have suspended single honours recruitment, while Royal Holloway, by threatening to “discontinue” its classics depart-
Nina Power is senior lecturer in philosophy at Roehampton University
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
ment, plans to move philosophy staff to a different programme.
management at post-92s may be more interested in, for example, developing overseas campuses, as
the forthcoming loss of the block grant to arts
Middlesex have done, or in reframing what they
and humanities subjects, but the way in which
think a university should provide – large courses,
different institutions are handling government
for example, or STEM subjects that won’t lose
cuts varies across the board. In a recent piece
government funding in future. It is certainly the
for the Times Higher Education, John Morgan
case that where institutions have academics sitting
suggests that “Post-1992 universities are being
on senates, advising those who run the universi-
more heavily affected by the government’s deci-
ties, departments are less likely to close. Other
sion to withdraw the teaching grant from all
reasons are sometimes given for an attempted
but science, technology, engineering and math-
philosophy closure. These include low recruit-
ematics (STEM) subjects, and some fear the
ment, although this is rarely true in the case of
creation of a new category of purely vocational
philosophy, which remains an extremely popular
institutions for disadvantaged students.”
choice at undergraduate level. Sometimes medi-
While fierce campaigns have been launched
ocre research performance is mentioned – this
to save philosophy departments, petitions
was one of the reasons cited by Liverpool manage-
created, buildings occupied by students, massive
ment, for example. Some express the fear that,
publicity drives pushed on Facebook and so on,
come the massive rise in tuition fees, students will
the rate of the success of such campaigns reveals
no longer want to take philosophy, and thus a pre-
that of the departments still slated to close, all of
emptive strategy of closure is allegedly required.
them are post-92 institutions. As Jonathan Wolf
Or, as the staff at Middlesex were told, it’s not
put it the Guardian when troubles at Middlesex
that the department wasn’t making a profit, it’s
were announced: “Philosophy is often under
that they weren’t making enough of a profit, and
threat, particularly in the new universities …
by cutting philosophy they could develop more
the chilling thing is that there doesn’t seem to be
lucrative areas of university provision, despite the
anything specially problematic about Middlesex
fact that philosophy was academically and popu-
philosophy, and the reasoning that has led to its
larly their top-rated department.
announced closure could be applied very widely throughout the universities.”
What we mean by a “university” though is an ongoing struggle – can we still pretend to univer-
Whenever departments do face threats,
sality when only a few subjects are represented
people rightly demand to know why. It is instruc-
and only a few subject areas remain? As one of the
tive to look at the different types of reason given
students involved in the (successful) campaign
by management, in answering campaigns against
to save Liverpool put it: “How can it even be a
closure, to understand why a department has
university without a philosophy department?”
finally been forced to disband or not. Following
Fights to save philosophy have followed a
a strong campaign against closure, older institu-
similar course, regardless of their outcome: initial
tions may be more likely to fear negative publicity
shock on the part of staff and their colleagues, who
and worry about their reputation, whereas
have often been fighting to preserve what minimal >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
actions & events/closures
Cuts to philosophy departments can look like part of a pre-emptive attempt to plan for
15
only being taught at institutions that have a low
on the part of the students who quickly organise
proportion of working-class and ethnic minority
meetings, Facebook groups, petitions and some-
students. (On the topic of London Metropolitan,
times occupations to defend their lecturers and
the institution has more black and ethnic minority
their subject; perhaps a piece or two in the press
students than does the whole of the combined
or on a high-profile philosophy blog, such as Brian
twenty universities who belong to the Russell
Leiter’s “Leiter Reports”. Sometimes then, under
Group, according to the minutes of a meeting of
pressure, management will back down. At other
its board of governors). While philosophy prides
times they wait, ride out the storm, and then
itself on being universal, open to anyone prepared
quietly close departments anyway.
to take time over its arguments, and of general
But what are the implications for the future
relevance, if the patterns we see happening now
of the subject in the UK if philosophy is taught
continue, and it disappears from post-92 institu-
at only a handful of institutions, and barely at all
tions, we run the practical risk of it being open to
at newer universities? John Morgan in the same
only a small portion of the population.
Times Higher article points out, for example, that
It is necessary to learn from the campaigns to
“London Metropolitan University, which has the
save philosophy at these different institutions, to
highest proportion of working-class students in
see where and when battles were won or lost, and
the country, is to scrap subjects such as history,
why. Perhaps what is most important is a sense of
philosophy, performing arts and Caribbean
solidarity between different departments, large
studies”. The immediate knock-on effect is
or small, Russell Group or new university, with an
clear: philosophy and other serious humanities
understanding that what unites them is greater
subjects such as history and classics could end up
than what separates them, and that increasing the quality teaching of philosophy across a variety of different institutions can only serve to benefit the
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
User:Justinc
discipline as a whole.
London Metropolitan University; Libeskind building in foreground
cc
actions & events/closures 16
security they might have for many years; outrage
actions & events/word of mouse
Luciano Floridi
word of mouse
Just cyberwar theory
17
C
yberwar is the continuation of
we shouldn’t be too optimistic about the non-
conflict by digital means. It is a new
violent nature of cyberwar. The more we rely on
phenomenon, which has caught
ICT (information and communication technolo-
us by surprise. With hindsight, we
gies) the more lethal cyber attacks will become.
should have known better, for several reasons. Take the nature of our society first. When
it was described as industrial, conflicts had
Soon, crippling an enemy’s communication and information infrastructure will be like zapping its pacemaker rather than hacking its mobile.
mechanised features: engines, from battleships
Consider next the nature of our environ-
to tanks to aeroplanes, were weapons, and the
ment. We have been talking about cyberspace
coherent outcome was the emphasis on petrol
for decades. We could have easily imagined,
and nuclear power. There was an eerie analogy
even without reference to science fiction, that
between assembly lines and warfare trenches.
this would become the new frontier for human
Conventional warfare was kinetic warfare, we
conflicts. We have been fighting each other on
just didn’t know it, because the non-kinetic kind
land, at sea, in the air and in space. Predictably, the
was not yet available. The Cold War and the
infosphere – as I prefer to call it, given the constant
emergence of asymmetric conflicts were part
erosion of the divide between online and offline –
of a post-industrial transformation. Today, in a
was never going to be an exception. Information
culture in which the word “engine” is more likely
is the fifth element and the military now speaks
to be preceded by the word “search”, advanced
of cyberwarfare as “the fifth domain of warfare”.
information societies are as likely to fight with
Finally, think of the origin of the Internet. It
bytes as they are with bullets, with computers
was the military outcome of the arms race and of
as well as guns, not least because digital systems
nuclear proliferation. We were distracted by the
tend to be in charge of analogue weapons. I am
development of the Web and its scientific origins >>>
not referring to the use of intelligence, espionage, or cryptography, but to cyber attacks of the kind witnessed in Estonia (2007) or in Iran (Stuxnet worm, 2010), or to the extensive use of drones in Afghanistan. From robots in physical environments to software agents in cyberspace,
Luciano Floridi (philosophyofinformation.net) holds the research chair in philosophy of information at the University of Hertfordshire and is president of the International Association for Computing and Philosophy
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
actions & events/word of mouse 18
and forgot DARPA (Defense Advanced Research
considered in terms of last resort? And within the
Projects Agency). History has merely caught up
jus in bello, what level of proportionality should
with us.
be attributed to a cyber attack? Or, how do you
The previous sketch should help one under-
surrender to a cyber enemy?
stand why information warfare is causing radical
Equally developed, in this case since Greek
transformations in our ways of thinking about
times, is our understanding of military virtue
military, political, and ethical issues. Are we going
ethics. How can virtue ethics be applied to
to see a new arms race, given the very high rate
phenomena that are actually reshaping the condi-
at which cyber weapons “decay”? After all, you
tions of the possibility of virtue ethics itself?
Societies are as likely to fight with bytes as bullets
Bear in mind that any virtue ethics presupposes a philosophical anthropology (Aristotelian, Christian, Confucian, Nietzschean and so forth), and information warfare is only part of the information revolution, which is also affecting our self-understanding as informational organisms.
can use a piece of malware only once, for a patch
Take for example the classic virtue of courage: in
will then become available, and only within, and
what sense can a tele-pilot be courageous when
against, a specific technology that will soon be
manoeuvring a drone? Indeed, will courage still
out of date. If cyber disarmament is ever going
rank so high among the virtues when the capacity
to be an option, how do you decommission cyber
to evaluate and manage information and act upon
weapons? Will the Pony Express make a patri-
it wisely and promptly will seem to be a much
otic come back in 2060 as the last line of defence
more important trait of one’s character?
against an enemy that could destroy anything
Similar questions seem to invite new theo-
digital and online? Some questions make one
rising, not merely the application of old ideas.
smile, but others are increasingly problematic.
Perhaps, instead of updating our old theories
Let me highlight two sets of them that should be
with more and more service packs, we might
of interest to philosophers.
want to consider upgrading them by developing
The body of knowledge and discussion behind just war theory is detailed and extensive. It is the
a new macroethics. Information warfare calls for an information ethics.
result of centuries of refinements since Roman times. The methodological question we face today is whether information warfare is merely one more area of application, or whether it represents a disruptive novelty as well, which will require new developments of the theory itself. For example, within the jus ad bellum, which kind of authority possesses the legitimacy to wage cyberwar? And how should a cyber attack be
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Cyberwar training course
The silence of the lambdas
19
KIT FINE TAKES JAMES GARVEY INTO THE DEEP WATERS OF SERIOUS METAPHYSICS
f you want to furrow the brow of a philoso-
I
you, but I hear nothing but the silence of the
pher, you might try saying just four words:
lambdas.
“the philosophy of mathematics”. If that
What’s the relationship of a part to a whole?
doesn’t do it, I suggest “possible world
How should we think of possible objects? Is a
semantics”, “multimodal logics”, “mereology”,
thing the same as its matter? How can thinkers
“arbitrary objects” and “vagueness”. It’s the deep
and speakers mean just the same thing? What
stuff lurking beneath the ground floor of logic
does it mean to exist not just in space, but in
and metaphysics, and it’s where Kit Fine lives.
time? In what way do numbers exist? What are
For the past thirty years he’s brought origi-
the limits of abstraction? These are just some
nality to ancient puzzles at the very heart of our
of the questions that Fine addresses, and his
conception of objects, thought and language. His
answers quite often depend on alarmingly tech-
university website is right to say that his ground-
nical logical manoeuvring. Scanning the titles of
breaking article “‘Vagueness, Truth and Logic’ is
his books and papers, even reading one or two
widely thought to have profoundly altered the
articles before reaching for a gin miniature I keep >>>
course of a debate that has been going on among philosophers for thousands of years”. When he agrees to an interview, I suspect that I’m about
James Garvey is editor of tpm
to take one for the team. Logic might speak to
4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/interview
“Mathematical objects are not exactly of our own making, but we actually have to do something to get them. There’s something out there which we prod, but there’s the prodding that’s also required. Numbers are not exactly out there or in us, but somehow in between.”
tpm
thoughts/interview
at my desk in case of emergency, I’m not sure
know what would have happened. Maybe I would
that I see a way in. But when I ask him how he
have become a chef.”
explains what he does to those unfamiliar with,
We press on with the question of mathemat-
say, the philosophy of mathematics, he shows me
ical reality. Are the objects of mathematics – such
around entirely agreeably, and the clouds break
things as numbers and sets – created or discov-
quickly.
ered? Fine explains that his view is somehow in
“In the case of mathematics you can just ask people to consider the question of what kind of
20
reality mathematical reality is. It doesn’t seem to
“Are numbers out there waiting to be discovered?”
the paradoxical middle of these two traditional possibilities. “A natural thought is that things exist in different ways. When it comes to mountains we’re inclined to think that they’re out there waiting to be discovered. When it comes to fictional objects, something like Sherlock Holmes or Hamlet, we tend to think of them as created by authors and not just out there, waiting to be
be part of the physical universe. We don’t seem
discovered. Those views might be incorrect, but
to be talking about our own thoughts. So are we
they’re views that we’re very inclined to have.
talking about a third realm? If so, how are we
“But when it comes to the objects of math-
in a position to do that? Most people can get a
ematics, it’s perhaps not so clear at least in terms
grip on that question. They might be baffled by it,
of that dichotomy where they should lie. Are
perhaps think there’s nothing to say, but at least
they out there waiting to be discovered and if so,
they can see that there is a problem.”
where and how discovered, or do we somehow
The problem is one that Fine has pursued in
create them? I think there are strong indications
some detail, and he has been at it for a while.
pointing in either direction. So it’s a genuine
He first read philosophy in his high school
puzzle.”
library, devouring Bertrand Russell’s A History
There are, then, two standard views – a
of Western Philosophy and his Introduction to
Platonic one, which holds that numbers exist
Mathematical Philosophy. Russell’s work on
independently of our world and our thoughts,
mathematics changed his life.
and a constructivist one, which says that we
“I had doubts,” he says, “doubts about the
somehow create numbers by an act of mind. I
definitions that were being given in calculus,
ask him to explain the attraction of what strikes
without being able to articulate what those doubts
me as the oddest of the two. Why would anyone
were. In Russell I found an articulation of what
think that numbers exist in some third reality?
was worrying me, and how those doubts might
“The extreme version of the Platonic view was
be resolved. I was about sixteen when I looked
held by Gödel. He thought there was something
at those books.” He pauses, thinking of how his
akin to sense perception, by which we can just
life might have been had some now-forgotten
grasp these objects. We can have some sense of
librarian stocked the shelves differently. “I don’t
what he has in mind when we just try to intuit
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/interview 21
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/interview 22
the number series. That’s something we do in our
seem to have a kind of freedom with numbers
imagination, where the numbers appear before
too. Fine explains, “One remarkable piece of
us like an endless series. There is a possibility
evidence from the history of mathematics in
that by consulting this picture we can read off
favour of this view has to do with the extension
facts about the numbers. For example, for every
of the number system. As Kronecker said, ‘God
number there’s a unique successor, there’s no last
made the integers; all else is the work of man.’
number, and so on. That would be an example of
“It does look as if there’s something like inven-
an extreme Platonism. There is this third dimen-
tion or construction going on when we extend
sion, this realm of reality, and we have something
the number series. Initially we don’t envisage
akin to sense perception by which we might
that there are negative numbers, for example,
apprehend it.” There is something to the idea. What numbers are and what we do with them is not entirely up to us. We’re not fully in charge, as we are with other creations, like fictional characters. Fine explains that, if we think we have something like sense perception when it comes to numbers, we might say that, just as the external world is somehow forced upon us – that when we open our eyes we have no choice but to take what we see before us as existing – mathematical facts are just forced on us too. As he puts it, “Someone who opens his eyes to the natural number series can’t fail to recognise various facts about numbers.” Just as I see the attraction of mathematical Platonism, Fine fleshes out the opposing view, and that gradually looks reasonable too. “According to the constructivist view, we actually construct these objects. They aren’t already there. It’s through the various constructions that we make that we discover what the mathematical facts are. So in some sense the facts are of our own making. Perhaps somewhat in the same way that fictional facts, facts about Sherlock Holmes say, are Conan Doyle’s making.” So even granting the Platonist’s point about the apparent reality of numbers, what’s attractive about constructivism is that mathematicians
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
author imagining a character. It’s more like intel-
imaginary numbers. If we need them there’s
lectually bumping into something, where the
some sense in which we make them up – we just
bumping and the something result in a new grip
suppose that they’re there. Just as for purposes
on mathematical objects. But he suggests that
of a story you might imagine that there’s a super-
the objects, once we have them, in a sense have
hero, mathematicians invent super numbers that
always been there. I ask him how he makes sense
seem capable of doing what would otherwise be
of the idea.
impossible. That does look like construction.” Fine’s own position, though, is somehow in
“The right picture isn’t one in which we just create the objects the way you might create a
between Platonism and constructivism, or
“Someone who opens his eyes to numbers can’t fail to recognise various facts”
anyway different from both. He says that the view is Kantian. Recall that, for Kant, we do not passively experience the world; we’re not just mirrors of nature. Instead, the mind is active, has a role in creating the things
thoughts/interview
or rational numbers or irrational numbers or
we experience. It does something to whatever is
statue, bring into existence something that didn’t
given to us in sensation – it categorises that some-
exist before. What you’re doing when you postu-
thing into a world of objects that causally interact
late is extending the domain of quantification,
in space and time. Fine thinks something similar
you’re extending the objects about which you’re
is going on with mathematical objects.
talking. It’s not that you’re bringing them into
“Dummett at one point gives expression to
existence. You’re targeting the domain of quanti-
such a view – he talks about prodding objects into
fication, a domain of discourse which hadn’t been
existence. Mathematical objects are not exactly
previously targeted. These objects are themselves
of our own making, but we actually have to do
mathematical objects that don’t exist in time, in
something to get them. There’s something out
fact, if they exist they necessarily exist. So it’s not
there which we prod, but there’s the prodding
that they didn’t previously exist, it’s just that you
that’s also required. So that’s a picture according
now managed to target a new domain of eternal,
to which numbers are not exactly out there or in
necessary existence.”
us, but somehow in between, but as Dummett
When I stare at him blankly, he’s very accom-
himself points out it’s very hard to know what
modating. “Here’s an analogy. Suppose I’m
such a view would amount to, in the end. I think
talking about English people. I could then start
you could see my view as a species of this kind
talking about British people, so I’m thereby
of view.”
talking about a wider domain of people. I don’t
Fine’s position is called “procedural postu-
bring those new objects into existence; I just
lationism”. When we postulate, when we do a
now have a more comprehensive domain of
certain sort of reflection on mathematical objects,
discourse. Postulation does something similar.
our acts in a sense bring those objects into exist-
It expands the domain of discourse, but not by
ence. But what’s going on is not quite like an
lifting a restriction that was previously in play, as >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
23
thoughts/interview 24
in the previous case, but by doing something else.
they’re talked about, isn’t up to us. That’s the
That’s the curiosity of the position. Somehow
quasi-paradoxical view that I have.”
you’re able to talk more comprehensively about
Fine has interesting ideas about not just
what there is, even though previously there was
mathematical objects, but objects as such. Again
no restriction on what you were talking about.
we’re in deep waters, considering objects in
We do something here. What we talk about is
abstraction. Fine has done a lot of thinking about
up to us. And even though what we talk about
the parts of objects, and what it takes for parts
is up to us, the existence of these objects, once
to form wholes. He argues that in many cases, a
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
would be to misunderstand something very
that a thing is not the same as its matter, because
important about sentences, namely that they’re
a thing is matter structured in a certain way. So
words structured in a certain way. Just as it is
the matter and the thing can be in the very same
important to try to understand the structure of
place and the very same time. We start with parts
language, so it’s important to try to understand
and wholes.
the structure of the material world. I follow
“Logical and philosophical investigations
Aristotle in thinking that there’s this other thing,
into parts and wholes have been dominated by
he called it the form, which is involved in under-
a certain tradition that goes under the name
standing what these things are.”
25
‘mereology’. According to mereology,
“Mathematical objects don’t exist in time, in fact, if they sum of its parts. The only difference between the whole and the parts is exist they necessarily exist” that the whole is one while the parts are there’s just one way of getting a whole
from parts, and the whole is a mere
many. I hold the view according to which there
Fine has also turned his attention to perhaps
are many different ways in which parts can form
the shiftiest objects of all: possibilia or possible
wholes, and many of those ways are not mere
objects. When a road sign warns of possible
sums. I think it’s unfortunate for philosophy that
traffic ahead, is it referring to anything? How
philosophers focus so much on mereology as
could it, if the traffic is merely possible? Actual
traditionally conceived.”
traffic might be inconvenient, but possible traffic
But how can a thing be more than the sum
shouldn’t make much difference. Fine identifies
of its parts? Where does the more come from?
four positions one might take with regard to any
Fine explains, “If you take a tower of blocks
subject matter and applies them to the case of
that a child might make, that’s composed of the
possibilia.
blocks, but it’s not a mere sum of the blocks. The
First of all, he explains, “you might be what’s
blocks have to be in a certain order, one has to
called an eliminativist and just deny the intelli-
be on top of the other. I’m inclined to think of
gibility of talking about possible objects. Just as
that tower as the blocks in a certain arrange-
you might think that there’s no intelligible way
ment. So when you think of it in that way it’s not
to talk of phlogiston, because there’s nothing
a mere sum of the blocks. If you want to actu-
to be talking about, so when people are talking
ally understand mereological structure as it’s
about possible objects there’s just the illusion that
presented to us, it’s very rare that we’re going to
there’s something to be talking about.”
be talking about mere sums. We’re going to be
But Fine rejects this view, because we really
talking about objects structured in a certain way
do seem to talk intelligibly about possible things.
to constitute a whole.
He talks about possible electrons, and asks how
“Take a sentence. You might think that a sentence is just a sequence of words, but that
many possible electrons there might have been, given what we know about the way the universe >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/interview
thing is not just the sum of its parts. He also says
tpm
thoughts/interview 26
“Even though what we talk about is up to us, the existence of these objects, once they’re talked about, isn’t up to us” works. “It seems to be perfectly intelligible. On
“This is the view I myself have,” he begins. “If I
the face of it, we’re talking about possible elec-
say, for example, ‘There is a countable infinity of
trons. I would always prefer to take at face value
possible electrons’, I would say that all that really
what appears to be intelligible. I’m inclined to
comes to is that there’s a possibility that there
think that almost always when a philosopher says
is a countable infinity of electrons. So it’s not as
that something is unintelligible, they’re wrong.”
though I’m speaking about the possible objects,
A second view about possible things, also
I’m just saying there are certain possibilities, the
rejected by Fine, takes it that talk of possible
possibility of the actual objects being such and
things is intelligible but non-factual, that is
such in number.
to say, it makes sense but states no facts. Fine
“Whenever you have a construction where
explains, “Perhaps the most famous view of this
you talk about some possible object X, and say
sort is the expressivist view in ethics. According
what’s possible for it, we can understand it in
to this view when we make moral claims we’re
terms of there being a certain possibility, the
expressing certain normative or evaluative atti-
possibly that there is an X. So we never find
tudes to things. When I say abortion is wrong,
ourselves talking about these possible objects.
I’m expressing my disapproval of abortion. And
Instead we’re always talking about possibilities.
so it might be thought that in an analogous way
That’s the hope, that we can understand one kind
this talk of possibility is not really in the busi-
of case in terms of the other.”
ness of stating the facts. In one version of this
The final view, which gets a lot more atten-
view, we engage in some kind of pretence, like
tion than the others, is the idea that our talk of
we’re playing a game, performing a play. I’ll make
possible things is factual but not reducible to talk
many claims, but I’m not actually asserting, I’m
about actual things. Metaphysics goes large, in
not stating facts. Similarly you might think when
other words. Possible things are things, just like
we talk about possibilities we’re playing a kind of
actual things are things. “Maybe someone like
game, we’re pretending there are these things.
Lewis holds this view, or Williamson. So we just
I think it’s implausible in itself, but also I think
accept that there are possibilia, and when we talk
there are detailed objections. We don’t seem to
about them this is factual discourse, but there’s
be engaging in any kind of pretence when we talk
no reduction. There just are these things.
in this way.”
“We shouldn’t try to understand talk of
According to the third view, there are facts
possible objects in terms of actual objects. There
about possible things, but such facts reduce to
just are all these objects, and it’s not as though the
nothing more than facts about actual things.
actual ones are somehow ontologically privileged,
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
notion of borderline case which is relevant to the
terms of them. Without going into detailed argu-
phenomenon of vagueness. We have to achieve
ments, I’d be happier if there were some sort of
an understanding of vagueness in some other
reduction. If you’ve got a robust sense of reality,
way.
there’s something slightly metaphysically offen-
“An analogy I sometimes make is in terms of
sive about this view. It’s hard to believe that in
some stepping stones being uneven. There’s one,
reality there are these possible objects.”
there’s another, and then there’s a drop. Then it
We come finally to Fine’s influential views on
goes back up. This is a global feature of the step-
vagueness and the so-called “sorites” paradox.
ping stones. It’s a feature of the stepping stones as
The name comes from the Greek word for heap,
a whole, not a single stepping stone. Single step-
“soros”. Eubulides, an ancient Greek philoso-
ping stones are not uneven in this sense. I have a
pher with a thing for paradoxes, asked, roughly,
similar view of vagueness. It’s a global phenom-
when do you go from a few grains of wheat to a
enon that has to do with the general application
heap? One grain doesn’t count, neither do two or
of the predicate, not its application in a partic-
three or four, but keep adding grains and, even-
ular case. That goes against the view of almost
tually, you’d say that you do have a heap. The
every other philosopher who has talked about the
trouble is that for a range of borderline cases, we
matter.
don’t know what to do with the predicate “is a
“Take a sorites series and start off with a
heap”. There are a number of instances in which
completely bald man and go to one who’s very
“This is a heap” is neither true nor false, but how
hairy through gradual increments. The predi-
could that be? When I ask Fine about his views
cate bald is indeterminate in its application
on vagueness, he thinks for a very long minute,
to that series of cases. It’s natural to think that
noticeably brightening as he does so, and finally
that’s because there’s some particular case that’s
tells me he’s found an entirely new way to think
borderline or has some sort of borderline status.
about vague predicates.
The new thought is that that’s a mistake, that the
“I can briefly outline my new view, which is very radical.” He goes on, half smiling, “If I’m right almost everyone else is wrong.” I lean in.
indeterminacy cannot be localised in that way. We cannot point our finger at any one case. “It means everyone else has been wrong. It
“Predicates can be vague. Take a predi-
leads to a very different conception of vagueness,
cate like bald. It’s vague. Perhaps one way
the logic of vagueness, how you handle various
of expressing that is that the predicate is not
problems. It leads to a completely new logic. It’s
completely determined in its application. Many
something I’ve been thinking about.”
people have thought that the phenomenon of
Sometimes seismic shifts way down in the
vagueness is to be understood though borderline
depths of our grip on logic and metaphysics do
cases: what it is for a predicate to be vague is for
more than cause ripples up here on the philo-
there to be borderline cases. My view is that this
sophical surface. If Fine’s right, his fresh line of
approach to the problem of vagueness is funda-
thought could be just the start of new waves in
mentally misguided. There is no intelligible
our understanding of logic, objects, and language.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/interview
and we’re to understand talk of the possible in
27
thoughts/sci-phi
Mathew Iredale
sci-phi
Altruism in artificial life 28
T
he origin and persistence of altruism
r > c/b, where c is the reproductive cost to the
is one of the enduring puzzles in
altruist, b is the reproductive benefit to the recip-
biology and the social sciences. Why
ient and r is their genetic relatedness. In other
should an individual carry out a behav-
words, altruism is favoured the more closely
iour that benefits another individual at a cost,
related you are to the recipient, and if the benefit
sometimes a significant cost, to itself? It seems
to the recipient is likely to be high and the cost to
to go completely against the Darwinian idea of
you is likely to be low.
“survival of the fittest”. Populations of altruists
One classic example of kin selection in action
are vulnerable to invasion by cheaters who do not
is an ant colony, which is generally composed of
cooperate, but gain the benefit from those who
one queen, who spends all her time laying eggs,
do cooperate, so we would not expect altruistic
and hundreds to thousands of workers who do all
behaviours to be maintained in a population. Put
the other jobs, from rearing the eggs to foraging
formally, altruism should not be evolutionarily
for food. These workers are sterile, and so unable
stable.
to reproduce. They altruistically give up this
This apparent paradox appeared to be
opportunity to spend their time helping to rear
resolved by William Hamilton’s “inclusive fitness
the offspring of the queen. As the queen is usually
theory”, at least, as far as altruism between rela-
their mother, they are rearing brothers and sisters,
tives is concerned. More commonly known as kin
and so kin selection explains their altruism.
selection, it makes specific the idea that individ-
Similar life cycles occur in other insects, such as
uals are not only able to transmit copies of their
termites, and many wasps, bees, and aphids.
genes directly, through their own reproduction,
But there are problems with Hamilton’s
but also indirectly by favouring the reproduction
theory. One prominent critic is the biologist
of kin, such as siblings or cousins. By helping a
Edward Wilson, who points out that ant and
close relative reproduce, an individual still passes
wasp colonies are not the exemplars of altruism
on its own genes to the next generation, albeit
they are taken to be. Social ants and wasps are
indirectly.
often founded by unrelated queens; workers
Hamilton expressed his theory in the form of
do not show preference for their own mothers
an equation, Hamilton’s rule, which states that
in multiple-queen colonies, and only occasion-
altruism is favoured by natural selection when
ally for their sisters; and colonies remain well
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
foraging tasks, such as pushing seed-like objects
their workers are only very distantly related or
across the floor to a destination – can evolve over
not at all.
multiple generations. Each robot has an arti-
Another problem for Hamilton’s theory
ficial genome, or genetic code, initially made
is that although advocates point to the many
up of a random string of zeros and ones, which
studies that appear to provide qualitative support
encodes the neural network that produces the
for kin selection theory, there is a clear lack of
robot’s behaviour. Those robots not able to push
studies providing quantitative support. The
the seeds to the correct location are selected
problems facing such a study are considerable,
out and cannot pass on their code, while robots
as any research involving live animals would
that perform comparatively better see their code
need to span hundreds of generations before
reproduced, mutated and recombined with
being able to reach any conclusions, and would
that of other robots into the next generation – a
involve far too many variables. But researchers
minimal model of natural selection.
Dario Floreano, Laurent Keller and Markus
For their latest experiment, groups of eight
Waibel from the Laboratory of Intelligent
micro-robots and eight food items were placed
Systems in Lausanne, Switzerland, have found
in a foraging arena with one white wall and three
an ingenious way around these problems and
black walls. The team chose a collective foraging
have, for the first time, provided quantitative
task to investigate the evolution of altruism,
support for Hamilton’s rule. Their solution,
because foraging efficiency is a key factor for
recently published in the open-access journal,
many biological social groups such as ant or
PloS Biology, is to use tiny robots smaller than a
bee colonies. The performance of the robots
matchbox to test Hamilton’s rule.
was proportional to the number of food items
Previous research by Floreano and Keller has
successfully transported to the white wall, and
shown that micro-robots – when doing simple
the robots were given the option of allocating the fitness rewards of successfully transported items to themselves (selfish behaviour) or sharing them equally with all the other group members (altruistic behaviour). The researchers conducted 500 generations of selection in a population consisting of 200 groups of eight robots. The probability of robots to transmit their genetic code from one generation to the next was proportional to how well they performed the task. The selected codes were randomly assorted and subjected to crossovers and mutations to create the 1,600 new genomes (200 groups of eight robots) forming the next
swarm robots
generation. This experimental setup allowed the >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/sci-phi
organised and stable even in extreme cases when
29
thoughts/sci-phi 30
researchers to independently manipulate the
The team found that when the c/b value was
relatedness between robots within a group and
very small, the level of altruism was very high in
the cost to benefit ratios of helping. To quan-
the populations where within-group relatedness
titatively test Hamilton’s rule for the evolution
was positive, but that it was close to zero when
of altruism, they investigated how the level of
robots were unrelated. In experiments with other
altruism (defined as the proportion of food items
c/b values, the level of altruism was also very
shared with other group members) changed over
low when the relatedness was close to zero, but
generations in populations with five different c/b
rapidly increased when the relatedness became
ratios and five relatedness values, making twenty-
higher than a given value. In all cases, the transi-
Natural selection also applies to synthetic organisms
tion occurred when r became greater than c/b, as predicted by Hamilton’s rule. The authors conclude that Hamilton’s rule is vindicated: kin selection theory always accurately predicts the minimum relatedness necessary for altruism to evolve. At the same time, they have
five different set ups in all. For each of these set
demonstrated that kin selection does not require
ups, the selection experiments were conducted in
specific genes devoted to altruism or sophisti-
twenty independently evolving populations.
cated cognitive abilities, as the neuronal network
Because of the impossibility of conducting
of their robots was composed of only thirty-three
hundreds of generations of selection with real
neurons. But what is perhaps most fascinating is
robots, the team used simulations that precisely
that they have shown that a fundamental prin-
model the dynamical and physical properties of
ciple of natural selection also applies to synthetic
the robots, having previously determined that
organisms when these have heritable properties.
evolved genomes can be successfully imple-
The question naturally arises: what other areas of
mented in real robots that display similar
evolution may be testable using synthetic organ-
behaviour to that observed in the simulations.
isms, where the insurmountable difficulties that
Because the robot’s genes were initially set to
would face quantitative studies involving living
random values, their behaviour was completely
organisms need not apply?
arbitrary in the first generation, with some robots just rocking backwards and forwards while others randomly moved around the arena or simply remained stationary. However, their perform-
Suggested reading “A Quantitative Test of Hamilton’s Rule for the
ance rapidly increased over the 500 generations
Evolution of Altruism” by Markus Waibel, Dario
of selection and most importantly the level of
Floreano and Laurent Keller, PLoS Biology (May
altruism also rapidly changed over generations
2011).
with the final stable level of altruism varying
“The evolution of eusociality” by Martin Nowak,
greatly depending on the within-group related-
Corina Tarnita and Edward O. Wilson, Nature 466
ness and c/b ratio.
(26 Aug 2010).
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/the tpm essay
It is evident that every moment of our life we depend on having some kind of brain in working order. But it does not follow from this that we are a brain in working order.
My brain made me do it, your honour
31
RAYMOND TALLIS ON NEURODETERMINISM AND NEUROLAW It is almost impossible to pick up a newspaper
only arise our pleasures, joys, laughter and jests,
without encountering a new story about what
as well as our sorrows, pains, grief and tears”.
brain scientists, armed with the latest technology,
This is a remarkably precise anticipation of what
have discovered about us. Functional Magnetic
Francis Crick wrote a few years ago: “You, your
Resonance Imaging (fMRI) scans are as ubiqui-
joys and sorrows, your memories and ambi-
tous in the broadsheets and red tops as scantily
tions, your sense of personal identity and free
clad women in the tabloids. The word is out
will, are in fact no more than the behaviour of
that, if you want to understand the true nature
a vast assembly of nerve cells and their associ-
and origin of our experiences, emotions, memo-
ated molecules”. In short, the apparent relevance
ries, motives, thoughts, and ethical, aesthetic,
of recent advances in neuroscience to under-
economic, political and religious behaviour, you
standing ourselves rests on an ancient idea: “You
need to look at brain activity.
are your brain”.
>>>
The source of this excitement is billed as being due to advances in neuroscience, in particular those that have been made possible by new non-invasive ways of looking at the living, awake human brain. In fact it owes more to assumptions than empirical discoveries. The most important goes back 2,500 years to Hippocrates who
Raymond Tallis was professor of geriatric medicine at Manchester University and a consultant physician. He was elected to the Academy of Medical Sciences for his research in neuroscience. He now writes poetry, fiction and books on philosophy, most recently, Aping Mankind: Neuromania, Darwinitis and the Misrepresentation of Humanity (Acumen, úøùù).
asserted that “it is from the brain and the brain
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/the tpm essay 32
In what follows, I want to
self, is dependent on brain func-
examine this assumption and its
tion. That much is beyond doubt.
relevance to our thinking about
What is in question is whether
free will and criminal liability.
we may conclude from this that
I will first set out the case for
our consciousness is identical
“neurodeterminism” – the notion
with brain activity, and that brain
that neuroscience has provided
science will consequently tell us
independent support for doubting
what we are. I shall return to this,
that we truly are agents who can be held responsible for our
Hippocrates by Peter Paul Rubens
but I want first to look at some widely discussed studies that
actions, since we are mere sites through which
seem to bear directly on the notion that, when it
the laws of nature, in particular the laws of biolog-
comes to action, our brains are calling the shots.
ical nature, are expressed. I will then critique the
The first is a famous set of experiments,
claim that neuroscience has anything specific to
carried out by the neurophysiologist Benjamin
say on this matter, first by arguing against the
Libet in the 1980s and repeated and refined
fundamental assumption that we are our brains
many times since, which seem to show that our
and then by subjecting to sceptical examina-
brain makes decisions to act before our conscious
tion a couple of widely discussed examples of
mind is aware of them, so they are not really our
research that is supposed to support that assump-
decisions at all. In a typical experiment, Libet’s
tion. Finally, I will glance at the application of
subjects are instructed to make a simple move-
neurodeterminism to the law and to the plea of
ment – to bend their right wrist or the fingers
diminished responsibility.
of their right hand – in their own time. Using
The case for neurodeterminism rests on the
electro-encephalography,
the
experimenter
belief that we are identical with activity in parts
records a particular activity in the brain that
of our brains. This belief seems to have a lot
indicates a readiness to move. This so-called
going for it, and the most compelling evidence
“readiness potential” (RP) is seen in the part
comes from quite homely sources. For example,
of the cerebral cortex most closely associated
decapitation results in a steep decline in IQ; a
with voluntary movement. Libet also asked his
bang on the head makes you behave oddly or lose
subjects to recall the position of a spot revolving
consciousness. More sophisticated observations
round a clock face in order to determine the
have uncovered close correlations between brain
time when they were first aware of their urge or
dysfunction and mind dysfunction – holes in the
intention to make a movement. To his surprise,
brain, for example, are associated with holes in
he found that the RP occurred a consistent third
consciousness and mental capacity. Over the last
of a second before the time at which the subjects
century or so, there have been ever more detailed
reported being aware of a decision to move.
demonstrations of the way every aspect of our
Libet concluded from this that the brain (not the
consciousness, from the most primitive tingle
subject or the person) had “decided” to initiate
to the most exquisitely constructed sense of
or at least to prepare to initiate the act before
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
button. Remarkably, the relevant regions (in the
a decision having been made. Put more simply,
part of the cerebral cortex associated with volun-
the cerebral causes of our actions seem to be in
tary movement) lit up a full 5 seconds before the
advance of our conscious awareness of deciding
individual was aware of having made a choice.
to perform them.
Moreover, there were other areas in the frontal
These findings are open to a range of inter-
cortex (traditionally ascribed executive func-
pretations, as we shall see, but they cannot be
tion) that were active no less than seven seconds
dismissed as mere artefacts of the method of
before awareness of the decision. If the delay in
recording. Nor can the gap between the elec-
the response of the fMRI scanner detecting the
trical signal of the initiation of action, the RP, and the awareness of the intention to perform the action be explained away as the interval between forming an intention and being sufficiently
Decapitation results in a steep decline in IQ
reflectively aware of the intention to allocate it to a particular time. This has been demonstrated
activity was accounted for, the interval increased
rather dramatically by more recent work using
to ten seconds. Such a long delay could not be
fMRI.
due to the subject mistiming the intention to
Chung Siong Soon and colleagues presented
move – a possible explanation for Libet’s original
a succession of letters on a screen. Subjects were
findings, as it is somewhat tricky to time one’s
asked to press a left or a right button at a moment
own decisions. The authors concluded that there
of their own choosing and to note the letter being
is a network of high level control areas “that
displayed when they felt that they were making
begins to prepare an upcoming decision long
a decision to press the button. The letter was a
before it enters awareness”. It looks like we don’t
time marker. The regions that lit up in the brain
know what we are doing until we have found that
predicted the subject’s choice of left or right
we have done it. Libet’s original interpreta-
cc
tion of his own experiments was
Bundesarchiv, Bild 183-1987-1209-027 / CC-BY-SA
that they demonstrated that we do not have free will: the brain “decides” to move, the brain “initiates” movement. As he put it in a more recent paper: “If the ‘act now’ process is initiated unconsciously, then the conscious free will is not doing it”. We do, however, have “free won’t”: we can inhibit movements that are Eye tracker
initiated by the brain. Instead >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/the tpm essay
there was any reportable subjective awareness of
33
thoughts/the tpm essay 34
fMRI
of initiating voluntary processes, we “select and
Conscious Will that the only connection between
control them”; either by permitting the move-
willing and acting is that both come from the
ment that arises out of an unconsciously initiated
same unconscious source.
process or “by vetoing progress to actual motor
I shall presently subject Libet’s and Soon’s
activation”. This has been expressed as our ability
experiments to a critical examination, but I want
to “rubber stamp” decisions that have already
first to examine their background assumption. It
been made by neural networks. It is, however,
is, put simply, that we are identical with observ-
not very clear why the decisions should require
able neural activity, so that what the EEG or
rubber stamping. In the personless world of
fMRI reveals tells us what we are. If observations
neuroscience, it makes no more sense for us to
of neural activity fail to demonstrate free will, our
“rubber stamp” the decisions of our brain than
free will is put into question: what neuroscience
for a falling pebble to endorse the gravitational
cannot find isn’t real.
field. Even so, it remains a highly popular view.
It is of course hardly surprising that, if we are
On the basis of this and other observations
identical with physical events in a material object
of the unconscious influences on our behaviour,
such as the brain, then we should turn out not
Daniel Wegner has argued in The Illusion of
to have the freedom we ascribe to ourselves. All
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
expect of something is that it should seem like
physical causes have physical causes in turn.
itself. The usual defence against this objection
This causal genealogy will ultimately go back to
is that neural activity in the visual cortex and the
the Big Bang, which clearly ante-dates anything
experience of the visible world are two aspects
which we can claim to have initiated. If we are
of the same thing, rather as (to use John Searle’s
brain activity, we are merely sites through which
example) molecules of H2O (which are not slip-
the material universe unfolds in accordance with
pery and shiny) are the same as water (which
the unbreakable laws of physical nature. In short,
is). Neither this defence – nor the comparable
neurodeterminism is merely a variant of deter-
idea that neural activity and conscious experi-
minism and requires no empirical proof. The critique of neurodeterminism must begin therefore with questioning the presupposition that consciousness (and the self, and the putative
What neuroscience cannot find isn’t real
agent) is identical with neural activity. The belief that neuroscience has provided
ences are the same thing seen at different levels
evidence for this identity is based on an elemen-
or under different descriptions – will work, for
tary error. It is evident that every moment of our
the simple reason that the notion of “different
life we depend on having some kind of brain in
aspects” (or “levels” or “descriptions”) presup-
working order. But it does not follow from this
poses an observer from which they are observed.
that we are a brain in working order. Likewise
The difference between neural activity and expe-
the ever closer correlations observed between
riences cannot be due to observers experiencing
neural activity and aspects of consciousness do
one or other of them in differing ways.
not demonstrate identity between them. To put
For those who are not knocked down by this
it another way, the fact that neural activity is a
knock-down argument, there is another that
necessary condition of consciousness does not
undermines the identity theory at an equally
demonstrate that it is a sufficient condition, that
fundamental level. Supposing my seeing an
neural activity is by itself sufficient to construct
object in front of me, such as a glass, was due
us so that the neurological properties of our
to the effect of light originating from this glass
brains define what we are.
producing activity in my visual cortex. This
As it turns out, the more closely we look at
forward causal link between the glass and my
the supposed identity between consciousness
brain is not sufficient for me to be aware of
and neural activity, the less convincing it seems;
the glass. The events in the cortex have then
indeed, it is self-contradictory. The most obvious
to be about the glass, which is explicitly quite
problem is that neural activity looks nothing
separate from them. This “aboutness” or “inten-
like the elements of consciousness. There is,
tionality” would have to reach from the visual
for example, nothing about the contents of the
cortex in the darkness of my cranium, back up
visual cortex that is in the least like the appear-
the causal chain, to those events in and around
ance of the visible world, but the least you might
the glass that brought about the nerve impulses >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/the tpm essay
physical events have physical causes, and those
35
thoughts/the tpm essay 36
and construct the presence of the
point of origin of events, that it has
glass out of them. The identity
selfhood, and that it is responsible
theory, in other words, requires of
for some events rather than others?
nerve impulses that they should
Those who assert that selfhood and
do something that no other kinds
agency are illusions must explain
of physical event (including most
how these illusions might arise in
nerve impulses) do – namely reach
bits of the material world.
back up causal chains in order to
There are many other very
be about their proximate causes.
serious problems with the assump-
The neural theory of conscious-
tion that we are identical with brain
ness translates being aware of
activity. The unity of conscious-
something into an utterly anoma-
ness, whereby I am both aware
lous property, ascribed to certain
of a myriad of items at any given
nerve impulses, of reaching out
moment, but still experience them
to something that is both spatially
as connected in a single field of
and temporally separate from
co-consciousness over time, has no
them. This reaching out is not, of
possible material basis. The unity
course, reverse causation. It is something even
of self over time is similarly resistant to mate-
more difficult to accommodate in the materialist
rialist explanation. In both cases, the standard
philosophy upon which neurodeterminism rests:
explanation of the convergence of neural path-
a mode of connectedness that is, as it were, at
ways does not explain how merging occurs
right angles to the causal net.
without mushing; how the conscious self is not
This is not the end of the problems faced
a place of unholy confusion. This is exacerbated
by the neural theory of consciousness. By over-
by the fact that we have an explicit aware-
looking intentionality (which tears open the fabric
ness of things that are past as being past, and
of the causally closed material world) it reduces
of possible future events as being located in a
the mind to a material, causal way station where
future. Material objects such as brains cannot
there is no basis for the difference between inputs
house or generate tensed time. As Einstein said,
and outputs, no point at which events “arrive” or
“we believing physicists know that past, present
are “received” (as perceptions); it offers nothing
and future, are simply illusions albeit stubborn
to locate the “brainified” person in the centre of
ones”. We have no grounds for supposing that
egocentric space; and even if it were to cope with
tenses could be generated in certain privileged
this by denying the self as a point of arrival and
enclaves of the physical world such as the stuff
origin, it would be left entirely unable to account
inside our skulls.
for the undeniable fact that we do have a sense
All of these difficulties arise from a yet more
of self, and agency, and of being the centre of
profound problem: the fact that the brain is a
our worlds. Why should part of the causal net
piece of matter whose fundamental properties
become possessed of the notion that it is the
are not different from those of the rest of the
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/the tpm essay
The unity of consciousness has no possible material basis material world. For the “lowdown� on matter, we
eyes of physics for which it is a piece of matter,
turn to physics, and this gives an account of what
it is none of those things. One could go further
there is that is entirely lacking appearance and
and state that it has no phenomenal appearance.
viewpoint. For several hundred years, physicists
And this is true of all pieces of matter: they have
have argued that the truest portrait of matter
no appearances in themselves. How could they,
is mathematical, and this by-passes the quali-
given that they are viewed through the lens of
ties that we experience. That table over there is
mathematics and not from a particular view-
brown, sturdy, beautiful, handy and so on. In the
point? In the absence of a subjective viewpoint, >>>
cc AaronY, and brain image from J. Talairach & P. Tournoux, Co-planar Stereotactic Atlas of the Human Brain (New York: Thieme, 1988).
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
37
thoughts/the tpm essay 38
items do not have appearances. A rock has a
of the wrist, a mere movement. That move-
certain appearance when looked at from the
ment, however, was only a minute part of a long
back, from the front, from above, from below,
sequence of movements adding up to a large-
from the outside looking in or the inside looking
scale action which could be described as “taking
out. But it has no appearance viewed from itself
part in Dr Libet’s experiment”. This large-scale
as it were, because this would require that it
action began at least as far back as getting up in
should have all of these appearances (which are
the morning to visit Dr Libet’s laboratory (after,
incompatible with one another) at once. As we
perhaps, setting the alarm to make sure one was
treat items purely as pieces of matter, there is a
not late); involved consenting to take part in an
disappearance of appearance; and this must be
experiment whose nature and purpose and safety
just as true of “biomatter” such as brains as of
was fully understood; and required (among many
rocks and clouds. It seems hardly possible, there-
other things) listening to and understanding and
fore, that the brain, lacking appearance in itself,
agreeing to the instructions that were received
can have the capacity to make other things (that
– and then deciding to flex the wrist. In other
have no intrinsic appearance) appear. But this is
words, the immediate prior intention, the
what the identity theory requires it to do as the
psychological event timed by Libet, was not the
supposed seat of consciousness.
whole story of the action, only a tiny part of it. It
That there is nothing inherent in neural
was preceded by many others that were minutes,
activity capable of making things appear is revealed indirectly by the fact that there is no fundamental difference between neural activity in parts of the brain that are, and parts that are not, supposed to be associated with consciousness. The hunt for distinctive “neural correlates of consciousnesses” has proved baffling and disappointing. This should be enough to make us less impressed by the experiments of Libet, Soon, and others: the relationship between neural activity and consciousness, and hence conscious behaviour, is not at all clear. But let us look more closely at what led them to conclude that, as the neural events supposedly preparatory to action occur before the subject is aware of making the decision to act, it is the brain, rather than the subject that is the agent. Recall that the action the subjects were asked to perform was extremely simple: a flexing
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Brain image from J. Talairach & P. Tournoux, Co-planar Stereotactic Atlas of the Human Brain (New York: Thieme, 1988).
hours, perhaps days before the action. The real
it shows us what is suspect about determinism
story is not just the flexing of the wrist but one
more broadly construed. If you want to make
of a sustained and complex resolve being main-
voluntary actions seem involuntary the first thing
tained over a very long time. This includes many
to do is to strip away their context – the self from
large items of behaviour – getting on and off
which they originate, the nexus of meanings that
buses, looking for the laboratory, cancelling or
is the world to which they are addressed – and
declining other commitments so as to be free to
then effectively break them down into their phys-
attend the lab, and so on – that have many thou-
ical elements. This gets you well on the way to
sands of motor components.
eliminating the difference between a twitch and
Once this is appreciated, then the temporal
a deliberate action, and to make an action seem
relation between the last step, the wrist flexing,
as if it could be explained by a burst of nerve
and the Readiness Potential seen in the lab
impulses, embedded in a no-person neural
becomes unimportant. The decision to partici-
reality that has nothing to do with a first-person
pate in the experiment, which alone gave the
world, where behaviour is not atomic but inter-
wrist flexion its meaning, began not millisec-
connected. The true locus of our free will is a
onds, seconds, or minutes, but hours before the
field of intention, rooted in the self and its world,
wrist was flexed. Perhaps weeks, when the person
which extends far beyond a few moments in a
decided to become a subject in the experiment.
laboratory. No wonder, in the lab setting, actions
The flexing of the wrist is just the last compo-
look simply like events that happen to the actor.
nent of this action called “taking part in Dr
They are seen to be “effects”.
Libet’s experiment” which would itself be part of
If, incidentally, we really were the uncon-
a greater intentional whole, such as “wanting to
scious, helpless playthings of our brains, it would
please Dr Libet” or “wanting to help those clever
be difficult to know how we could deliberately set
scientists understand the brain, as it might one
out to demonstrate this – to become conscious of
day help doctors to treat my child’s brain injury
our unconsciousness and voluntarily devise exper-
more effectively”. This would be very difficult
iments that demonstrate our inability to initiate
to find in a study which recorded small slices of
voluntary actions. The source of our selfhood and
neural activity.
our freedom cannot of course be located in the
Libet’s experiment illustrates how the (neuro)
no-person world of the brain. No, the theatre in
determinist case against freedom is not only
which we lead, rather than merely organically
based on ropy metaphysical assumptions but
live, is the human world, the boundless field of
is also rooted in a very distorted conception of
shared intelligibility, or the community of minds
what constitutes an action in everyday life, and
in which, courtesy of our brains, we participate.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/the tpm essay
There is nothing inherent in neural activity capable of making things appear
39
thoughts/the tpm essay 40
It is through that outside-of-the-brain that we
voluntary behaviour. Laboratory determinism
are able to express our freedom in numerous
looks a little patchy.
ways, including launching investigations into
The “pick and mix” nature of neuro-
the workings of our own brains. In an entirely
determinism
neurodeterministic world, none of this would be
neuroscience-based pleas of diminished respon-
possible. This is what makes some of the ambi-
sibility. The defendant who says “it was my
tions of so-called neurolaw self-contradictory.
brain what made me do it” is usually referring
We are now better placed to challenge the claim
to the crime with which he is being charged:
that our brains are calling the shots. This idea lies
the action in which he stole money, beat up a
Neurodeterminism is no different from determinism period
is
seen
most
strikingly
in
person who irritated him, or reduced to rubble a pub in which he had been denied a sixteenth pint. He does not offer this explanation as to why he turned up in court, retained counsel and listened to his advice, why the QC defended him, why he offered this plea, or why the judge
behind the increasing expectation that we ought
should accept it. If he subscribed to neurode-
to look at brain activity to determine whether or
terminism, it would be global, and he would
not defendants are actually responsible for the
have to assume that everyone else in court was
crimes they may have committed: it is, in short,
equally helpless.
the founding assumption of neurolaw.
What is more, given that his brain is a mate-
We should be suspicious of the plea, “my
rial object wired into the material world – so
brain made me do it”, because it leaves unre-
that events in the brain are the effects of events
solved who (or more precisely what) is making
outside of the brain – his plea would amount to
the plea, is passing the blame on to the brain –
“the Big Bang made me do it”. The notion of
another bit of the brain, presumably. But there
being coerced by a piece of the causal net that
are further grounds for suspicion that apply
happened to target him would also be problem-
also to those experiments that seem to demon-
atic: why should a particular brain single him out?
strate that we are unfree. The research that
Only if he was his brain. In which case, “my brain
Daniel Wegner summarises in The Illusion of
made me do it” would amount to “I made me
the Conscious Will reveals situations in which
do it”, which is hardly an argument for mitiga-
we are less free than we think we are. But, if
tion. What this illustrates is how the very act of
neurodeterminism were true, there would be no
blaming one’s brain actually presupposes a posi-
“more” or “less” free. Likewise, the participants
tion outside of the neurodeterministic frame
in Libet’s and Soon’s experiments presumably
of reference in which the role of the brain is
signed consent forms that made it clear that they
visible. This position is, of course, the commu-
knew exactly what they were doing and why. So
nity of minds that lies outside the individual brain
there seem to be little arias of set-piece deter-
housing a self, acting in a world that cannot be
minism against a background of what seems like
reduced to neural activity.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
siasm of the aficionados of the practitioners of other neuro-prefixed disciplines such as
thoughts/the tpm essay
The limited role of neuroscience in the law should incidentally temper the enthu-
neuroaesthetics, neuroeconomics, neuropolitics, neurosociology, neurotheology and neuroethics who wish to see the traditional humanities replaced by studies of the brain. While it is clear that normal brain function is Once this is appreciated, neuroscience loses
a necessary condition for everyday consciousness
its metaphysical traction and just becomes one
and ordinary behaviour, it does not follow from
piece of evidence among others. It is perfectly
this that it is a sufficient condition of conscious-
obvious that, if I have a frontal lobe tumour, I
ness and an explanation of behaviour, even less
may be less inclined to control my impulses. But
that consciousness is identical with neural activity.
such obvious cases (acknowledged long before
Experiments that seem to demonstrate that we
the present era of neuromania) are obvious
are in the grip of our brains overlook the context
because they arise out of particular, unusual
in which the experiments take place and the
circumstances, not out of our general relation-
conditions that make it possible for scientists to
ships to our brains. The extension of the plea of
set up the experiments and, as we have seen, for
mitigation to include people whose scans show an
subjects to take part in them. Even those who are
imbalance between one part of the brain (such
committed to neurodeterminism seem to apply it
as the frontal cortex) and another (such as the
in a pick and mix way in real life situations, when
amygdaloid body) – and the prediction that justice
they are judging whether some actions are less free
will eventually be better served by neuroscience
than others. They should not allow a “more or less”.
than by the conventional forensic disciplines – is
Given that the brain is a material object, neuro-
an empirical claim that needs to be tested and
determinism is no different from determinism
not one that is rooted in what we think we know
period, placing us in the network of causation that
of our general relationship to our brains. What is
unfolds from the Big Bang to the Big Crunch. It is
more, it will have to be tested against standards
not only incompatible with free will but also with
that have been established long before neuro-
the apparent discovery that our free will is an illu-
sciences started hankering after a curly wig. The
sion. The fundamental error is that of believing
more general claim (by writers such as Semir
that an empirical inquiry – a set of actions, presum-
Zeki) that with the advance of neuroscience the
ably freely undertaken – could demonstrate
untidy, ill-informed decision-making processes in
whether or not we are determined to behave as
the law courts will be replaced by a “biological
we do. Contemporary neurodeterminism works
justice” that can connect actions with the neural
within, rather than demonstrates the truth of, an
activity that drove them and the wider biological
assumption about human nature that goes back
bases of that activity, is clearly self-contradictory.
2,500 years. And it is an incorrect one.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
41
thoughts/illness
Trying to figure out the contours of the concept of disorder is worthwhile because whether something counts as a disorder frequently makes a huge difference to us in everyday life. Suppose I drink a lot – if I think alcoholism is a disease I may visit a doctor, if I consider it a moral failing I may blame myself for my weakness of will.
For good or ill
43
RACHEL COOPER CONSIDERS JUDGEMENTS OF NORMALITY AND DISORDER
W
here is the line between the
Trying to figure out the contours of the concept
normal and the pathological?
of disorder is worthwhile because whether some-
How can we tell whether a
thing counts as a disorder frequently makes a
condition is a disorder (which
huge difference to us in everyday life. Think of
I take to be an umbrella term that encompasses
various controversial cases – alcoholism, mild
all diseases, illnesses, injuries etc.) or something
depression, psychopathy, ADHD and sex addic-
else? Cases where it’s unclear whether a condi-
tion. We want to know whether these conditions
tion is a disorder or a moral failing include drug
are disorders as this makes a difference to how
addiction, attention deficit hyperactivity disorder
we treat others and think of ourselves. Suppose
(ADHD), and personality disorders. Cases where
I drink a lot – if I think alcoholism is a disease I
it’s hard to distinguish disorders from normal
may visit a doctor, if I consider it a moral failing >>>
states include middle-aged male impotence, mild depression, and forgetfulness in old age. Sometimes a condition may not actually be a bad thing and so just be a difference rather than a disorder. Some groups argue that conditions such as Asperger’s syndrome, asexuality and deafness are not harmful and so should be seen as differ-
Rachel Cooper is senior lecturer in philosophy at Lancaster University. She is author of Psychiatry and Philosophy of Science (Acumen, úøøÿ) and Classifying Madness: A Philosophical Examination of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (Springer, úøøý).
ences rather than as disorders.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/illness 44
Determining whether a condition is a disorder might involve values I may blame myself for my weakness of will. Or
might be partially genetic, and yet we wouldn’t
as another example, suppose my child struggles
want to pathologise such states. Even if the physi-
to pay attention in class. If ADHD is a disorder
cian can tell us that the state is likely to cause
then he may qualify for special help. If it’s not,
an early death or infertility, we may still resist
then he’ll just have to try harder.
the conclusion that it is a disorder. A predis-
Physicians are generally considered the
position to great heroism might be unusual, it
authorities when it comes to determining whether
might be genetic, it might tend to lead to early
a condition is a disorder or not. Whenever there’s
death, and yet we might consider it of such value
a debate in the media, an authority in a white coat
that it would be considered a good thing rather
will soon be asked to tell lay people what’s what.
than a disorder (suppose, it was discovered that
Thus we will be told that ADHD is a disorder
Ghandi, Mandela and Martin Luther King all
because some brain differences can be detected,
had the heroism trait). This example shows that
for example, or that women who have little
determining whether a condition is a disorder is
interest in sex suffer from a disorder because
intimately connected with questions about the
they can be treated with drugs. But deter-
good life for human beings, and this is why phil-
mining whether a condition is a disorder is not
osophical, as well as medical input may be of use.
merely a medical matter – there’s work for others
But, as the proof of the pudding is in the eating,
(including philosophers) in figuring this out too.
let’s consider some concrete examples. Here we
The major reason why philosophical thought
will examine two cases that help make it clear
is needed to help determine whether various
how it is that determining whether a condition
conditions should be considered disorders is that
is a disorder might involve values, and can be
any physical difference, no matter what it might
the sort of problem that philosophical thought
be, is plausibly not a disorder unless it is also
can contribute to solving. The first case, homo-
a bad thing. A physician can tell that a state is
sexuality, was controversial in the late 1960s and
statistically unusual – but this on its own is incon-
1970s. The second case, complicated grief, is
clusive. Suppose that 1 per cent of the population
currently being debated.
is found to have unusual brain activity. On its own
In 1973 the American Psychiatric Association
this isn’t enough for us to conclude that they have
voted to remove homosexuality from its classifi-
a disorder. Perhaps the brain activity is associated
cation of mental disorders. In the years leading
with something unusual but good, for example,
up to the vote, the inclusion of homosexuality in
great musical ability. Even if the state is genetic
the manual had become increasingly controver-
and runs in families, we cannot conclude that it
sial, with pressure for removal coming from both
is a disorder. Good things, like musical talent,
gay activist groups and within the profession.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/illness
usually does that contributes to the overall goals of the organism, which are taken to be survival and reproduction. Thus the function of the eyes is to enable us to see, the function of the lungs is to take oxygen into the body, and so on. When we are healthy all our subsystems function normally. Of course, the functioning that we can expect from a subsystem depends on our age and sex. Boorse says that we can consider a subsystem to dysfunction whenever its functioning falls below the level that would be statistically normal for other people of our sex and age. On Boorse’s account it will be hard to deterHysteria chronophotography, from Iconographie photographique de la Salpêtrière (Jean Martin Charcot,1878)
mine whether homosexuality is a disorder. The biological causes of homosexuality are contested. From an evolutionary point of view one might
While gay activists picketed psychiatry meet-
expect that humans are designed to be sexu-
ings, research papers were presented that found
ally attracted to members of the opposite sex.
that homosexuality was more common and that
Sexual attraction facilitates sex, which, so long
homosexuals led lives that were more “normal”
as it’s between opposite sexes, tends to lead to
than previously thought.
offspring – all good from an evolutionary point
Homosexuality is an interesting test case for
of view. This being the case, one might suspect
thinking about the concept of disorder. If one
that homosexuality occurs when some mental
thinks that whether a condition is a disorder
mechanism dysfunctions and leads to someone
depends only on biological facts, it is very hard
who was supposed to be attracted to members
to resist the implication that homosexuality may
of the opposite sex being attracted to their own
well turn out to be a disorder. The best known
sex. Things are not so clear-cut, however. I share
biologically based account of disorder has been
much genetic material with my relatives, so if I
put forward by Christopher Boorse. In his 1975
help raise my siblings, and nieces and nephews,
paper “On the Distinction Between Disease
and there are enough of them, this may be as
and Illness”, Boorse claims that we can think of
good from an evolutionary point of view as having
human beings as being made up of numerous
children myself. For such reasons, only one
subsystems – where subsystems are things like
female in a colony of naked mole rats breeds, and
bodily organs (the heart, kidney and so on), more
the other females help raise the babies. Some
diffuse bodily systems (like the nervous system),
theorists have suggested that homosexuality in
and also mental mechanisms (such as the mental
humans might arise via such “kin-selection mech-
systems that enable us to recognise faces). Each
anisms”. The truth will be hard to determine, but
subsystem has a function, which is whatever it
the key point to note is that if one adopts Boorse’s >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
45
thoughts/illness 46
Courtyard with Lunatics, Francisco de Goya, 1794
account of disorder, whether homosexuality is a
disorder-status of homosexuality have to do with
disorder will depend on the details of biological
whether it is harmful rather than its biological
fact. In so far as it may turn out to be a biological
origins, one should abandon Boorse’s account,
dysfunction, homosexuality may turn out to be
and instead accept that a condition can only be a
a disorder.
disorder if it is harmful. Only on an approach that
During the debates over the disorder-status
sees values as central to determining the bounda-
of homosexuality, however, many thought that
ries of the normal can one say that homosexuality
theorising about the biological basis of homosex-
is not disorder.
uality missed the point. Those who thought that
Suppose a close friend dies. You feel grief; you
homosexuality should be demedicalised thought
lose your appetite, activities that once pleased you
this because they considered homosexuality
no longer seem worthwhile, you think about your
not to be a bad thing. In so far as it is plausible
friend and spend time going to visit their grave.
that the important questions to do with the
If this goes on for a few months, then we may
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/illness
Homosexuality may turn out to be a disorder think it an understandable response to a great
circumstances arise. Suppose, for example, that
loss. But what if it goes on for years and seems
I love my son. This commits me to feeling various
to get no better? What if you become so preoc-
other emotions in different circumstances. If my
cupied with reminiscences of your friend that
son does well, I will be happy. If he is in danger,
you become a poor employee and lose your job?
I will feel worried. And if he dies, I will feel grief.
What if you decide that life is no longer worth
Such reasoning suggests that feeling grief when
living and try to kill yourself? Such a response, we
a loved one dies is conceptually tied to having
may think, appears pathological. But given that
loved them. Seeking to get rid of normal grief
it is plausible that there are normal and patho-
would thus be a mistake, as normal grief is linked
logical forms of grief, where, and how, might the
to positive human emotions such as love.
distinction between normal grief and pathological grief be drawn?
Can we conclude that normal grief is a part of the flourishing human life and thus normal,
One way to address this question is via
while pathological grief is grief that is dispropor-
considering why it would be unwise to medi-
tionate? Unfortunately, matters are not quite so
calise normal grief. In their 2003 report Beyond
clear-cut. Issues become complicated because
Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of
the amount of grief that is perceived to be propor-
Happiness, the President’s Council on Bioethics
tionate to a loss varies from culture to culture. In
asks us to consider the following thought experi-
current European cultures one might expect to
ment. Suppose you die, and looking down from
grieve for a partner for around six months, but in
heaven you observe the behaviour of your loved
other cultures much shorter or longer periods of
ones. You are expecting them to be huddled
mourning are expected. Given that our expecta-
round your grave, drying their tears, but instead
tions are clearly culturally shaped, distinguishing
life for them seems to carry on as normal. None
between normal grief and grief that is too intense
of them seem to be bothered that you’re dead.
or lasts for too long is difficult. We can say that
Would you consider this a good thing? Most
grief is not a disorder so long as it plays a proper
people do not want their family and friends to
part in enabling us to lead flourishing lives, but it
simply move on. The worry is that those who are
is unclear how we might decide how much grief
ungrieved in death were unloved in life.
a flourishing human should feel. At bottom the
We can usefully use Bennett Helm’s account
question depends on decisions about the sorts of
in his book Emotional Reason to get a clearer
individuals we want to be and the sorts of socie-
grip on the links between grief and love. Helm
ties we want to live in – and these are hard issues
argues that for me to feel an emotion at one
indeed. Once again conceptions of the good life
time is conceptually tied with me also feeling
play a key role in determining the boundaries of
various other emotions, should the relevant
disorder.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
47
thoughts/letter from …
letter from …
Malta 48
JOE FRIGGIERI THINKS WHILE THE SUN SETS
M
alta is the smallest state of the
splendour of the Baroque churches and palazzi
European Union, of which it
built by the Knights of the Order of St John, the
became a member in 2004,
impressive fortifications surrounding Valletta
forty
gaining
and the Three Cities on the other side of Grand
its independence from Britain. Occupying
Harbour, the Gozo Citadel, the Caravaggio
122 square miles and supporting a popula-
and Preti masterpieces, are among its main
tion of 420,000, it lies at the very heart of the
attractions.
years
after
Mediterranean, with Sicily to the north and
The Maltese language constitutes one of the
Libya directly south. The former fortress colony,
most important ingredients of our national iden-
heavily hit by Mussolini’s bombers and Hitler’s
tity. All political parties are very strongly aware of
Luftwaffe during the Second World War, now
their responsibility to promote it, since it is the
attracts over a million tourists annually to its
only language with Arabic roots to be adopted as
shores. Roughly half of them come from the UK.
an official medium of communication in the EU.
Malta’s cultural heritage is a result of its long
While “il-Malti” is the national language,
and chequered history. There is no other country
English is recognised as the other official
its size where you can find such a concentration
language together with Maltese, and is widely
of archaeological and artistic treasures. The
used as the main means of communication in
awesome grandeur of the prehistoric temples,
many fields. The language of instruction at the
the indelible marks of Roman and Arab rule, the
university is English, most of the books in the library are in English, as are the films shown in our cinemas and the two locally produced news-
Joe Friggieri is professor of philosophy and head of department at the University of Malta
papers with widest circulation. Together with our temperate climate, the widespread knowledge and use of English is
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
faculties, departments and institutes. Thanks to
many foreign students to our shores. The atmos-
the hard work and dedication of our sixth-form
phere on campus reflects the cosmopolitan feel
teachers, all of whom received their philosoph-
of the rest of the country. Maltese students know
ical education in the department, and most of
at least one other language apart from English
whom are either in possession of or reading for
and Maltese, and this makes it possible for them
a PhD, we have had a steady intake of students,
to establish friendly relations with their foreign
some of whom take philosophy as their main or
counterparts without any difficulty. Social scien-
second area in the BA course, but most of whom
tists familiar with Wittgenstein’s aphorism that
choose it as a subsidiary subject in conjunc-
to understand a language is to share a
We help students see how their beliefs fit together multilingual, multicultural society like Malta. way of life are often led to reflect on the
significance of this claim in the context of a
Like looking through a pair of old binoculars, it takes time for the mind to bring things
tion with their main course outside the faculty
into focus from the past, and even then most
of arts.
images are blurred. There were only six hundred
The number of students who are required
students on campus when I joined the BA
to take a number of philosophy credits as
course in philosophy and modern languages at
part of their course is always on the increase.
the University of Malta forty-five years ago. Now
These include students reading for a degree in
there are over ten thousand, spread over an area
theology, law, political science, European studies
that’s at least four times larger than it was then.
and communications, as well as those following
The number of faculties, institutes and centres
courses in the history of art, theatre studies,
for specialised research has more than doubled.
psychology, the MA course in human rights and
The function of the department of philos-
democracy, and the Edward de Bono Institute
ophy at the university is not restricted to running courses for its own students, but essentially includes giving multiple services to other
for the Design and Development of Thinking. We strongly feel that practically all students can benefit from doing at least some philosophy >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/letter from …
clearly one of the main factors attracting so
49
thoughts/letter from … 50
One course will deal with some of the wonderful stories told by philosophers at the university. Despite the small size of the
systematically, though ultimately it would be up
department, the syllabus covers a wide range
to them to decide which ones to hang on to and
of areas and provides a well-rounded philo-
which to discard.
sophical education. The history of the subject is
“Philosophical anthropology” is the name of
well-covered, and students are exposed to both
the most important study unit offered in the first
Anglo-American and continental traditions in
year of the course. It consists of a discussion of
modern and contemporary philosophy.
the main issues related to perception, language
Asked to comment about his own work,
and action, and introduces students to topics like
Eugenio Montale, one of the six twentieth-
sensory communication, the relation of signs to
century Italians to be awarded the Nobel Prize
the world, speech acts and conversation, the logic
for Literature, once said: “The subject matter of
of practical reasoning and the will, freedom and
my poetry is the human condition considered in
responsibility. This last topic receives fuller treat-
itself: not this or that historical event. This does
ment in the course on ethics, while philosophy
not mean cutting oneself off from what goes on
of mind and metaphysics are dealt with in the
in the world; it means knowing the difference
second and third years.
between what is essential and what is transitory, and refusing to trade off the one for the other.”
On top of these compulsory core subjects, students are also expected to choose from a
What Montale says about his poetry can also
number of optional or elective study units.
describe the role of philosophy as we see it at the
These include political theory, aesthetics, philos-
University of Malta. Like most young adults else-
ophy of religion and the social sciences, medieval
where, those who come to us to study philosophy
Islamic philosophy, philosophy of science and
do so because they are interested in discussing
mathematics, Far Eastern philosophies, as well
those basic questions concerning “the human
as a number of selected texts from the great
condition considered in itself” that form the core
philosophers, ancient, medieval, modern and
of the subject as we know it. So what we do in
contemporary.
the first year of the course is introduce students
Everybody likes a good story, so one course
to such questions and teach them how to think
we intend to introduce in the near future will
clearly about them, how to argue coherently
deal with some of the wonderful stories told
and convincingly, how to distinguish between
by philosophers down the centuries. Plato’s
good and bad arguments by applying some very
cave, Aristotle’s sea-battle, Avicenna’s flying
simple and basic rules. What we’re aiming at is to
man, Descartes’ evil spirit, Wittgenstein’s
help students see how their more or less uncon-
beetle, Quine’s rabbit, Searle’s Chinese box, and
nected beliefs fit together, how to organise them
Putnam’s twin earth will feature prominently in
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
divorced from the conflicts that mark the course
extraordinary thought experiments invented by
of human history.
philosophers in connection with the problem
Though not likely to face a firing squad for
of personal identity – from Locke’s prince and
their political militancy, the present members
pauper fairy tale to Sydney Shoemaker’s brain
of the philosophy department do not live in an
transplantation,
mind-
ivory tower. Refusing to “cut themselves off from
cleaning machine and Derek Parfit’s Star Trek
what goes on in the world” (Montale again), they
fantasy of teletransportation.
are often invited to take part in discussions of a
Bernard
Williams’s
As I write this piece in my room on the second floor of the humanities building, I can see the sky getting darker by the minute, though it still manages to preserve that kind of phosphorescent luminosity the Germans associate with what they call die blau stunde, the blue hour. The weather today was glorious,
theoretical or practical nature on radio and tele-
Eclipse, the faculty cat, sleeps on top of a boxful of students’ essays
following yesterday’s freak summer storm, and
vision, and they also contribute articles to the
the pine-trees outside my window sparkle under
local press on topics of current national and inter-
the reflected glow of the yellow floodlights stuck
national interest. Many of them are also involved
on top of the assembly hall, a building named
in activities of a cultural nature that go beyond
after Sir Temi Zammit, Maltese scientist, archae-
their normal academic and administrative duties
ologist and historian who discovered the source
on campus.
of undulant fever in goats’ milk and showed
In this part of the world, twilights are short
how the transmission of the disease that killed
and night takes over from day in a matter of
hundreds of people could be prevented.
minutes. When I’m alone in my room, after the
Another building, covered at this time of year
students and most of my colleagues have gone
by a thick red carpet of bougainvillea, is dedi-
home, I can hear Plato and Aristotle, Descartes
cated to the heroic figure of Dun Mikiel Xerri,
and Hume, Kant and Hegel, Heidegger and
the best-known professor of philosophy at the
Wittgenstein whispering their secrets from the
university, immortalised in our history books not
books stacked behind my back, as I draw comfort
because of his philosophy but on account of his
and inspiration from the theatre posters hanging
patriotic zeal. Xerri was shot by a French firing
on the wall in front of me.
squad for plotting against the regime during the
Eclipse, the faculty cat, sleeps on top of
very brief spell of French rule, a year after the
a boxful of students’ essays left lying in the
Order of the Knights of St John, who had ruled
corridor, right outside my door. He serves to
the island for two and a half centuries, capitu-
remind members of the department, lecturers
lated to Napoleon in 1798. Xerri’s fate, like that of
and students alike, that when a philosophical
Socrates, shows that what is generally regarded as
problem becomes intractable, it might be best
an “unworldly” discipline has never been entirely
to sleep over it.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/letter from …
these lectures, together with the cluster of quite
51
thoughts/portraits 52
“The contents of a photograph are not facts, nor reality, nor truth. They are a means we have created to extend our way of seeing on a search for truth.”
Philosophers CYNTHIA FREELAND TAKES A LINGERING LOOK AT STEVE PYKE’S PORTRAITS
W
hat does a philosopher look
philosophers through photographs – Bertrand
like? The label calls to mind
Russell (angular head, white hair, pipe), Jean-
a classical bust of a man with
Paul Sartre (wall-eyed, thick lips gripping a
noble brow, beard and blank
cigarette) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (hand-
inward-seeing eyes. His high forehead conveys
some and aristocratic). Women philosophers
deep wisdom, like those super-smart aliens on
too entered our consciousness, from Simone de
the original Star Trek with their big-brained bald
Beauvoir with her elegant chignon to the Afro-
heads. In art history, philosopher portraits range
crowned activist Angela Davis.
from the impish-looking Descartes (possibly)
What do philosophers actually look like?
painted by Frans Hals to Holbein’s Erasmus,
Rather odd, I’m afraid, or if truth be told,
sensitive hands carefully crafting a letter. Or
unappetizing – at least if we are to go on this
there is the moustachioed Nietzsche painted
collection of portraits by Steve Pyke. The book
posthumously by Edward Munch, gazing across
includes an interview with Pyke by Jason Stanley,
a blustery Expressionist landscape. In the twen-
and there the artist explains that, given his own
tieth century we acquired iconic images of
origins among the working classes, he initially approached intellectual heavyweights like A J Ayer feeling intimidated. But now he sees them
Cynthia Freeland is professor of philosophy at the University of Houston. She is the author of Portraits and Persons and But is it Art?, both published by Oxford University Press.
as more human. The pictures suggest that Pyke also finds philosophers strange. Here we find philosophers, warts and all: wild eyebrows, unkempt beards, lank hair, lantern jaws, crossed
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
of philosophers are more specific. The label is
philosophers are rare. Among the few who do
often employed as an honorific, designating
smile, one appears gleeful (Robin Jeshion) and
someone with wisdom and depth. Not everyone
another maniacal (Hartry Field). Pyke seems to
who is a philosophy professor can claim to be a
have wandered into the territory of Théodore
“philosopher” in this sense. To pose as a philoso-
Géricault who depicted people suffering from
pher, an individual must rise to the occasion. What should a philosopher look like? In a
I have argued in my book Portraits and
fascinating but frustrating introduction to the
Persons (Oxford, 2011) that we are drawn to
volume (“The Face of Philosophy: Steve Pyke’s
portraits in part because in human evolution it
Gallery of Minds”), Arthur Danto (who is
was important to recognise individual faces and
himself included) says that all the people shown
track the facial expression of others’ emotions.
here look “fiercely smart”. I beg to differ. A few
We encounter other human beings through their
(you will understand my not naming names)
bodies and prepare responses to actions forecast
look a bit vacant. Judith Thomson looks mischie-
by their faces. But the reasons to look at images
vous, Peter Singer tired, Timothy Williamson
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
“monomanias” in the asylum at Ivry in the 1820s.
thoughts/portraits
eyes, weak chins, bad teeth, weird noses. Smiling
53
>>> Hartry Field
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/portraits
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
54
Harry Frankfurt
meek, and Sydney Morgenbesser sad. Some of
Curtis’s Native Americans, August Sander’s
them (Ernie LePore, Harry Frankfurt) just look
Germans, Diane Arbus’s outcasts and socialites,
like nice guys to have a beer with at the local
Richard Avedon’s denizens of the still-wild West).
pub. Why the “fiercely smart” label, anyway?
The artist in effect compiles a sociological study
Philosophers should be smart, sure; but why
with possibly diverse aims, from Curtis’s glorifi-
“fiercely” so? There are other qualities we might
cation of “noble savages” to Arbus’s penchant for
wish for from our philosophers, such as that they
the freakish.
be judicious, insightful, sceptical, kind, witty or
Pyke too is undoubtedly moulding the
compassionate. (The face of the Dalai Lama
subjects he photographs in some way. The
comes to mind.)
problem is that there is not really anything to
The representation of individuals as members
be seen about philosophers per se. The group
of a type is of course not new with Pyke. There
in question displays no characteristic uniform
are many previous examples both in painting
or accessory attesting to its activities. One might
(Rembrandt’s
Gerhard
as well guess instead “chemists” or “magicians”.
Richter’s 48 Portraits) and photography (Edward
Their outward appearance can seem unkempt.
Night
Watchmen,
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
thoughts/portraits
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
55
Malcolm Budd
Pyke is interested in the fact that these philoso-
from Michael Friedman, who is shown in front
phers form a community, but this suggests that a
of a blackboard covered in glyphs (and, inciden-
group shot might have been more intriguing (if
tally, wearing a zippy tie). We don’t see Brian
harder to arrange). I love the thought of a photo-
Leiter, prominent blogger, before a keyboard,
graph constructed à la The Night Watchmen, in
nor Aristotle scholar Alan Code puzzling over the
which philosophers from a given field – say, ethics
Greek text of Metaphysics Zeta. We don’t see any
– are shown as an investigative team bursting out
other people here working in the settings where
from interior spaces of moral darkness, led into
philosophers do work: at a desk, in a classroom,
the light of certainty by some stalwart individual.
at a convention, or even, in these days of cogni-
Related to the problem of trying to show a
tive science, examining an fMRI. There are no
community by depicting its members in isola-
Peripatetics here, no Cynics walking around with
tion is another problem: the philosophers seen
lanterns seeking an honest man.
here are mostly heads (remember those aliens
Traditionally,
philosopher
portraits
did
from Star Trek). Rarely do they have bodies. Nor
depict tools of the trade: Helleman showed
do they employ any tools of their trade – apart
Descartes with his foot on the works of Aristotle, >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
thoughts/portraits 56
and Ramsay placed Tacitus’s history under
are naked, of course, but their clothes are irrele-
Hume’s plump arm. Often philosopher portraits
vant, since after all they are simply heads, homes
showed more of the thinkers’ bodies in action,
for minds. Scorn for fashion has long been a hall-
conversing, as in the famous juxtaposition of
mark of the profession, ever since its beginning
Plato and Aristotle, hands gesturing impatiently
in barefoot Socrates. The rare exception here
upwards or down, in Raphael’s The Academy of
is Frances Kamm, whose beautifully patterned
Athens. Or think of David’s Socrates, with sturdy
shawl must have compelled the camera’s respect.
leg and strong chest, firmly pointing to the soul’s
Let us infer some things, if we can, from the
higher destiny even as he reaches for the fatal
heads of philosophers shown here. Pyke shoots
cup of hemlock while those around him wail and
with a twin-lens Rolliflex using Tri-X film and
weep. (Now there’s a picture of a community!)
available light. In some cases the result he gets
Removing the body from a portrait erases a lot
is quite beautiful, as in his portrait of Robert
of information about size, posture, and setting, all
Stalnaker, shown in three-quarter view with
of which are used by artists to convey character,
lovely side lighting. His portrait of Malcolm
including status and duties. Ramsay famously
Budd is powerful: Budd confronts us directly,
depicted Hume in an elegant (the king thought
and the bristles of his incipient beard add inter-
too elegant) scarlet uniform while Rousseau, in
esting visual texture. In a surprising number
the companion portrait, wore rustic furs and a
of cases, though, the results are blurry enough
bed-coat.
to have been rejected by a regular studio artist
Clothing is often a clue enabling us to read
(Ludlow, Strawson, Papineau, Longuenesse, and
people’s identity in pictures. Scholars hypothesise
Langton). I cannot tell that this blurriness has any
that when Rembrandt’s Aristotle contemplated
specific emotional or aesthetic effect. Pyke’s New
the bust of Homer, he did so wearing costly robes
York exhibit of the series included original proof
and a jewelled belt (the putative gift from his
sheets, and it would have been very interesting
former student Alexander) to illustrate the choice
to peruse these to examine his choices, including
between the unadorned life and a more magnifi-
the reasons for occasional profile views.
cent one. In photographs too, clothing is crucial,
Pyke’s lens choices (I suspect he uses
as with the impressive headdresses in Curtis’s
Rolleinar close-up attachments) can distort
Native American portraits. Dress is also revela-
facial features in unflattering ways, making
tory in Sander’s oeuvre, from the ill-fitting Sunday
nice-looking people appear to be missing chins
suits on his workers going to town to the slinky
or to have huge noses. In more than a few
black silk of his androgynous secretary. Arbus’s
cases the philosophers look either cross-eyed
famous little girl twins are made more creepy
or wall-eyed (an impolite name for the condi-
by their matched dresses with Peter Pan collars
tion Sartre suffered from, strabismus). There
and white hair bands. And Avedon’s waitresses,
are several cases in which the prints show the
drifters, and carneys wear shabby and even filthy
face of a sitter as bright white against a dark
clothes that speak of their bitter lives. But Pyke’s
background, making it seem to float above the
philosophers have no clothes. It’s not that they
picture plane (Mothersill, Sperber and Williams).
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
drama, inducing a kind of alienation effect.
thoughts/portraits
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
Such faces are frozen like painted masks in Noh These instances contrast with some more fullbodied portraits, as in the wonderfully sculptural image of a reflective Arthur Danto. A few of the portraits in Pyke’s series seem to have wandered in from another photographer’s studio, such as the chiaroscuro silhouettes of Ruth Millikan and Ruth Barcan Marcus, which would fit well in the Peter Ludlow
nineteenth-century Romantic pictorial oeuvre of Julia Margaret Cameron. Perhaps his respect for
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
wise, older women prompted Pyke to associate them with icons of the Victorian period. It has been argued that photography affords a superior form of realism: Kendall Walton alleges that we literally see Abraham Lincoln, for example, in photographs of him. In the interview, Pyke tries to deflect claims about truth, saying, “The contents of a photograph are not facts, nor reality, nor truth. They are a means we have created to extend our way of seeing on a search for truth”. However the book’s presentation screams “Truth”, with its black and white format and spare layout – just one photograph printed Mary Mothersill
full-frame on each two-page spread. And further-
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
more the specimens are exhibited in alphabetical order, “Philosophers from A-Z, Albert to Žižek”. As sociology, Philosophers reveals various things about the profession. The ratio of women to men is about twenty per cent, fairly representative of women’s lamentably low inclusion in the field. More disgraceful is the paucity of nonCaucasians (Anthony Appiah and Jaegwon Kim are the only two). Among the women more are smiling here than men. Is this because women simply did smile more at Pyke, since women in general seek to please in social interactions? The non-smiling women are austere. This renders any >>> Ruth Millikan
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
57
looks toward her father as he talks, but this
flash of an earring, startling in contrast with their
could connote filial respect rather than gender
overall sober mien. The two images of philoso-
hierarchy.
pher relationships, at the back of the volume, are
I have written so far as if the book includes
interesting. (There could have been more, but in
only photographs, but this is not correct. Pyke
the book two well-known philosophy couples, the
asked each person to provide a digest definition of
Kitchers and the Churchlands, are shown indi-
philosophy. It is intriguing to see how the diverse
vidually, not pairwise.) In their joint photo, Sally
figures here met the capsule challenge, probably
Haslanger gazes off to the side while husband
more so for those of us in the business than for
Stephen Yablo looks at the camera. Haslanger
others. But the blurbs bear little relationship to
looks as if she would rather not be there. Their
the image on the facing page. The only exception
poses reverse the common trope of marriage
might be the image of Louise Antony. She speaks
portraits in nineteenth-century photographs,
about her lifelong desire to “figure it all out”, a
showing a wife who looks towards her husband
sentiment that fits perfectly the image showing
while he gazes straight ahead. (I have just such a
her as rather toothily voracious.
wedding photograph of my great-grandparents.)
The most interesting of the comments for my
In the photograph showing daughter–father
purposes was also the only one that connected
couple Elizabeth and Gilbert Harman, she
philosophy to the portrait process itself, by
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
thoughts/portraits 58
small adornments, like a trace of lipstick or the
Sally Haslanger, Stephen Yablo
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
shares. He does not pretend that we can under-
thoughts/portraits
Reprinted with permission from Philosophers by Steve Pyke, published by Oxford University Press, Inc. © 2011 Oxford University Press
for creative activity because it is something he stand philosophy, as he puts in it in the book, “by looking at the faces of its practitioners”. Rather, he is showing people as part of a community or almost a family. He explains, “The Philosophy Tribe is made of thinkers, which is an honourable profession that deserves a wider audience. My series ‘outs’ these thinkers”. The problem I have Louise Anthony
with this may come back to the ambiguity of the label “philosopher”, between the honorific sense
Richard Moran. Moran says he doesn’t recall the
and its usage as the title for someone who works
moment of each picture or what he was expressing,
as a university teacher of philosophy. “Outing”
and this means it is just up to the viewer to see.
philosophers in Pyke’s oeuvre appears to involve
“This abandonment of control over meaning can
showing them as people who are fixated on some-
seem to compromise one’s autonomy; it can also
times odd problems and pursuits. They have a
seem a condition of embodiment and expressivity
form of life that is alien to many and that does
at all.” Pyke echoes Moran’s sentiments when he
not require meeting conventional standards
describes the person in a photographic portrait
of attire or grooming. Publicity from his New
as experiencing a sense of puzzlement about the
York Gallery, Flowers, puts the point this way:
picture, “How is that me?” This is indeed the
“Through the stark detail of his portraits Pyke
ultimate challenge of the portrait encounter:
is able to erase the lofty reputation that is often
the artist is in control of the depiction, but
placed on philosophers who ponder life’s seem-
must also render the subjectivity – the person-
ingly unanswerable questions” (my emphasis).
hood – of the sitter. Portraiture often places the
The aims of “outing” and “erasing lofty reputa-
artist and subject in a competitive relationship,
tions” may account for the somewhat odd look
a struggle for dominance about who controls
of so many of the people in these portraits. But
the final image. Many famous portrait artists
it also means, unfortunately, that if we seek the
detested their work because of the requirement
mystique of the philosopher as sage here, we will
to please sitters. Those who work today without
not find it.
such restrictions, like Lucian Freud, can afford to treat subjects (even the Queen!) with hostility. In an Youtube clip called “Mind the Gap”, Pyke says that using the Rolliflex meant he had a more passive relationship with his subjects, looking down at the camera to focus rather than through it and at them, getting “in their face”.
Steve Pyke’s Philosophers is published by Oxford University Press The Philosophers Exhibition moves to Flowers Gallery, Cork Street, London, from ÿ September to ý October. See www.pyke-eye.com for more details.
He says he appreciates philosophers’ passion
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
59
tpm/forum
Best of luck
W
hat are the philosophical implications of chance? It turns out that there’s talk of luck almost everywhere in philosophy – in morality, theories of knowledge, debates about free will and determinism, thoughts about justice, even in reflection on the best way to live. A few questions will give you a feel for it. Whether or not someone does something wrong is often just a matter of luck – so how can we hold each other morally responsible for what we do? How free are we, if luck plays a large role in what we take to be our freely chosen actions? Can I really be said to know something if my knowledge depends on a bit of luck? What is the right response to the bad luck we encounter in life? Does justice demand that we help those who are down on their luck, through no fault of their own? It’s slightly weird that something as slippery as luck can figure in to questions at the heart of philosophy – questions about who we are and how we ought to live. Maybe we’re getting at something near the centre of our understanding of things, when we wonder about luck.
What does the idea that you could have done something else at the time come to? According to some philosophers, it comes to this: in a hypothetical universe that has exactly the same past as our universe and exactly the same laws of nature, you do something else at this very time.
forum/lucky choices
Chance, choice and freedom ALFRED MELE SPINS THE NEURAL ROULETTE WHEEL BEHIND OUR DECISIONS
ou’re enjoying a leisurely walk in
Y
else instead at the very time you made that
the woods when you come to a
decision.
fork in the path. You pause to think
What does the idea that you could have done
about what to do, and you decide
something else at the time come to? According
to go right. According to some philosophers, if
to some philosophers, it comes to this: in a hypo-
free will was at work at the time, you could have
thetical universe that has exactly the same past as
acted differently.
our universe and exactly the same laws of nature,
Philosophers tend to be cautious about theo-
you do something else at this very time. In our
retical matters. Decided to go left is a different
universe, you decide on the right fork at noon.
mental action from deciding to go right. But we
And in a possible universe that would have been
might say that deciding a bit later than you actu-
actual if you had behaved differently at noon –
ally did – say, deciding on the right fork after an
one with the same past as the actual universe >>>
extra thirty seconds of thought – is another way of acting differently. Other alternatives include deciding to turn back and deciding to sit for a while. The main point, according to the philosophers I have in mind, is that if you freely decided
Alfred Mele is William H and Lucyle T Werkmeister Professor of Philosophy at Florida State University and author of Free Will and Luck (Oxford University Press, úøøþ)
on the right fork, you could have done something
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
61
forum/lucky choices
How do your decision-making processes work? right up to noon and the same laws of nature –
deciding to turn around, deciding to sit down,
you do something else at noon. Having a label
and so on. When the wheel is activated, a tiny
for this idea will save space: I’ll call it Openness.
neural ball drops onto it. The ball bounces
Does Openness fit your experience of
along the wheel and eventually lands in a slot.
decision-making, at least in some cases? I predict
Its landing in a slot represents an outcome –
you’ll say yes. I’m not saying that you experience
for example, deciding to take the right fork or
other possible universes. The question is whether
continuing to think about what to do. Two adja-
it sometimes seems to you that, when you decide
cent slots represent the same outcome only when
to do something, you could have done something
one outcome is represented by more than five
else instead – and not just in the sense that if the
hundred slots. What determines the distribution
past (or the laws of nature) had been different,
of slots are the things I mentioned – your beliefs,
you would or might have done something else.
desires, reasoning and so on.
Your answer, I’m guessing, is yes. How do your decision-making processes work
how you work as a decision-maker if and when
if and when you have Openness? A simple model
you have Openness. But it is a model, and it may
might help. Here’s one. When you are unsettled
help you think about the nature of Openness.
about what to do, your beliefs, desires,
62
I’m not claiming that this is the only model of
wishes, hopes, habits, reasoning and the like all feed into a tiny neural roulette wheel in your head. The
The model suggests that your deciding on the right fork at noon was partly a matter of luck. Until the ball settled into a slot for that decision, there
wheel has a thousand slots. The
was a chance that it
slots represent outcomes. For
would land in a slot for
example, two hundred slots
another outcome.
may represent your deciding
Openness can be
on the left fork at noon while
frightening. Imagine a pres-
another two hundred repre-
ident who believes it would be
sent your deciding on the
best not to order a nuclear attack
right fork then. Continuing
but is considering doing it anyway. He
to think at noon about which
has Openness, the launch button is in
fork to take may be repre-
front of him, and pressing it is represented
sented by five hundred slots.
by several slots on his wheel. Pressing the
And the remaining hundred may
button would probably start World War III,
be divided among such things as
as the president knows.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
I prefer a less frightening
away, and his wheel is
story. Here’s one. Joe is down
activated. He decides
on his luck. He was expelled
to fire a warning shot. But
from college for cheating a
he’s nervous and shaky. He
few months ago, and his parents
accidentally shoots the cashier
disowned him. He’s been strug-
in the hand. Things could have
gling to make ends meet. Joe’s
turned out very differently.
complaints about his condition in a
I’ll return to Joe shortly, after a brief note on brain science. Some
ance to offer to sell him a gun. “With
scientists have reported what they
this,” the acquaintance says, “you can
regard as evidence of indetermin-
raise a lot of money in a hurry.” Joe’s
istic brain processes that influence
wheel starts spinning. He has never
behaviour. Indeterministic processes,
committed a violent crime and he
by their nature, leave open more than
has never handled a gun, but he is
one outcome. The experiments I have
open to the possibility. He decides
in mind were done with fruit flies, not
to buy the gun. In another possible
human beings. But if tiny brains are indeter-
universe in which everything is the same right
ministic organs, big ones might be too. The tiny
up to the moment he makes that decision, he
neural roulette wheel is a cartoon image of how
declines the offer.
an indeterministic brain might work in producing
A couple of days later, Joe’s thoughts turn to
decisions. I will not speculate about the low-level
the gun. He considers selling it for a small profit.
mechanics of indeterministic brain processes, but
His wheel starts spinning. Joe decides to keep the
I will mention an alleged possibility. In his book
gun for a while, but he could have decided to sell
The Mindful Universe, Henry Stapp suggests that
it. If the ball had landed one slot away, that’s what
there are quantum probability clouds associated
he would have done.
with calcium ions moving toward nerve termi-
A week later, Joe is wondering how he will pay his rent. He thinks again about selling the gun.
nals. This low-level openness can underwrite Openness.
And again the wheel starts spinning. He decides
Back to Joe. He had a string of bad luck. He
to use the weapon at a small shop on the other
made several bad decisions. Joe definitely isn’t a
side of town. Joe’s plan is to brandish it while
hardened criminal; and he’s far from thoroughly
loudly demanding money. He’s confident that the
bad. He’s good enough to have decided not to
cashier will simply comply; he definitely has no
buy the gun, to have decided to sell it without
intention of firing the gun. Unfortunately, things
ever using it, and so forth. And, each time, if the
don’t go according to plan. As Joe is speaking to
ball had landed just a slot away, he would have
the cashier in what he hopes is a very threatening
made a better decision.
voice, he sees the man reach under the counter – perhaps for a weapon. Joe thinks about running
Does Joe’s bad luck get him off the hook? Does it mitigate his moral responsibility for his >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/lucky choices
sketchy saloon prompt an acquaint-
63
forum/lucky choices
Your deciding is partly a matter of luck bad decisions? Or what? These questions are
that includes Openness and leaves nothing to
difficult. Some reflection on Joe’s internal work-
chance. They may believe that only this kind of
ings might help.
control – call it Magic – can make it truly up to
In the roulette wheel model of Openness, as
them what they do. But this kind of control is
I mentioned, a person’s beliefs, desires, wishes,
just as impossible as a delicious cake sitting on
hopes, habits, reasoning, and so on all feed into
my kitchen counter even though I just devoured
the tiny wheel and determine what its slots
it. Why? Because indeterministic control in the
represent (including how many slots a possible
absence of chance is impossible. If Joe decided
outcome gets). All these things are influenced
with Openness to buy the gun, there was, right
by past decisions the person has made and his
up to the moment he made that decision, a
or her past behaviour. People can and do learn
chance that he would not make that decision
from their mistakes and from their successes; and
then.
what they learn has an effect on how the wheel
Some believers in Magic may be irresistibly
is divided up when it’s time to make a decision.
drawn to the conclusion that Joe lacks free will
Efforts at self-improvement can also have an effect on this. A person who has been smokefree for a year is likely to have a very different distribution of outcome slots when he feels tempted to smoke now than he did a year ago.
64
The same is true of a person who has made a lot of progress in overcoming a tendency to procrastinate or overeat. With this in mind, we might be inclined to see Joe as having significant responsibility for how his wheel is configured when he makes the decisions I described and for the decisions he ends up making. After all, he spent years shaping his wheel. To be sure, whenever there was Openness in his decision-making, some luck (or chance) was involved – but “some luck” might not be enough to absolve him of responsibility entirely. There are people who want to have their cake and eat it too. Some such people may want to have a kind of control over their decisions
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
and moral responsibility. But some of us seem
eliminate (or at least reduce) luck in an impor-
to be free to struggle with the question how free
tant sphere of life. Blackjack players who want
will and moral responsibility can coexist with
to maximise their chances of winning (legally, of
Openness. I struggle with this question in my
course) should learn how to minimise the poten-
book Free Will and Luck – even though I’m not
tial consequences of bad luck and to maximise
convinced that free will requires Openness.
the potential consequences of good luck. So they should learn to count cards, memorise a good set of blackjack tables, and play accordingly. What
moral responsibility. I thought about discussing
might rational folks do about the luck involved
a second kind of luck here (one associated with determinism), and I decided to settle the question
whether
I
would by tossing a coin. Given the outcome, I’ll
Scientists have reported evidence of indeterministic brain processes
stick with Openness.
in
Openness,
given
their aspirations? One thing they might do is to try to become so good at resisting temptation that there is no longer a chance that they will decide contrary to what
Many games involve a mixture of luck and
they judge best. If you see no good reason to
skill. In blackjack, players compete only with
prefer the left path to the right, and vice versa,
the dealer, whose every move is dictated by the
a wheel that gives you a fifty percent chance of
rules. Unlike the dealer, the players have options:
each decision should be fine with you. But when
for example, they can hit (request another card),
you know that it would be much better to go left
stand (refuse additional cards), double their bets
than to go right, a wheel that gives you a chance
in certain situations, and split pairs (for example,
of deciding to go right is potentially dangerous.
two aces) into two hands. What cards one gets is
Rational folks also try to learn from their
a matter of luck, and skilled players have memo-
mistakes and successes, and they sometimes
rised and are guided by reliable tables about
embark on projects of self-improvement. Again,
when they should hit, stand, and so on. Very
in the roulette wheel model of free agency, these
skilled players keep track of the cards they have
efforts shape decision wheels.
seen – they “count cards” – and they adjust their playing strategy accordingly.
In “Gimme Shelter,” Mick Jaggar warned that war is just a shot away. In a decision-maker
Free will may also involve a mixture of luck
with Openness, war might be just a slot away.
and skill. According to one way of thinking about
Fortunately, decision-makers who can shape
free will, just as luck is an essential part of (legal)
their wheels are not entirely at the mercy of
blackjack, the kind of luck involved in Openness
luck. And with luck, free agents may be able
is an essential part of becoming a free agent.
to configure their wheels in such a way that
But whereas luck is an ineliminable part of legal
they have no chance at all of making very bad
blackjack, free agents might reasonably seek to
decisions.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/lucky choices
Even if Openness is an illusion, other kinds of luck may seem to threaten free will and
65
forum/lucky knowledge
Our judgements about luck – and about related things, like risk – are for the most part sensitive to what is happening in close possible worlds rather than probabilities.
66
Knowledge or just a lucky guess? DUNCAN PRITCHARD EXPLORES NEARBY POSSIBLE WORLDS
I
t is a platitude in epistemology that knowl-
So, for example, a gambler who bases her
edge excludes luck. Epistemologists mean
belief about which horse won the 4.20 race on
something very specific by this claim,
mere guesswork, and who by luck happened to
however. In particular, they are not denying
be right, did not know what she believed. This is
the obvious fact that it is sometimes a matter of
because it is just a matter of luck that her belief is
luck that someone acquires knowledge (think,
true. In contrast, someone who forms her belief
for example, of lucky scientific discoveries, like
about which horse won the 4.20 race by seeing
the discovery of penicillin). Rather, what they
for herself the winning horse cross the line (in
are claiming is that if someone’s true belief is to
clear light, at close range, and so on) does know
amount to knowledge, then it cannot be a matter
what she believes. But in this case it is not down
of luck that the belief in question is true.
to luck that her belief is true. That knowledge is incompatible with luck in this way thus explains why mere true belief
Duncan Pritchard is chair in epistemology, school of philosophy, psychology and language sciences, at the University of Edinburgh. He is author of Epistemic Luck (Oxford University Press, úøøý).
cannot amount to knowledge, since merely true belief can be lucky true belief. But what needs to be added to true belief to eliminate knowledgeundermining luck and thus put that true belief into the market for knowledge? Here’s a natural
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
so on). We can now imagine the farmer believing
“justification”). If you saw the horse cross the line
on this basis that there is a sheep in the field.
for yourself in good conditions, then you’re in a
This belief is surely justified, in that the farmer
position to offer good reasons in support of what
can offer good grounds in support of his belief
you truly believe. If, on the other hand, you are
(for example, that the object in question looks
merely guessing which horse won, then you are
just like a sheep, that as a farmer he’s good at
not in a position to offer good grounds. Having a
spotting sheep, that he got a clear look at it, and
justification for your true belief therefore seems
so on). But now suppose that what the farmer
to suffice to exclude knowledge-undermining
is actually looking at is a sheep-shaped object
epistemic luck, and thus suffice for knowledge. Unfortunately, matters are not so simple, as Edmund Gettier showed in his famous threepage 1963 article which was published in the
Knowledge is incompatible with luck
journal Analysis (you can read the paper yourself at ditext.com/gettier/gettier.html). Gettier
which is not a sheep (but a big hairy dog, say).
offered some counter-examples to the idea that
Moreover, suppose that the farmer’s belief is
knowledge is justified true belief. Crucially for
nonetheless true because there happens to be a
our purposes, these examples appealed to the fact
sheep hidden behind this sheep-shaped object,
that even justified true beliefs could be subject to
away from the farmer’s view. The farmer thus has
knowledge-undermining epistemic luck.
a justified true belief, but it is not a case of know-
Here is an example of a Gettier-style case
ledge, and the reason why is that it is merely a
(not one of Gettier’s own, but due to Roderick
matter of luck that his belief is true. After all, his
Chisholm). Suppose that a farmer sees what
belief is only true because there just happens to
looks very much like a sheep in the field before
be a sheep hidden from view behind the sheep-
him (in good light, at sufficiently close range, and
shaped object.
67 >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/lucky knowledge
answer: good grounds (what epistemologists call
forum/lucky knowledge
Even justified true beliefs can be subject to knowledge-undermining luck
68
The upshot of Gettier-style cases is that
not a justification strong enough to eliminate
merely having justified true beliefs will not
knowledge-undermining epistemic luck, as we
suffice to eliminate knowledge-undermining
have just seen. Interestingly, however, Lottie is
epistemic luck. But that prompts the question of
able to come to know that she’s lost the lottery
what is required in order to have knowledge if it
by having a justification which is, from a purely
is not justified true belief? In particular, if having
probabilistic point of view anyway, much weaker.
a justification for your true belief won’t eliminate
For example, reading the result in a reliable
knowledge-undermining epistemic luck, then
newspaper is a good way of finding out whether
what will eliminate it?
your ticket has won. But the odds of even a reli-
Notice, first, that simply demanding a higher
able newspaper printing the wrong result, while
level of justification won’t help you deal with
no doubt very long (since a lot hangs on news-
Gettier-style cases. Imagine someone – let’s call
papers getting things like this right), are surely
her “Lottie” – who buys a ticket for a lottery with
much lower than a million-to-one. But why then
very long odds (a million-to-one, say). The lottery
can Lottie come to know that she’s lost via this
has been drawn, and the winner declared. Alas,
route but not by reflecting on the odds involved?
Lottie hasn’t won, but she hasn’t heard the result
In order to explain what is going on here, we
yet and so she doesn’t know this. Suppose that
need to make use of the notion of possible worlds.
Lottie now reflects on the long odds involved
(There are philosophical issues surrounding the
and so forms the true belief that she hasn’t won.
notion of possible worlds, but we don’t need to
Consequently, she tears up her ticket. Intuitively,
worry about them for our purposes – just think
though, Lottie can’t come to know that she’s lost
of these worlds as a helpful heuristic device.) The
on this basis (if it helps, imagine that it’s your
way things actually are is the actual world. But
lottery ticket that she tears up). Moreover, the
the world could have been different from how
reason why she lacks knowledge is that her belief
it actually is. I could have not eaten that bacon
is only luckily true. Her ticket could have been
roll this morning, and had fruit instead. The
the winning ticket after all, and if it had been,
capital of France could have been Lyon rather
then Lottie would have just made a very big
than Paris. Bill Gates could have been two-feet
mistake indeed in tearing up the ticket.
taller than he actually is. And so on. When we
Here’s the thing. Given that the odds are
imagine the world as being different from the
massively stacked against Lottie winning the
actual world, we are imagining a possible world.
lottery, and given that she knows this, her justi-
So, for example, there is a possible world which is
fication for thinking that she’s lost is about as
just like the actual world except that in this world
good a justification as it could be. But it’s still
Bill Gates is two foot taller than he actually is.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
order for you to be a winner (just a few coloured balls need to fall in a slightly different configuration). In other words, the possible world in which you win the lottery is a very close possible world, and it is in this sense that it “could” be you. This highlights something interesting about our ordering of possible worlds in terms of their similarity to the actual world, which is that close
The possible world where you win the lottery is a very close possible world We can think of these possible worlds as being more or less similar to the actual world in terms
worlds in which highly unlikely events, like
of how much would need to change about the
a lottery win, occur. Interestingly, our judge-
actual world in order to make it like the possible
ments about luck – and about related things, like
world. So, for example, a possible world in which
risk – are for the most part sensitive to what is
all that is different is that I am wearing blue
happening in close possible worlds rather than
rather than brown socks is much more similar to
probabilities.
the actual world than a possible world in which
For example, suppose the odds of me winning
London and Tokyo have switched places. Call
the 100m sprint at the 2012 Olympics are a
possible worlds that are very similar to the actual
million-to-one, just like the odds of our imaginary
world, close possible worlds.
lottery (in fact, I suspect these odds might well
With this framework in place, we can now
flatter my athletic potential). Would you think it
understand what is going on in the Lottie case.
a good bet to put a £1 punt, at those odds, on me
The slogan for the UK national lottery is “It
winning? I think you would be crazy to do so,
could be you”. Given the long odds involved,
and the reason for this is not the odds involved,
this is clearly not the “could” of probability, since
specifically, but rather the fact that the possible
from a probabilistic point of view it (basically)
world in which I win the 100m sprint at the 2012
couldn’t be you. The slogan makes sense though,
Olympics is simply too different from this world.
and that’s because the “could” question is not the
This is just not the sort of thing that happens in
could of probability. Rather, what the slogan is
worlds like the one we are in (think of all the
saying is that if you play the lottery, then very
things that would have to change about the actual
little needs to change about the actual world in
world in order to make it a world where someone >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/lucky knowledge
possible worlds can nonetheless be possible
69
like me wins this race). As far as this bet goes,
a way that she could very easily have formed a
then, it couldn’t be you in either of the senses of
false belief.
forum/lucky knowledge
“could” distinguished above.
that she had lost the lottery by reading the result
odds is not so crazy though (which is not to
in a reliable newspaper, then she would not be
say that it is rational), since while the odds are
exposed to anything like the same degree of epis-
still against you, this is the sort of thing which
temic risk. Reliable newspapers, after all, have
happens in worlds like the one we are in. That’s
sophisticated systems in place to ensure that
why even though most of us have the good sense
they don’t make errors of this sort (and for good
not to place bets on crazy events obtaining, lots
reason – think of all the problems that would be
Knowledge requires that our belief couldn’t have easily been false
caused by printing the wrong result), and so quite a lot needs to be different about the actual world before Lottie would form a false belief via this method. More specifically, the possible world in which Lottie wins the lottery but falsely believes that she hasn’t by this method is not nearly as
of us nonetheless play lotteries. We’re not being
close as the possible world where she forms
inconsistent in this regard. Rather, we’re being
the same false belief by reflecting on the odds
responsive to the fact that lottery wins, unlike
involved.
crazy events, obtain in close possible worlds (even despite the long odds). Putting all these points together, we can
70
In contrast, if Lottie had formed her belief
“Betting” £1 on a lottery ticket with the same
start to get a sense of what is going on in the Lottie case. The possible world in which Lottie wins the lottery is a world just like the one she is in; it is a close possible world. Now imagine this possible world where all that has changed is that Lottie’s ticket has won. Since Lottie forms her belief about whether she has won by reflecting on the odds involved (which of course have not changed), in this possible world Lottie will continue to believe that she has lost even though she has won. In this close possible world she will thus believe falsely, and that’s why her true belief in the actual world is subject to knowledge-undermining epistemic luck, even despite the excellent justification she has for her belief. For she is forming her belief in such
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
We can now see what we need to add to true belief in order to eliminate knowledge-undermining epistemic luck. What we are looking for is
forum/lucky knowledge
a belief which is not only true in the actual world,
famer continues to believe that there is a sheep
but which is also true in possible worlds that are
in the field on the basis of the sheep-shaped
similar, and thus close, to the actual world. What
object that he sees, and yet believes falsely (that
we are doing here is in effect trying to eliminate
is, the possible world where all that is different
high levels of epistemic risk from our beliefs. If
is that the sheep in question has wandered into
our true beliefs would have been false in close
a different field). That’s why the farmer lacks
possible worlds, then the success of that belief
knowledge in this case.
being true in the actual world was a risky success,
Having a true belief which is justified, even
in that it was a success that could so very easily
where that justification is very strong from a prob-
have been a failure. But knowledge ought not to
abilistic point of view, will not suffice to eliminate
be “risky” in this way. Knowledge thus requires
knowledge-undermining epistemic luck, and
not merely that our belief is true, but also that it
hence knowledge cannot be justified true belief.
couldn’t have easily been false.
Instead, we need to think about knowledge as
We can see this point in action in the Gettier-
demanding something which, in addition to true
style cases. Take the “farmer” case offered above.
belief, also ensures that one’s belief is true in
While this belief was both justified and true, that
close possible worlds. Epistemologists have done
it was true was still epistemically risky in that
a lot of work in the last few decades exploring
the belief could so very easily have been false.
what this “something” might be. But that is a
That is, there is a close possible world where the
topic for another occasion.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
71
forum/stoic luck
The worst thing that can happen to us is to be blessed with a life of unending luxury, comfort, and wealth, for such a life would make one weak and lazy. But worst of all, the longer we experience a comfortable and easy life, the harder it will hit us when our luck finally changes, as it surely one day will.
72
Tough luck JOHN SELLARS EXPLAINS HOW THE STOICS DEALT WITH ADVERSITY
T
here is a sense in which all of Stoic
philosophy is happiness or well-being. The way
philosophy is about luck. Strictly
in which the Stoics think we can achieve well-
speaking this is not true, of course, as
being is by looking closely at our relationship
the ancient Stoics developed a philo-
with the external world and at the way in which
sophical system addressing a wide range of topics
we ascribe value to things. In particular they
(from logic to politics, astronomy, and grammar),
suggest that we ought never to ascribe value to
but if one were forced to try to summarise the
external objects, situations, or even people. The
general thrust of Stoicism in just a few words it
only thing that has genuine value for the Stoics
would be tempting to say that it is most concerned
(or “goodness” in their technical terminology) is
with luck.
virtue, which might be glossed as an excellent
Let me try to flesh this out some more. Like
internal mental state. Conversely the only thing
the majority of other ancient philosophers the
that is truly bad is having a terrible mental state.
Stoics are eudaemonists, and so the goal of their
By happy coincidence, our internal mental state is practically the only thing that we can claim to have any control over, the Stoics suggest, making
John Sellars is a senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of the West of England and the author of The Art of Living: The Stoics on the Nature and Function of Philosophy (Duckworth, úøøā) and Stoicism (Acumen, úøøþ)
our well-being completely within our grasp. All those other things like wealth, success, health, and family that fate, fortune, and luck can withhold from us or take from us turn out to be completely unnecessary for a happy and good
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
To achieve happiness we must rethink our notion of luck There are two ways in which one might
that in order for us to achieve happiness or well-
unpack this doctrine, both of which I suspect
being we must completely rethink our notion of
will seem unpalatable to most modern readers.
luck.
The first would be to emphasise the fact that
In particular the Stoics suggest that we ought
the Stoics also believe that the universe is prov-
to reject our everyday notion of “bad luck”.
identially ordered. Without going too far into
Usually we talk in terms of being unlucky or
Stoic cosmology and theology, for our present
having bad luck when some unfortunate event
purposes we can simply note that the Stoics claim
occurs, or something we hold to be valuable is
that everything that happens is part of a deter-
taken away from us, or even when we fail to attain
mined and providential plan expressing the will
something that we hold to be valuable. In short
of a divine rational principle within Nature. So,
we think we experience bad luck when we lose
if it comes pass that my beloved pet cat should
or fail to attain some external thing that we think
die today, not only should I not be upset because
can contribute to our happiness. According to
the loss of my cat ought not to affect my virtue,
the Stoics such negative judgements are wholly
but I should also welcome the death of my cat
misplaced, for no external object or state of affairs
as a necessary part of a rational and providential
can either bring us happiness or impinge on our
divine plan. If “welcome” is too strong a word, I
happiness. Only our internal mental state can do
ought at the very least calmly to accept its death
that. Once we have the correct mental state, we
today as a necessary and inevitable moment in
shall realise that these supposed instances of “bad
the order of events.
luck” are no such thing; indeed, they ought to be of no consequence to us at all.
A second way to read the Stoic position would be to remain agnostic about the existence >>>
If one accepts this way of thinking, then it is equally so that there is no such thing as “good luck”. When we say that someone is lucky or has experienced good luck we suppose that something of real value has been gained or retained. Yet as we have seen, the Stoics will argue that this also mistakenly ascribes value to externals. I can experience neither “bad luck” nor “good luck” for whatever the external world might throw at me it can never take away or supply anything of genuine consequence for my happiness.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/stoic luck
life. The essence of Stoicism, then, is the claim
73
forum/stoic luck
of providence, as indeed a number of ancient
affect the spirit of a brave man”. The fact that
Stoics occasionally did, and treat external events
here and throughout On Providence Seneca’s
and states of affairs as just chance and random
references to “adversity” suggest he is closer to
occurrences. On this reading, there is certainly
the second reading of the Stoic position that I
no reason for me to welcome the death of my
outlined a moment ago. Even so, Seneca goes on
cat, or even to accept it as something necessary;
to argue that these adverse events not only don’t
I might instead see it as a completely random
affect the virtuous but are also genuinely posi-
event. Nevertheless I still ought to remain
tive for the rest of us too. We should approach
undisturbed by his death, ever conscious of the
any adversity we encounter in our lives as a “training exercise”. Like wrestlers who welcome
Why it is that good people suffer?
challenges that life throws at us as opportunities to develop our character. What we might be inclined to think of as “bad luck” should instead
fact that this cannot impinge on my inner virtue,
be embraced as valuable experience. Here
which, in turn, secures my happiness.
Seneca comes closer to the first reading of the
In the first reading there is no good or bad luck, for whatever happens is the necessary product of divine providence; in the second reading there is no good or back luck because whatever happens is of no significance for us. Strictly speaking the first reading is the orthodox
74
strong opponents, we too ought to welcome the
Stoic view, although ancient Stoics such as Seneca and Marcus Aurelius do sometimes write as if adopting the second reading, either because they are trying to persuade someone who doesn’t accept the existence of providence or because they themselves are conscious of the limits of their own grasp of the way the universe works. Many of these issues are explored in Seneca’s essay On Providence, in which he tries to answer the question why it is that good people suffer misfortunes in a supposedly providentially ordered world. As one would expect, Seneca challenges the assumption standing behind the question: “nothing bad can happen to a good man … adversity’s onslaughts are powerless to
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Stoic position, and indeed he goes on to suggest
Like wrestlers who welcome strong opponents, we ought to welcome challenges that we ought to think of these sorts of so-called
has something to say to us: such adversities may
adversities as not only positive but also deliber-
well be genuine evils, but if that is the case then
ately sent by divine providence.
all the more reason to train oneself to be able to bear them more effectively. The only serious training available is to suffer them first hand, so
adversity or bad luck, he suggests that it can have
suffering them does have its benefits.
two distinct positive roles: it can train virtue, and
As well as training the imperfect, these
it can test virtue. Those of us who are a long way
adverse events also test the perfect. Seneca
from having an excellent mental state (and that’s
quotes the Cynic philosopher Demetrius:
almost all of us, according to the Stoics) ought
“nothing seems to me more unhappy than the
to welcome adverse events as a form of training.
man who has no experience of adversity”, adding
I have already noted Seneca’s use of an analogy
“for he has not been allowed to put himself to
with wrestling, but now he uses use the more
the test”. We only find out who we are and what
graphic image of cauterisation. Poverty, hunger
we are made of when we are put to the test. If
and bereavement are all painful but necessary
we were never to experience any kind of bad
cures that will toughen us up and make us better
luck in our lives then we would never know how
prepared to cope with these same things in the
we would respond. Only when faced with a real
future.
challenge do we find out who we really are, and
It might be objected here that Seneca vacil-
that may be someone quite different from who
lates between the two readings of the Stoic
we thought we were. In any case such adversi-
position. If adversities such as poverty, hunger
ties are an inevitable part of life, so wanting to
and bereavement are not really bad at all, then
avoid them completely simply displays a failure
why do we need to be trained to endure them?
to grasp the nature of the real world. It is part
Surely we shouldn’t be thinking of these things
of the human condition to be tested in this way:
as needing to be endured at all, if they cause us
things will not always work out the way we would
no genuine harm. That would certainly be true
like; our plans will be thwarted some times; our
if we had mastered virtue, but while we are still
loved ones will die. Given these are simply facts
imperfect, I take it that these sorts of events
about the way the world works that reflect our
will continue to feel unwelcome for some time
limited power to control events, the real choice
to come, and the sceptic will of course say that
left to us is to decide whether to learn from
they will always feel unwelcome because they are
such experiences or simply moan about them.
genuine evils. But note that if one were to follow
As Seneca puts it, “disaster is virtue’s opportu-
that sceptical line of thought, then Seneca still
nity”. As for those who have never faced disaster, >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/stoic luck
As Seneca develops his thoughts about the positive nature of what we might ordinarily call
75
forum/stoic luck
“no one will know what you were capable of, not
one weak and lazy. But worst of all, the longer
even you yourself”.
we experience a comfortable and easy life, the
So, Seneca suggests that truly great people will delight in bad luck, treating it as both further
76
harder it will hit us when our luck finally changes, as it surely one day will.
training and an opportunity to show their true
So, turning all of our ordinary thinking about
worth. If one is minded to believe in divine
good and bad luck on its head, Seneca argues
providence then, given these benefits of adver-
that the truly unlucky are those that have never
sity, one might even see bad luck as a gift or
experienced adversity. As for us, we ought not
blessing from the gods. We should think of such
only to welcome what we ordinarily call bad luck
tests as compliments, a bit like the soldier who
but also be very wary of good luck. The tradi-
is selected by his commander for an especially
tional problem of evil that opens Seneca’s essay
difficult mission.
– why bad things happen if the universe is provi-
If this sounds a bit extreme, Seneca goes even
dentially ordered – simply vanishes, for those
further. Not only should we welcome what we
supposedly bad things are in fact of great service
might ordinarily call bad luck; we should also
to us. The same thought was expressed many
shun what we usually think of as good luck:
centuries later by Friedrich Nietzsche, when he
“the greatest danger comes from excessive good
wrote “that which does not kill me makes me
fortune”. The worst thing that can happen to us
stronger”. This line of thinking offers a powerful
is to be blessed with a life of unending luxury,
challenge to how we ordinarily think about luck,
comfort, and wealth, for such a life would make
even if we might not be entirely convinced.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Even before we come to consider the influence of luck in terms of the results of our actions or the types of situations we come across, luck plays a decisive role in who we fundamentally are.
NAFSIKA ATHANASSOULIS PONDERS CASES OF MORAL LUCK
To understand the problem of moral luck we
connection between assigning moral responsi-
need to take a step back and consider what is
bility to agents for their actions and assuming that
involved in making moral judgements. When we
they had control over their action.
77
make judgements of moral praise and blame,
Moral luck poses a problem because it chal-
we do so on the assumption that the actions
lenges this fundamental assumption about
we are judging are attributable to the person in
morality and control. In cases of moral luck, a
question. In other words, what the person did
significant aspect of the action is outside the
was, in some sense, under his control. So, for
agent’s control, but we nevertheless still think
example, if A slaps B, fully intending to cause B
that moral praise and blame are appropriate
harm, we would hold A responsible for the slap.
responses. It’s not clear why we should. Bernard
However, if instead it so happens that A suffers
Williams calls moral luck an oxymoron, because >>>
from unpredictable, involuntary movements, and B unknowingly moved into A’s space so that A’s jerking hand made contact with B’s face, we would no longer think it appropriate to hold A morally responsible for this act. It was not something A had control over. Morality presupposes
Nafsika Athanassoulis is lecturer in ethics at the Centre for Professional Ethics at Keele University and author of Morality, Moral Luck and Responsibility: Fortune’s Web (Palgrave, úøøý)
control, and there seems to be a fundamental
4TH QUARTER 2011
forum/moral luck
The good, the bad, and the lucky
tpm
forum/moral luck
morality presupposes control and responsi-
gun works, and he kills his intended victim. The
bility, but luck is about the lack of control. Cases
second is not, because his gun jams, and rescuers
of moral luck bring to the surface exactly this
step in to prevent him from taking further action
tension between morality and luck, and leave
– his intended victim survives unharmed. It
us wondering about the validity of our moral
seems that the only difference between the two
judgements.
men is the quality of their guns. In the end, one
Thomas Nagel described cases of moral luck
man stands over a corpse, and the other has not
as falling into three broad categories: resultant
caused any harm. The results – the presence of
luck, situational luck, and constitutive luck. We’ll
a dead victim in one case and a lucky survivor in
consider some examples of each, and then briefly
the other – might be what leads us to conclude
consider some responses to the problem of moral
that the successful murderer is more morally
luck.
reprehensible than the unsuccessful murderer.
To get a handle on resultant luck, imagine two
We draw this conclusion despite the fact that it is
people plotting murders. They both take steps to
only a matter of luck – something entirely outside
carry out their vicious intentions: they load their
of their control – that separates them.
guns, point them at their victims, and pull the
It’s not just rare events like murders that
triggers. The first agent is “successful” in that his
are affected by luck. There are far more
78
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Luck challenges assumptions about morality and control The difference in law is partly because of an
changing the outcomes of our actions. Many
important legal principle which says that legal
drunken drivers have the good luck to make it
sanctions are only applicable for what people
home in one piece without harming anyone else,
have actually done, as opposed to what we
but a number of them will, unfortunately, swerve
might think could have happened. While for
onto pavements just as pedestrians happen to
the purposes of a philosophical example we can
cross their path. Many overworked parents take
imagine two agents whose intentions to kill are
their eyes off their children at bath time, but only
identical, for legal purposes evidence of guilt
a few will suffer the horrific consequences of a
is only established based on what the agents
child drowning because they happened to look
actually did, rather than what they might have
away at just the wrong time. What differentiates
done had things been otherwise. So it may be
the agents who get away with their inattention or
less problematic to draw a sharp division in
their drunkenness from those who do not is often
terms of our legal judgement of murderers and
just a matter of luck.
attempted murderers than in terms of our moral
While we want to hold people responsible for
judgement of the same agents. It is anyway
the results of their actions, there does seem to be
not unusual for legal and moral judgements to
an incongruity in letting some off with a lighter
diverge. It is illegal to ride a bicycle on a foot-
judgement simply because something outside of
path, but there’s nothing immoral about this,
their control prevented a disaster from occurring.
and while it is immoral to betray one’s partner
There is both a sense that the outcome should
with an adulterous relationship, there’s no
sway our moral judgements in these cases, and
reason that this transgression should be dealt
a sense of the underlying unfairness that that
with by the law.
chance should make such a huge difference to our evaluations.
We come now to situational luck. The proverb “There but for the grace of God, go I” captures
It is perhaps worth pausing here to make an
in a very evocative manner the recognition that,
important point about the distinction between
sometimes, luck is all that separates us from the
moral and legal judgements in cases of moral
fate of others.
luck. The severity of legal judgements in cases
Consider two German citizens just before
like the ones above may well vary depending
the start of the Second World War, who have
on elements of luck. We give the successful
pretty much similar moral characters in terms of
murderer a long sentence, but the attempted
their ability to stand up to moral inequities. One
murderer gets off with a shorter one. But how
of them happens to emigrate to Latin America
could a jammed gun make a moral difference?
shortly before the rise of the Nazi party, just >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/moral luck
commonplace examples of this kind of luck
79
forum/moral luck 80
because he is fed up with the cold weather in
from actors or people posing as authority figures.
Northern Europe. As a result, he avoids all of the
The surprising results of the experiments were
subsequent moral challenges involved in living in
that while 100% of subjects predicted that they
Nazi Germany. Simply because he is no longer in
would resist being forced to behave immorally,
the country, he does not need to decide whether
up to 60% of subjects in experimental situa-
to collaborate or not, he is not tempted by Nazi
tions gave in to authority, to the point where
inducements or threats to behave in morally
they were willing to seriously harm and possibly
abhorrent ways. The other German citizen
kill another human being simply because they
happens to continue living in the country, and
were being told to do so. The problem here is
How could a jammed gun make a moral difference?
that while we want to hold those who fail such moral tests responsible for their actions, there is a sense of unease that others escape the same moral judgement merely by luckily avoiding certain situations altogether. Since the situations we find ourselves in are largely governed
therefore his ability to continue to behave morally
by luck, this seems, again, to sever the link
is put to the test. He faces the pressure of social
between moral responsibility and control over
conformity and the threat of punishment for non-
one’s actions.
compliance. While some people did successfully
We can generalise this point to include
resist the Nazis, at huge cost to themselves and
not merely situations involving great tempta-
their families, a lot of German citizens at the time
tions or threats, but all situational factors that
failed this moral test. However, the disturbing
go towards shaping who we are. Situational
conclusion of this example is that many more
luck then broadens to become a kind of devel-
people might fail moral tests if they are exposed
opmental luck, for all sorts of arbitrary factors
to them. The reason they were not is down to
go towards determining the sorts of people we
nothing more than the luck of their situation.
are. Factors such as where we are born, what
In the example above, a coincidental move to
kinds of role models we are exposed to, who our
another country at the right time got a person
friends, influences and peer group are, how we
out of a morally difficult situation.
are educated, and so on – all of this shapes our
While we would all like to assume the best
personalities.
for ourselves and would think that, faced with
Imagine a child exposed to the worst influ-
great temptation or great difficulty, we would
ences and role models. This child has a much
rise to the occasion, empirical evidence suggests
more difficult situation to overcome than a child
that this is just wishful thinking. In the 1960s,
who is exposed to much better influences and
the American psychologist Stanley Milgram
role models. The first child’s failure on the road
conducted famous experiments which placed
to virtue may be the result of the kinds of influ-
participants in situations that tempted them to
ences he was exposed to, rather than a personal
perform immoral acts, pushed on by pressure
characteristic under his control which we might
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
think naturally merits moral blame. And what
factors outside the agent’s control affect moral
holds true for children often holds true for adults
judgements. At the centre of this response is the
as well, for the road to vice or virtue is a long one,
Kantian idea that the goodness of the good will
one that involves a lifetime of gradual and deli-
is entirely independent of external factors. One
cate development. We can be easily diverted by
is good or bad no matter what the consequences
factors we have little control over.
of one’s actions are. Think again about the two people planning murder. Neither the dead victim nor the lucky escapee are relevant. The agents’
third type of moral luck that is even more perva-
intentions were identical in both cases, and it’s
sive than the first two: constitutive luck. We have no control over the tendencies and character traits that form who we are in the first place. When we observe even small infants we can sometimes see temperamental differences, differences which may eventually make virtuous
One is good or bad no matter what the consequences are
choices a lot easier for some than for others. For someone who is naturally even-tempered, kind,
the will of the agent that matters in judgements
and fair-minded, it will be much easier to culti-
of moral praise and blame. So Kant can side-step
vate these natural tendencies into stable and
the problem of moral luck. Both the attempted
fixed dispositions. Someone who is naturally iras-
murderer and the murderer are equally blame-
cible, self-centred, and rash might have a natural
worthy. There’s a Kantian reply to problems
tendency towards vice to constantly overcome.
associated with developmental luck too. For
This seems to suggest that even before we come
Kant, the freedom to make good choices is avail-
to consider the influence of luck in terms of the
able to anyone at any time, so developmental and
results of our actions or the types of situations we
constitutive factors do not carry the weight we
come across, luck plays a decisive role in who we
might think they do.
fundamentally are.
Finally, a second approach accepts the influ-
So the problem of moral luck affects a wide
ence of luck but argues that this is a positive
range of our moral judgements. And in many
feature of human experience. This approach,
cases there is a tension: we both want to hold
broadly speaking, has its roots in the work of
people morally responsible for aspects of their
Aristotle. It is the very fragility of our moral
behaviour and, at the same time, we feel uneasy
endeavours that give human lives their interest
in the recognition of the influence of luck in
and richness. We should neither deny the influ-
shaping these aspects.
ence of moral luck, nor abandon ourselves to it.
Broadly speaking there are at least two
Instead, we should embrace it as a fundamental
general responses to the problem of moral luck.
feature of what it means to live distinctively
The first resolves the tension created by the
human lives. Morality is fragile, and all the more
problem of moral luck by refusing to accept that
precious for being so.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/moral luck
If resultant and situational/developmental luck were not problematic enough, there is a
81
forum/luckless
People who suffer survivor’s guilt reason that, if they survived while others didn’t, then this must be because of the choices that they made, and that others did not make. People with survivor’s guilt feel just the way they would feel if they did not really believe in luck.
82
No such luck DARREN DOMSKY’S THOUGHTS ON THE PSYCHOLOGY OF LUCK
T
wo men walk to the middle of a
blocks their view. This particular pair of pedes-
highway overpass in order to do a
trians is disappointed by this, because it makes
terrible thing. They are going to drop
their evil task extra difficult. They can hear the
bricks down onto the road underneath.
steady stream of cars passing underneath, but
Tragically, people sometimes do this without
they have no idea when exactly to throw. They’ll
realising what could happen, but these two men
have to guess.
know exactly what could happen. If a brick hits
To reduce later uncertainty, each spray paints
a car, it will go right through, and instantly kill
his brick a distinct colour, and gains a useful nick-
anyone it hits. From the tops of overpasses,
name in the process. Red sprays his brick red,
dropped bricks are like fired cannonballs, and
and Green sprays his brick Green. With the paint
these two men know it.
still wet, they throw their bricks over the wall,
On many overpasses, pedestrians can see the
and down onto the passing traffic.
cars passing down below, but on this particular
As it happens, one of the bricks hits the
overpass they can’t, because a tall brick wall
pavement, and smashes into harmless pieces. The other smashes through a car roof, and kills someone instantly.
Darren Domsky is assistant professor of philosophy at Texas A & M University Galveston
Obviously these two men are terribly blameworthy. They have each done a terrible thing, on purpose, and with malice aforethought. But
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
forum/luckless
are they equally blameworthy? Put another way,
only once. I’m not sure that Green is twice as
when you find out that one of the bricks killed
blameworthy as Red, but he certainly might be.
someone, do you need to know its colour?
Many insist that Red is more blameworthy.
If you say yes, this means that you believe in
They insist that blameworthiness hinges on the
moral luck. If you say no, this means that you
luck of outcomes. Yes, in one sense, Red and
don’t. I don’t. To my horror and amazement,
Green did exactly the same thing: they know-
though, many do.
ingly and deliberately risked killing innocent
To make our contrast clearer, let’s add two
people. But in another, very important sense,
details to the story. As it turns out, the brick that
Red did something in addition to this: he actu-
killed was the red brick. But as it also turns out,
ally killed someone. For some, this just matters;
Green did not throw just one green brick, but
and it matters a lot.
two. The one red brick killed someone. The two green bricks shattered harmlessly on the road.
83
I suspect that this has been one of our strangest, most difficult to catch errors. It is
Now the blameworthiness has to be unequal.
widely, even standardly believed that when you
But which person is more blameworthy? I say
try to do an evil thing, and succeed, then obvi-
it is obviously Green. He did a terrible thing –
ously the thing to say is that you did an evil thing.
he knowingly and deliberately risked killing an
Though the outcomes of their actions were
innocent person – and, even worse, he did it
uncertain, Red did an evil thing, and Green only
twice. Red did the exact same thing, but did it
tried to.
>>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/luckless
Most people expect that their futures will be lucky
84
Nonsense. Red tried to do an evil thing, and
In two articles, “There Is No Door”, and
that is all that Red did. Green also tried to do
“Tossing the Rotten Thing Out”, I offered an
an evil thing – twice – and that is all that Green
explanation that seemed to do better. Our belief
did. Obviously things worked out differently with
in moral luck, I argued, stems from the combina-
the different bricks, but this is because of how
tion of two biases: a selfish bias, and an optimistic
Red and Green’s doings interacted with the rest
bias.
of the world’s doings. Red and Green only modi-
To be selfishly biased is to be tempted
fied the probabilities of what might happen, and
toward moral beliefs that you would like to be
made various outcomes possible. The world then
true. If your name is Mr Aardvark and you are
resolved those probabilities, and made certain
a white graduate student, then it is not terribly
outcomes actual.
surprising if you are morally appalled by affirm-
We fail to see this in the case of Red and Green
ative action and flat taxation, but morally fine
because we fail to see such things in general. As
with mandatory retirement and alphabetical first
Gilbert Harman originally noted on this topic,
authorship.
human beings reliably commit what researchers
To be optimistically biased is, in effect, to
describe as the fundamental attribution error. We
believe that you have a special, even magical
tend to over credit agents, and we tend to under
knack for being lucky. Most people expect,
credit features of those agents’ situations, in our
and seem to expect, that their futures will be
explanations of behaviours. I’ve always suspected that this explanation was not enough. As it turns out, so has Harman. In correspondence, Harman describes a problem that he noticed right from the start. For whatever reason, people tend to commit the fundamental attribution error selectively. When they judge others, they typically commit the error; but when they judge themselves, they typically resist committing the error. This predicts that people would blame others for their bad moral luck much more than they would blame themselves for their own. In reality, though, we see the opposite pattern. People blame themselves more.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
You probably suffer from the illusion of control disproportionately more lucky than the futures
use this power. In other words, in my particular
of similar others.
case, negligence plus bad luck is probably not negligence plus bad luck at all. It is probably negli-
belief that most of us are selfishly tempted to
gence all the way down. I negligently took a risk
hold, but on irrationally optimistic grounds. If I
that I shouldn’t, and I negligently failed to use my
have a magical gift for being lucky, and if a belief
special powers to prevent the unlucky outcome. I
in moral luck will allow this gift to systematically
am especially blameworthy because I am blame-
favour me, by letting the ungifted shoulder much
worthy for two reasons, instead of just one.
more statistical blame than the gifted in cases
Even when I submitted them, though, I could
of equal negligence, then I will be tempted to
tell that these two articles did not go far enough.
uphold this belief. This, I insisted, is where our
If Sally is morally unlucky, and someone gets hurt
belief in moral luck comes from.
or killed as a result, Sally probably does not react
One of the best features of this explanation
like someone who rarely experiences bad moral
was that it got the pattern right. If I see myself as
luck. She probably reacts like someone who
having a magical gift for being lucky, then I will be
never does. But how could this be?
especially horrified when I am morally unlucky,
As a precursor to a possibly improved answer,
because this means that I had the power to avoid
let me ask an interesting question. Do you really
the unlucky outcome, but somehow failed to
believe in luck?
forum/luckless
The two biases combine to produce a moral
>>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
85
There are many reasons to doubt that you do.
forum/luckless
Let’s survey four examples.
does, I am likely to suspect that Fred deserved
To begin with, you probably suffer from illu-
this good fortune, and am likely to like Fred more
sion of control. If we set up a randomly blinking
than before. These phenomena are described
light and a button, and ask you to figure out
in the research as just-world phenomena, and
how to control the light with the button, you are
they become much easier to make sense of if we
very likely to figure out a method, even though
hypothesise that people do not actually believe
there is none. The button is not connected to
in luck.
the randomly blinking light. You only think that
Fourth, if, by luck, you survive something (a
it is. The same goes for rolling dice or flipping
battle or a car crash) and others do not survive
coins: we are easily tempted to think that we have
it, you are likely to suffer survivor’s guilt. This
control when we do not. For laughs, consider
mental condition is complicated, and it is typi-
asking your friends why they find it so difficult
cally subsumed under the broader category of
to watch a sporting event after it has taken place.
post-traumatic stress disorder, but notice the
This can be surprisingly difficult for people to do,
common thread. People who suffer survivor’s
and, time and again, only one explanation really
guilt reason that, if they survived while others
fits. We believe, as TV viewers, that we can affect
didn’t, then this must be because of the choices
the outcome of live televised sporting events. If
that they made, and that others did not make.
I cheer just right, my team will win. This can
In other words, people with survivor’s guilt
be embarrassing to realise. But does realising it
feel just the way they would feel if they did
change anything?
not really believe in luck. Again, unless it turns
Second, you probably have a tendency toward
86
chance, Fred wins something and no one else
out that people do not actually believe in luck,
hindsight bias. In other words, you probably
this phenomenon can be very difficult to make
overestimate how foreseeable – and personally
sense of.
foreseen – events and outcomes were before
If I am right about this, and human beings
they happened. Unless you doubt the reality of
don’t really believe in luck, then no wonder so
resultant luck, this belief is hard to make sense of.
many of us blame Red more than Green. Deep
Third, if, purely by chance, something bad
down, without necessarily realising or even
happens to someone, you probably cannot help
suspecting, we think that Red must have tried
but like that person less than before. Strangely
harder, or better, than Green did. Red killed
enough, we humans read meanings and expla-
someone because he really tried to. Green did
nations into purely chance events. If my friends
not because Green did not really try to.
and I draw straws to see who pays, and if, just by
But wait a minute. If I am right, then why do
chance, George comes up short, I am likely to
only many of us blame Red more than Green?
suspect that George must have deserved to come
Why do some of us – me included – blame Green
up short, and am likely to like George slightly
more than Red?
less than before. Similarly, if a group of us buy scratch-and-win lottery tickets, and if, just by
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
These are excellent questions. Something is still missing. But what?
What is it that makes the involuntarily unemployed, those suffering from genetic disorders and congenital illnesses, and the victims of unforeseen natural disasters the rightful recipients of assistance?
forum/just luck
Should a just society neutralise luck? ALEXANDER BROWN CONSIDERS THE POSSIBILITIES
P
hilosophers have had much to say
the freedom to take risks and trust to good
on the subject of luck and justice. In
fortune enables individuals not merely to accu-
her book Justice By Lottery, Barbara
mulate wealth at a pace that would otherwise be
Goodwin proposes the use of lotteries
very difficult or impossible, but also to express
for settling certain questions of distribution, such
to other people the type of characters they are.
as the allocation of places at elite universities, as
Since the early 1980s, however, discussion
an alternative to distribution-by-merit, which
of another type of luck has become prevalent
is susceptible to deadlock, error in judgement,
in philosophical books and journals. A number >>>
bias and freak results. For Goodwin, luck is the servant of just outcomes. A more general point of consensus is that the influence of luck per se does not make outcomes unjust. So, for example, Ronald Dworkin insists that it is perfectly just for inequalities of wealth to develop on the basis of “option luck”, which is “a matter of how delib-
Alexander Brown is lecturer in social and political theory at the University of East Anglia. He is the author of Ronald Dworkin’s Theory of Equality: Domestic and Global Perspectives (Palgrave, úøøā) and Personal Responsibility: Why it Matters (Continuum, úøøā).
erate and calculated gambles turn out”. Having
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
87
Suffering “brute luck” can be a source of claims in justice
forum/just luck
of philosophers are persuaded by the idea that
However,
before
luck
egalitarians
can
suffering “brute luck” can be a source of claims in
convince the rest of the philosophical commu-
justice. The popularity of this idea owes much to
nity to adopt the luck-neutralising aim − not to
the popularity of the late Oxford philosopher G A
mention those legislators who are responsible
Cohen. For Cohen and other “luck egalitarians”
for doing something about it − there is a large
(as Elizabeth Anderson calls them) a just society
amount of scepticism and unease which remains
is one that attempts to neutralise the influence
to be conquered and dispelled.
of brute luck on people’s life prospects. What
Some of that scepticism derives from
is it, for instance, that makes the involuntarily
uncertainty about what qualifies as brute luck.
unemployed, those suffering from genetic disor-
Metaphysical theories of brute luck appeal to
ders and congenital illnesses, and the victims of
the notion of circumstances that lie beyond the
unforeseen natural disasters the rightful recip-
control of the individual. Cohen freely admits
ients of assistance? That they have all suffered
that his theory of brute luck “subordinates
brute luck of course.
political philosophy to metaphysical questions that may be impossible to answer”. Hence, if the philosophical theory of hard determinism is true, and there is no such thing as a genuine choice between two or more actions, then
88
everything is down to brute luck. Or, as Cohen ironically puts it: “We may indeed be up to our necks in the free will problem, but that is just ‘tough luck’.” Yet many political philosophers are disinclined to follow Cohen down this road. Moralised theories of brute luck, by contrast, describe brute luck in terms of circumstances that are “arbitrary from a moral point of view”. One prominent idea is that something is arbitrary from a moral point of view if it is “undeserved”. In his A Theory of Justice, for example, John Rawls describes the contingencies of people’s starting place in society and the distribution of natural abilities as undeserved. At first glance it remains unclear what makes
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
But even the more limited task of persuading
fact that it lies beyond the control of the indi-
egalitarians to become luck egalitarians depends
vidual. But for some moralised theories it makes
on how the category of brute luck is to be speci-
more sense to think of the terms “brute luck”
fied. It might be tempting to see this as a matter
and “undeserved” as placeholders for the more
of social convention. Brute luck is simply what-
complex idea that, in a society of equals, it is
ever different cultures deem it to be. But then
departures from equality which stand in need
this opens the door to an objection from moral
of justification, and there are some things that
relativism. For it seems to rule out the possibility
a society of equals rejects as grounds for such
of external criticism of what another society does
departures.
or does not deem to be brute luck − the possibility
This way of thinking about brute luck answers
of criticising a society that regarded localised
another objection that has dogged luck egali-
flooding as divine punishment as opposed to
tarianism over the years, and which Susan
brute luck, for example. Even so, there is an
Hurley articulates in her book Justice, Luck and
alternative way of developing a moralised theory
Knowledge. From the mere fact that individ-
of brute luck that avoids the charge of relativism.
uals suffer underserved circumstances it does
It is to provide an objective account of what any
not follow that society has a duty to neutralise
successful political community must deem to be
or mitigate the impact of those circumstances.
brute luck, where success is defined in terms of
After all, just because someone does not deserve
fulfilling its most basic function over time, that >>>
forum/just luck
something underserved if not the metaphysical
to be ditched by his girlfriend it does not mean that he has a right to expect someone else to take her place. This is not how luck and justice work. However, the luck egalitarian does not claim
89
that the existence of undeserved circumstances alone renders people entitled to assistance. Rather, he claims that a society of equals is one in which everyone has a right to a certain range of basic opportunities, and brute luck does not have a rightful bearing on whether or not people enjoy such opportunities. What this means, of course, is that luck egalitarianism is unlikely to attract those who deny the basic premise that it is departures from equality that stand in need of justification. But then again, perhaps luck egalitarianism was never intended for those people who deny that basic premise. As Cohen puts it, “I take for granted that there is something which justice requires people to have equal amounts of.”
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
of protecting life and providing ample opportu-
aim is only one among other important aims
nities for comfortable living for all its members.
of justice and the good, so its pursuit must be
Arguably a society could not be successful in
subject to those other demands. While turning
these terms if it systematically failed to regard
over institutions to strong luck egalitarianism
genetic disorders and congenital illnesses, for
could well bankrupt a society, there is less
instance, as brute luck.
reason to be fearful of moderate luck egalitari-
However, whether brute luck is defined in
forum/just luck
metaphysical or moral terms, many philoso-
90
phers harbour deeper worries about what they
Brute luck is simply whatever different cultures deem it to be
anism, its aim being to neutralise brute luck only as far as is reasonable, all things considered. Nonetheless, some philosophers remain sceptical about luck egalitarianism because they say it ignores the distinction between justice and charity. If someone is in dire straits we may be more inclined to help her if we know she was the victim of brute luck than if she made reckless decisions. But that surely is a matter of charity,
see as the potentially disastrous consequences
not justice. Justice has to do with addressing the
of pursuing the luck-neutralising aim. Dworkin
consequences of human trespasses such as theft,
was among the first political philosophers to
fraud, exploitation, oppression, abuse, and negli-
be labelled “luck egalitarian”, yet he himself
gence. Perhaps theft, fraud, and so on, can all be
rejected the label on the grounds that in order
viewed as so much bad luck from the perspec-
to fully neutralise the influence of brute luck
tive of the victim. But to call these things “bad
on people’s life prospects it would be necessary
luck” is to overlook the fact that they are perpe-
in some cases to provide a level of compensa-
trated by human beings. And strictly speaking
tion that imposes an unbearable cost on society
justice is a matter of making amends for acts of
at large − “to spend all it could to improve the
humanity as opposed to “acts of God”.
position of those who had become crippled in
However, on closer inspection it can be hard
an accident, for instance”. How can it be just
to differentiate between human trespasses and
to bankrupt an entire community for the sake
natural misfortunes. For example, one might be
of neutralising the brute luck suffered by only a
tempted to categorise the victims of the drug
few of its members?
thalidomide as victims of human negligence
However, Dworkin’s misgivings about luck-
and the victims of childhood polio as simply
neutralisation overlook an important distinction
“unlucky”. But this is called into question if one
between two kinds of luck egalitarianism.
reflects on the facts that thalidomide passed the
Strong luck egalitarianism is the view that the
drug safety standards of the time and insuffi-
luck-neutralising aim is the principal or domi-
cient funding of polio vaccination has caused
nant aim and must be pursued at all costs, in an
millions of infections in the third world − a situ-
unqualified way. Moderate luck egalitarianism,
ation that is itself a product of man-made global
by contrast, is the view that the luck-neutralising
inequalities.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Justice is a matter of making amends for acts of humanity as opposed to “acts of God” mitigating the influence of social contingencies like family life on the distribution of life chances
being disabled is not the fact of being unable to
inclines in the direction of abolishing the family.
walk or hear or see but being forced to live in a
So much for luck egalitarianism.
society where access to valuable forms of work
But perhaps luck egalitarianism could be
and play are made conditional on being able
upheld without abolishing the family, provided
to walk or hear or see. For the most part we as
that more families, that is, more parents, are
citizens get to choose how our societies will be
willing to assume responsibility for engaging
organised, and if we have chosen to organise
in luck-neutralising activities − or at least
things (or have allowed things to be organ-
refraining from activities that make the distri-
ised) such that some individuals among us are
bution of advantages dependent on brute luck.
prevented from carrying out activities we take
What might this entail? Andrew Mason suggests
for granted, then this is a matter of justice after
that if the agreed aim is to neutralise the influ-
all. To the sceptic who says, “Nobody said life
ence of brute luck on people’s life prospects,
was fair”, one can reply, “True, but as citizens we
then it follows that parents should refrain from
have a responsibility to make society fair.”
reading bedtime stories to their children for fear
A final cause of unease surrounding luck
of placing them at an unfair advantage over chil-
egalitarianism has to do with the site of justice.
dren whose parents do not read such stories.
Many political philosophers share Rawls’s view
Mason regards this as a highly counter-intuitive
that the primary subject of justice is the “basic
implication of the luck-neutralising aim.
structure” of society, meaning the way in which
However, it is possible to avoid this implica-
major social and economic institutions shape
tion by appealing once again to moderate luck
the distribution of advantages that arise through
egalitarianism. Even though parents have a
social cooperation. It does not take long to
luck egalitarian reason to refrain from reading
recognise that the family is one major social
bedtime stories to their children, they also have
institution which actively enables brute luck to
other reasons to continue as they are. Shlomi
influence people’s life chances. A person’s will-
Segall avers one such reason: the desires of
ingness to make an effort in life will be partly
parents and children to develop close, loving
determined by upbringing, meaning that so
familial relationships. This falls under the more
long as there are variations in family life there
general heading of what Harry Brighouse and
will not be equal life chances. Rawls surmises
Adam Swift call “legitimate parental partiality”.
that “taken by itself” the aim of neutralising or
So long as parents are acting from the motive of >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
forum/just luck
More generally, disability rights campaigners have long argued that what is disabling about
91
forum/just luck
It would be wrong to think of luck as the enemy of justice
92
wanting close, loving familial relationships it is
no objection to luck egalitarians to point out that
not the end of the world that they are thereby
they have a long way to go in this endeavour.
failing to luck-neutralise. What we want is a
A stronger objection would be that teaching
society of reasonable luck egalitarians not a
parents to feel guilty about reading bedtime stories
society of luck egalitarian zealots.
to their children is either impossible or contrary to
Nevertheless, Mason insists that our intu-
what it means to be a parent. That encouraging
itions in this area are strongly against luck
parents to become luck egalitarian is either a waste
egalitarianism: what we intuitively feel is not that
of time or alienating. But how could one definitely
a luck egalitarian motive for parents refraining
prove that parents are incapable of feeling guilty
from reading bedtime stories to their children
about giving their children unfair advantages or
is being trumped by other concerns but that
that such guilt is contrary to the essence of parent-
parents have no reason whatsoever to refrain
hood? After all, do not (some) progressive parents
from reading bedtime stories. The evidence for
who send their children to expensive private
this putative strong intuition is the fact that most
schools feel a little bit guilty about this practice?
parents do not report feeling guilty about failing
My own experiences as both a parent and progres-
to luck-neutralise combined with the assump-
sive are that feeling guilty about what I do for my
tion that if the luck-neutralising aim did matter
own child comes as easily as feeling guilty about
to patents, then they would report feeling guilty
what I do not do for other people’s children. The
about setting it aside. This evidence must be
struggle that comes with believing that I have
taken with a pinch of salt, however, since it can
special duties toward my own child and general
be explained in a number of ways. It might be
duties to do the right thing by other people’s chil-
that some parents do experience these feelings
dren strikes me as entirely normal.
of guilt but simply do not admit it to others. Or
To sum up, while it would be wrong to think
it could be that the human psyche is capable
of luck as the enemy of justice, luck egalitarians
of unconscious suppression of certain forms of
believe that how societies respond to certain
guilt as a coping mechanism when faced with
kinds of luck can be just or unjust. That there are
the emotional challenge of parenthood. But
different ideas about what the relevant kind of
even if the evidence does suggest that at present
luck is and what governments and individual citi-
very few parents are luck egalitarians, this is
zens should do about it is a source of scepticism
hardly a knock-down objection to luck egalitari-
and unease concerning this theory. But that is to
anism itself. The ambition is to make the world
be expected. Few theories of justice escape it.
more luck egalitarian: to socialise new parents
Besides, the scepticism and unease is not always
into adopting this sort of egalitarian ethos. It is
well founded.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
PP CULTURE His renunciation of citizenship is a symbolic denial of American exceptionalism, but it is not an abandonment of America or the values that it – but not it alone – represents and promotes.
Un-American hero WAS SUPERMAN RIGHT TO RENOUNCE HIS CITIZENSHIP, ASKS ANDREW TERJESEN
S
uperman caused a bit of a stir in
Strip, Superman favours giving her a light
the real world when he announced,
sentence. Jimmy Olsen is outraged that he would
in the landmark 900th issue of
turn a blind eye to the danger she had posed, but
Action Comics, that he was going to
Superman answers him with a speech in defence
renounce his US citizenship. One conservative
of second chances: “That’s what America is about, really. That’s
displayed a “blatant lack of patriotism” and that
the American way. Life, liberty, the pursuit of
Superman was “belittling the United States as
happiness – and second chances. None of us
a whole”. Though this seems to be mostly an
are forced to be anything we don’t want to be …
example of media overreaction during a slow
People from all over America – from all over the
news cycle, why did it cause such a stir?
world – who went to the city to live the lives they
It’s worth noticing at the start that, for
wanted, to be the people they wanted to be. That’s >>>
decades, Superman has been seen as a distinctly American superhero. After all he fights for “truth, justice, and the American way”. But what exactly is the “American way” that he is fighting for? In a story that appeared just weeks after Action Comics #900, Superman explains what the American way means to him. After preventing
Andrew Terjesen is assistant professor of philosophy at Rhodes College. This article is abridged from Superheroes: The Best of Philosophy and Pop Culture, edited by William Irwin, and is part of a continuing series of extracts from the Blackwell Philosophy and Pop Culture Series.
the villain Livewire from destroying the Vegas
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
the lowdown/pop culture
activist told Fox News that Superman’s actions
93
the idea that America was founded on, but it’s not just for people born here. It’s for everyone.”
In his book Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers, Kwame Anthony Appiah
This statement dovetails very nicely with what
argues for a modern form of cosmopolitanism.
Superman said when he threatened to renounce
Instead of claiming that we are all part of one
his citizenship: “I can’t help but see the bigger
rational being or creature, as the stoics did,
picture. I’ve been thinking too small. I realize
Appiah appeals to the fact that we need to be
that now.” Superman may have meant that the
responsible for the effects our actions have on
values of America are not limited to America,
people around the world. Appiah emphasises
in which case it’s not clear why renouncing his
connectedness, as did the stoics, but he does not appeal to a single standard of the good.
What is the “American way” Instead, Appiah embraces the idea that there is more than one way to live a good that he is fighting for? life, and explains that cosmopolitanism has
the lowdown/pop culture
to find a way to balance the interconnectedness
94
citizenship is so controversial. Superman is
of peoples, and the obligations between them,
just trying to show how universal those values
with mutual respect for their differences.
are, and that there is no reason why one has to
Critics of cosmopolitanism fear that respecting
be an American in order to stand for them. If
everyone else’s life choices would create a
anything, renouncing his citizenship would serve
community based entirely on twenty-something
as a message to the world that those values are
hipster irony. Instead of patriotically defending
for everyone.
their community from threats, people would
The idea that we should think in global terms is
“patriotically” defend their community, going
known as cosmopolitanism, a word that combines
through the motions but not really believing that
the Greek words for the world (cosmos) and city-
it was truly worth saving. Since the members of
state (polis). Cosmopolitans are people who see
the community can’t fully commit emotionally to
themselves as part of a worldwide community
its defence, it is likely that they would not fight
and who try to experience and understand the
as vigorously as they otherwise would. Despite
larger world. As a philosophical view, cosmopoli-
what some commentators in the media may say,
tanism is the idea that we should organise society
Superman has not really rejected America. His
in order to create such a worldwide community.
renunciation of citizenship is a symbolic denial of
Many ancient Greek and Roman stoics
American exceptionalism, but it is not an aban-
endorsed a cosmopolitan worldview, according
donment of America or the values that it – but
to which the entire universe was a sentient
not it alone – represents and promotes.
and rational being that made sure everything
In all of the brouhaha surrounding Superman’s
happened in a rational manner. Endorsing a
decision, very little attention has been paid to the
strong form of cosmopolitanism, the stoics sought
context in which he says he is surrendering his citi-
to supplant particular cultures with a universal
zenship. In Action Comics #900, we see Superman
rational culture.
talking to the US national security adviser, who is
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
very upset because Superman created an inter-
authority he needs to demonstrate the essential
national incident when he travelled to Tehran to
traits of a moral person, especially impartiality.
support anti-government protesters. Rather than
We tend to think of an impartial person as
throw his weight around, he took no actions against
having an abstract point of view that transcends
the government forces, even when it seemed that
any particular feelings, but there is another
they would hurt the protesters. Instead he merely
way to think about impartiality. In The Theory
stood in the public square for twenty-four hours
of Moral Sentiments, Adam Smith proposed a
in tacit support of the protesters. The Iranian
theory of moral judgement that hinged upon
government nonetheless interpreted this as the
what he called the “impartial spectator”, but
American government, acting through Superman,
this meaning of “impartial” is not unemotional.
supporting the protesters, and voilà – we have an
Instead, Smith’s sense of “impartial” simply
international incident and further erosion in US–
refers to someone who does not have a partic-
Iranian relations.
ular interest in the outcome nor any connections
Superman feels compelled to renounce his
to anyone who is affected by the outcome. Notice
citizenship because as long as the most powerful
that Smith did not call for us to imagine an
being on the planet appears to be affiliated with
“unemotional spectator”. In fact, Smith thought
a particular government or nation, he is always
that our emotions conveyed important informa-
seen as acting in its best interests rather than
tion, although they need to be pure in order to
those of the world in general. As he says, “I’m
give us the right picture of the situation. If we are
tired of having my actions construed as instru-
personally interested in the outcome, we might
ments of US policy.” Superman sought to be a
not feel the right way about it. Whenever we think that someone has a
government and the protesters to resolve their
particular interest in something, we begin to
issues peacefully. But in order to exert moral
question their judgements on that topic. As >>>
the lowdown/pop culture
moral force in Iran, putting pressure on both the
95
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
Laura Hudson, a blogger at comicsalliance.com,
involved with the American government. In many
points out, as long as Superman is viewed as a
professions, conflicts of interest are dealt with by
US citizen “it would indeed be impossible for a
creating a so-called “Chinese wall” that blocks
nigh-omnipotent being ideologically aligned with
the flow of information between different parts
America to intercede against injustice beyond
of an organisation. Superman needs to maintain
American borders without creating enormous
a wall between him and the US government, so
political fallout for the US government.” Anything
that he does not appear to be receiving national
that Superman did that had indirect benefits for
secrets or taking orders from the president.
the US would be called into question. Superman’s
Superman is inescapably an American icon in that he is deeply embedded in American society.
“I’m tired of having my actions construed as US policy”
More accurately, he’s an icon who happens to be American. To some extent he will always favour America, but not because there is any clear set of distinctly American values that only America promotes or embodies. Still, Superman has to avoid creating the impression that his commit-
presence in Tehran could be viewed as support for
ment to America is also a commitment to US
a democratic movement, or it could be viewed as
foreign policy and its national interests. So the
an American attempt to destabilise an unfriendly
symbolic gesture of renouncing his citizen-
government. So the question we need to consider
ship might help in distancing himself from the
is whether Superman should feel morally obli-
American government in people’s minds.
the lowdown/pop culture
gated to avoid the appearance of impropriety.
96
The renunciation is not enough on its own,
To answer this question we need to recognise
however. Superman needs to show that he does
that impropriety is an unavoidable fact of life if
not take national interest into consideration
one is to maintain any commitments or close ties
when he acts, and the best way to do that would
at all. Rival newspapers undoubtedly think that
be to spend more time helping on a global scale.
Superman is “in bed with” the Daily Planet, but
Appiah’s modern cosmopolitanism encourages us
the fact that he often grants them interviews and
to broaden our perspective without giving up the
that they tend to portray him in a favourable light
culture that makes us who we are. Superman can
is more a function of his close contact with the
affect the world in ways that far exceed Appiah’s
members of the staff (one in particular). If we
examples of interconnectedness, so the argument
want to avoid the appearance of impropriety alto-
for cosmopolitanism is much more compelling
gether, we would need to shun any commitments
for Superman. If nothing else, the symbolic act of
that would produce normal associations. That, of
renouncing his citizenship would help Superman
course, is impossible, since our connections and
to think like a modern cosmopolitan when he
associations are part of who we are.
looks at the world’s problems – or, as the bumper
Even so, Superman does have a moral responsibility to make sure that he is not too closely
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
sticker says, he should act locally while thinking globally.
SNAPSHOT
Thomas Reid by James A Harris
T
homas Reid (1710–96) was the most
professorial system, so Reid was a “regent”, and
influential British philosopher of the
taught the whole curriculum to assigned cohorts
eighteenth century. David Hume is
of students. This demanded a wide range of learning, and for the rest of his life Reid maintained an interest in a large number of academic
taken positive inspiration from Hume’s writ-
subjects in addition to his specialism in philos-
ings. Hume had no disciples in his own time,
ophy. Philosophy was itself then a very much
and founded no school. Until the early twentieth
more capacious subject than it is now, and had
century Hume’s philosophy survived as some-
yet to be decisively separated off from empirical
thing to be refuted rather than as something
natural science, or from what we now call the
to be refined and extended. Reid, on the other
social sciences. Reid was a more than capable
hand, played a key role in the establishment of
mathematician, and was actively engaged in the
a method and body of doctrine that in the nine-
ongoing business of clarifying and developing
teenth century was taught in Scotland, France,
Newton’s scientific achievements.
Germany and Italy, and that also quickly crossed
Reid moved from Aberdeen to the chair of
the Atlantic to America. His influence waned
moral philosophy at Glasgow in 1764. He took his
at the beginning of the twentieth century, but
professorial duties as seriously as he had done his
the past thirty years has seen a major revival of
work as a regent, and letters survive in which he
interest in Reid and his style of philosophising.
complains, much as present-day academics do,
He is now once again a major figure in the phil-
about how teaching and administrative matters
osophical landscape, the subject of books and
are getting in the way of reading and writing.
conferences, and the first complete edition of his works is being published by Edinburgh University Press. Reid began his teaching career at Aberdeen, which then had two separate universities: King’s College in the old town, and Marischal College
James A Harris is senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of St Andrews and (with Knud Haakonssen) editor of Reid’s Essays on the Active Powers for the new Edinburgh Edition. He is writing an intellectual biography of Hume for Cambridge University Press.
in the new. Aberdeen had yet to switch to the
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
the lowdown/snapshot
now considerably better known, but it
is only relatively recently that philosophers have
97
The best way to approach Reid’s philosophy is
conscience, and the will. Very much a man of the
to see it in its original context, the context of the
Enlightenment, Reid saw it as his task to get his
classroom and the lecture hall, and to take seri-
pupils to understand the powers, or abilities, that
ously the idea, which Reid certainly believed in,
made them distinctively human, and to under-
of philosophy as a way to teach people how to
stand also how they might take responsibility for
form their beliefs and direct their actions. All of
themselves by exercising these powers in the best
Reid’s published works concern what he called
possible way. While still at Aberdeen, Reid read Hume, and
perception, imagination, memory, judgement,
came to the conclusion that Hume had brought
the lowdown/snapshot
“the powers of the human mind”: notably sense
98
ll
we
uth
ret
o hS
Ga
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
to light a scepticism that was inherent in Lockean
account of the powers of the human mind, Essays
empiricism. This scepticism was not, according
on the Intellectual Powers (1785) and Essays on
to Reid, a merely theoretical or academic issue.
the Active Powers (1788). In both works he insists
It was a scepticism about, precisely, the powers
on the activity involved in the life of the mind
of the human mind, and about the capacity of
as human beings know it. Hume presents the
human beings to know the world they lived in,
mind as a kind of machine, a machine moved by
and also about their capacity to engage practically
causal interactions between mental representa-
with that world in the manner of autonomous
tions. Reid, by contrast, conceives of thoughts as
moral agents. This scepticism, Reid thought, was
actions performed by persons. Action considered
dangerous, because if people took it seriously, they would be bound to live more intellectually and morally impoverished lives than they might do otherwise. An important aspect of Reid’s published writings was therefore a concerted effort to refute Hume’s arguments, not so much
What we perceive with our senses are things, not ideas
by showing them to be invalid as by showing that they proceeded from false premises.
quite generally, he argues, requires an agent, and agents are (so Reid says) by definition free in the
Mind on the Principles of Common Sense (1764)
way they use the powers at their disposal. Reid, in
is a brilliant assault on what Reid took to be the
other words, is a proponent of “agent causation”,
fundamental principle of modern scepticism
and rejects the view that actions, as such, can be
(Hume’s included), the claim that the immediate
caused by mental events. He gives a powerful
object of perception is always a mental repre-
series of arguments against the assumption that,
sentation, an “idea”, not the three-dimensional
at its most basic, the world is to be conceived
world of material entities. Reid argues that no
in terms of law-bound relations between events.
one has ever given a good reason to believe that
Reid’s renewed appeal today perhaps lies in
ideas exist, and that no one has ever explained
the fact that he enables us to say things that we
how, even if they do exist, they make percep-
are naturally inclined to say before we come into
tion possible. Reid proceeds by means of patient
contact with the arguments of philosophy: that
analyses of each of the five sense modalities, and
what we perceive with our senses are things,
he was one of the first philosophers to question
not ideas; that our actions are performed by us,
the assumption that vision should be regarded as
rather than being the product of causal chains
the paradigm case of sense perception. He gives
over which we have no control. He is wise
special attention to touch and vision, but also has
enough not to try to prove these things to be
fascinating things to say about smell, taste, and
true. He restricts himself to providing arguments
hearing.
against assumptions upon which they seem not to
Reid left it until he had retired from teaching to publish his magnum opus, a two-volume
be true. The burden of proof, according to Reid, always lies with the sceptic.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
the lowdown/snapshot
Reid’s first book, An Inquiry into the Human
99
Make your self scarce ROBERT J HOWELL ON AN INVITING INTRODUCTION TO THE PUZZLES OF PERSONAL IDENTITY The Ego Trick: What Does it Mean to be You? by Julian Baggini (Granta) £ùü.āā (pb)
review/ego trick
J
ulian Baggini confidently walks the
questions, this one can seem both mind-bogglingly
tightrope of popular philosophy writing,
profound and annoyingly slippery. Baggini helps
consistently
that
us find our footing by asking more concrete
producing
books
convey the excitement of philosophy
questions: “Are you the same person as you were
without dumbing it down. The Ego Trick, his
when you were four?”; “Is the Alzheimer’s patient
latest, introduces the puzzles surrounding the
next to me the same person as the witty woman
self and personal identity, as well as his own take
I married?”; “Are we the sorts of things that can
on those puzzles, with humour, style and insight,
survive death?” Furthermore, by conducting
making it an inviting entrance to this debate for
interviews and telling stories of people who
the non-academic philosopher.
face versions of these questions, Baggini keeps
Baggini aims to answer the question, “What,
issues firmly in the human realm, and well away
if anything, is the self?” Like many philosophical
from philosophical fictions involving teleportation and brain-swapping. Instead, the reader is introduced to real life relatives of Alzheimer’s
Robert J Howell is associate professor of philosophy at Southern Methodist University. He is author of The God Dialogues (with Torin Alter) and Subjective Physicalism (forthcoming), both from Oxford University Press.
100
tpm did not review any of Julian Baggini’s books under his editorship. Now that the reviews section is produced without his input, we’re pleased to bring you this review of his latest book. (Jean Kazez, reviews editor)
patients, people who have undergone gender reassignment, a former prostitute, individuals with “multiple personality disorder”, and Buddhist tulkus who claim to be reincarnations. But philosophers and cognitive scientists are not simply left behind; woven into each chapter are conversations with Richard Swinburne, Galen Strawson, Derek Parfit, Daniel Dennett, David
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
“The solidity of the self is an illusion; the self itself is not” Chalmers, Susan Blackmore, Philip Zimbardo
can’t say much more than that without returning
and many others.
to a version of the pearl view.
Baggini does not simply report, however.
Baggini’s bundle view, which has precedents
Throughout the book he works to undermine
in Hume, Parfit and others, seems profound and
the commonsense view, which he calls the “pearl
can appear inevitable once one loses hope for the
view”, that there is a persisting core within each
existence of an immaterial soul. However, this
person that makes us who we are and explains
may be partly because the thesis is left some-
why we are, while fat and forty, the same people
what sketchy. Baggini tries to satisfy sceptics by
we were when we were naive and nineteen.
asserting that all entities are bundle-like construc-
Instead, Baggini argues for a “bundle view” of the
tions (excepting perhaps the basic microphysical
self that maintains that each of us is a collection
constituents of the universe), but that leads one
of “mental, neural and physical” activity, lacking
to wonder whether there is anything particularly
clearly defined borders and ever evolving.
constructed and fragile about the self. Baggini also sometimes shifts between what
thing which has a strong sense of unity and
are actually subtly distinct topics – for example,
singleness from what is actually a messy, frag-
between numerical and qualitative identity.
mented sequence of experiences and memories,
It’s one thing to say, “I was a different person
because all mental experience emerges from a
before I quit drinking.” It’s another to say of
messy, fragmented, and hugely complicated set of
two presidents, “The George Bush who failed
processes in the brain”. So, although it is not true
to catch Saddam is a different person from the
to say there is no self, it is also false that that there
one who caught him.” Baggini notes this distinc-
is a pearl-like core to the self. Each of us is, instead,
tion halfway through the book, but it’s not always
a sort of construction, with parts that come and
clear which sort of identity he’s addressing. And
go. “The solidity of self is an illusion; the self itself
sometimes the arguments move a little too fluidly
is not.”
between nearby topics, such as the self and the
The boundaries of the self are fuzzy, and what
sense of self, personality and what it is to be a
makes us the same selves over time depends
subject of experience. Some of this, though, is
on many factors, with memory and continui-
an understandable consequence of the book’s
ties of conscious thought playing crucial roles.
impressive scope. Baggini’s aim is to make the
Nevertheless, we should not always expect to get
reader think about a cluster of related problems,
a single, final answer to the hard questions, such
to challenge some of her deepest assump-
as whether the Alzheimer’s patient next to me is
tions about the self, and to keep the topic vivid,
the same person as the woman I married. Some
grounded in real life and enjoyable. In all these
things are the same, others are different, and we
tasks, The Ego Trick is a success.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/ego trick
The “ego trick” is the construction of “some-
101
Inhabiting philosophical ideas JOHN KOETHE APPLAUDS POEMS ONLY A PHILOSOPHER COULD WRITE At Lake Scugog: Poems by Troy Jollimore (Princeton University Press) £ùù.āý/$ùþ.āý (pb)
review/Jollimore
P
hilosophy and poetry have had an
It is perhaps surprising then that so few
uneasy relationship at least since
people have been both philosophers and poets:
Aristophanes ridiculed Socrates in
Plato himself was also an astonishing stylist;
The Clouds and Plato returned the
Lucretius presented a view of the natural order
favour by banishing poets from his Republic. In
in verse; Coleridge engaged in extended (and
the popular mind both represent paradigmatically
tedious) Kantian reflections; T S Eliot completed
useless pursuits. Looked at more sympathetically,
a Harvard dissertation on F H Bradley, which he
both are often motivated by similar reflections
declined to return to the United States to defend.
and concerns: the nature of the self and its rela-
I know of only four living American philosophers
tion to the world; the relations between reality,
who have achieved a degree of recognition for
thought, perception and the imagination; the
poetry, and two of these (including myself) are
nature of time and its relation to experience and
retired. One of them is Troy Jollimore, a philos-
memory; happiness and the search for a satisfying
opher at California State University, Chico who
and meaningful life.
did his graduate work at Princeton under Harry Frankfurt and has written books on ethics and friendship, and on love. His first book of poems,
102
John Koethe’s last book of poems, Falling Water (HarperCollins), received the Lenore Marshall Prize from the Academy of American Poets. He is distinguished professor of philosophy emeritus at the University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, and last year was the Bain-Swiggett professor of poetry at Princeton University.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Tom Thompson in Purgatory, received the 2006 National Book Critics Circle award for poetry, and his second, At Lake Scugog, was published last spring by Princeton University Press. There is a sense in which “philosophical poetry” is an oxymoron, if it means poetry in which
the activity of doing philosophy is conducted.
The sentence is the unit of thought, and since
Philosophy and poetry might both begin in, say,
the thoughts involved in philosophical and other
a wonder at the relation of the mind to the world,
abstract forms of reflection involve obsessive clar-
but to respond to that wonder philosophically
ification and qualification, they demand sentences
involves staking out and clarifying a view of what
of complementary syntactic complexity, sentences
that relation is, and arguing for it and defending
capable of accommodating, for example, subjunc-
it against alternative views and objections, all
tive modes and subordinate clauses. One of the
subject to strict constraints of consistency and
distinctive aspects of Jollimore’s poetry is his
coherence. Poetry on the other hand is largely
ease with an idiom that allows him to elaborate a
free of such constraints, which is a source of the
complex line of thought:
exhilaration and the sense of freedom it allows. What poetry can do, and which Jollimore does brilliantly in a great many poems in At Lake
What land grew the plant whose powder composed
Scugog, including the poem “The Solipsist” (see
this ink? What ship carried it in what bottles?
overleaf), is imaginatively inhabit and explore
I have seen it half-flashed, subliminally sensed
philosophical ideas by dramatising and person-
against a blank field of sky
ifying them. This isn’t an idle or ornamental
through whose invisible perforations
exercise. Imaginability is commonly taken by
the starlight would soon come flooding.
philosophers as a criterion of possibility, yet As this brief excerpt from the fairly extended
imagines or conceives. The vividness with which
poem “Stain” may suggest (although the labyrin-
a poet can inhabit a philosophical position can
thine quality of his poems makes them difficult
thus reinforce the sense of its genuine possi-
to excerpt), one thing Jollimore excels at is the
bility, whether the possibility is solipsism, or the
working out of what are often called meta-
possibility of a disembodied existence central to
physical conceits, tropes of a kind associated
traditional arguments for mind–body dualism, or
with so-called metaphysical poets like Donne
the Kantian experience of the sublime that lies at
and Herbert: comparative or analogical lines of
the heart of high romanticism.
thought which gesture at abstractions that resist
Another impediment to poetry that might be
being directly conveyed. It is in this, rather than
called philosophical is the language character-
in the enterprise of propounding and arguing
istic of much contemporary poetry, which tends
for philosophical theses, that Jollimore’s poetry
either towards the fragmented and disjunctive or
is genuinely philosophical. Of course, there
towards the straightforwardly declarative. These
are many pleasures of more familiar sorts to
modes may be fine for tracing the phenome-
be found in At Lake Scugog – for example, the
nology of perception or enacting the suspension
lovely concluding poem, “His Master’s Voice” –
of thought in a swoon of sensation one critic has
but what makes the book exceptional is the way
called “the rhapsodic fallacy”, but they aren’t well
it embodies a style of language and thought only
suited to thought of any subtlety or complexity.
a philosopher could deploy so effortlessly.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/Jollimore
there is often a question about just what one
103
The Solipsist
review/Jollimore
by Troy Jollimore
Don’t be misled:
which the world is, retires.
that sea-song you hear
Someday it will expire.
when the shell’s at your ear?
Then all will go silent
It’s all in your head.
and dark. For the moment,
That primordial tide –
however, the black-
the slurp and salt-slosh
ness is just temporary.
of the brain’s briny wash –
The planet you carry
is on the inside.
will shortly swing back
Truth be told, the whole place,
from the far nether regions.
everything that the eye
And life will continue –
can take in, to the sky
but only within you.
and beyond into space,
Which raises a question
lives inside of your skull.
that comes up again and again,
When you set your sad head
as to why
down on Procrustes’ bed,
God would make ear and eye
you lay down the whole
to face outward, not in?
universe. You recline on the pillow: the cosmos grows dim. The soft ghost in the squishy machine,
104
“The Solipsist” is from At Lake Scugog (Princeton University Press, úøùù). First published in Poetry magazine.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Chester by John Koethe
Wallace Stevens is beyond fathoming, he is so strange; it is as if he had a morbid secret he would rather perish than disclose … Marianne Moore to William Carlos Williams
Another day, which is usually how they come: A cat at the foot of the bed, noncommital In its blankness of mind, with the morning light Slowly filling the room, and fragmentary Memories of last night’s video and phone calls. It is a feeling of sufficiency, one menaced By the fear of some vague lack, of a simplicity Of self, a self without a soul, the nagging fear Of being someone to whom nothing ever happens. Thus the fantasy of the narrative behind the story,
review/Jollimore
Of the half-concealed life that lies beneath The ordinary one, made up of ordinary mornings More alike in how they feel than what they say. They seem like luxuries of consciousness, Like second thoughts that complicate the time One simply wastes. And why not? Mere being Is supposed to be enough, without the intricate Evasions of a mystery or off-stage tragedy. Evenings follow on the afternoons, lingering in The living room and listening to the stereo While Peggy Lee sings “Is That All There Is?” Amid the morning papers and the usual Ghosts keeping you company, but just for a while. The true soul is the one that flickers in the eyes Of an animal, like a cat that lifts its head and yawns And stares at you, and then goes back to sleep.
“Chester” is from Ninety-Fifth Street (HarperCollins, úøøā), copyright úøøā by John Koethe
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
105
Get the vote out ALAN HAWORTH FINDS A BOOK THAT TICKS ALL THE BOXES
review/voting
The Ethics of Voting by Jason Brennan (Princeton University Press) £úø.āý/$úā.āý (hb)
W
hy should you vote? The
on the result. Maybe you should just stay home
answer is that – well – maybe
and watch TV.
you shouldn’t; at least not if
Such is the negative case argued by Jason
you are a “wrongful” voter
Brennan in this intellectually incisive, lucidly
motivated by immoral bigotry, who votes from
argued book. But Brennan also has a positive
ignorance or is quite inept at weighing arguments
case to make, namely that you are under no obli-
and evidence. There is also the consideration that
gation to vote, but that if you do, you should
your individual vote will likely have a negligible
“vote well”. In other words, you should exer-
effect on the outcome of an election. Worse, you
cise “civic virtue” by voting for what is, in your
may be a resident of North Dakota, in which case
considered judgement, most likely to promote
the probability of your causing an accident as you
the common good. (If you can’t do that, then
drive to the polling-station will be far higher than
you shouldn’t vote, and you may even be enti-
that of your vote’s having any appreciable impact
tled to sell your vote to someone else.) This is an interesting thesis, partly because it contradicts many a received view, including the view that every citizen has a duty to vote. Brennan makes
106
Alan Haworth’s most recent book is Understanding the Political Philosophers: From Ancient to Modern Times (Routledge, úøøü). He is currently preparing the second edition.
short work of the latter in his opening chapters. His thesis requires definitions of “civic virtue” and “the common good”, conceptions of which he advances an “extrapolitical” account. This is
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
another interesting feature of his argument, for
means that anyone who reads it will find his or
it runs counter to the liberal commonplace that
her own points of disagreement. Personally, I
“the common good” denotes nothing more than
was bothered by his claim that there must be
a fancy abstraction.
a “motivational component” to the exercise of
According to Brennan, then, the exercise of
civic virtue; that is, you must both act to promote
civic virtue is, quite simply, a matter of acting
the common good and intend to do just that if
in ways which tend to promote the common
you are to count as exercising civic virtue. This
good; the common good itself being that which
seems right, but I would tentatively suggest that
“promotes the interests of most people either
it sits uneasily with his claim that individuals can
without harming others’ interests or, if it does harm them, without exploiting them”. This is an eminently sensible, level-headed view, and in line with his equally level-headed conviction that “political institutions are like hammers”, to be judged “in the first instance by how functional
Maybe you should just stay home and watch TV
they are”. Accordingly, Brennan takes an attrac-
promote the public good, when pursuing purely
tively unpretentious view of liberal society as “an
private ends, which would seem to imply that one
institutional framework in which individuals can
can promote the public good unintentionally.
best serve their vision of the good by also serving others”.
I would also suggest that Brennan may have a tendency to underestimate what he calls “the symbolic value” of voting. If personal trainers writing political philosophy would have a
pursuing their own private ends. Brennan is
tendency to overestimate the value of exercise
critical of social theorists and others who enjoy
then mightn’t it be that philosophers writing
participatory activities – and who therefore
about politics have a tendency to overplay the
idealise the society of the politically engaged – on
rational and to downplay the symbolic? In 1994,
the grounds that they should be more self-critical
South Africans queued for hours to vote in the
and remember those to whom political activity
first free elections since the end of apartheid.
can be aversive. As he says, “If personal trainers
Many will tell you it was the most moving experi-
wrote political philosophy, I suspect they would
ence of their lives. Again, in 2009, Iranians were
deemphasise political deliberation and instead
prepared to risk their lives demonstrating against
stress the value of exercise.” Just so.
the outcome of a fixed election. What was it that
The real value of books such as this lies in
moved those South Africans, and what was it
their potential to raise the level of public debate.
those Iranians were prepared to die for? If it is
If only they were read by more people. Brennan’s
an implication of Brennan’s argument that they
argument is detailed and searching, which means
might as well have stayed home and found other
that it presents a challenge to anyone prepared
ways to exercise civic virtue, it’s hard to say. Were
to take it seriously. Its detailed character also
they were just being irrational? Really?
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/voting
It is within that framework, he claims, that individuals can exercise civic virtue, even when
107
All due respect MICHAEL ANTONY ON A CALL FOR REASONED DEBATE Reasonable Atheism: A Moral Case for Respectful Disbelief by Scott F Aikin and Robert B Talisse (Prometheus Books) £ùĀ.āā/$úø (pb)
review/atheism
T
his book is aimed primarily at reli-
Believers who think that atheists, no less than
gious believers who think that “atheists
theists, can be moral, trustworthy, intelligent,
must be dishonest, irrational, amoral,
and so on – and there are many such believers
untrustworthy, mean, deceitful, delu-
as well – are thus unlikely to feel that their views
sional, and unintelligent”. Although there’s little
are being directly addressed throughout much of
doubt that millions of believers do view atheists in
the book. The same will hold for most atheists
this way, it’s safe to say that this is a philosophically
and agnostics. But there’s enough in Reasonable
unsophisticated bunch. Authors Scott Aikin and
Atheism to make it a worthwhile read for all three
Robert Talisse wish to show that such believers
groups.
have “false beliefs about atheists”, and should
One of the book’s central themes is that a
view atheists “in roughly the same way they regard
proper concern for our beliefs – caring that they
those who subscribe to religious faiths different
be true – requires that we intellectually engage
from their own” – namely, as reasonable and moral
in a respectful manner with people with whom
people with false beliefs about reality. This is how
we disagree. Pursuing truth demands that we
the authors view thoughtful religious believers.
subject our views to criticism, and attempt to understand where our opponents (or we) have erred when we fail to persuade. This presupposes
108
Michael Antony is senior lecturer in philosophy at the University of Haifa
that we treat our critics as generally reasonable people (for otherwise what value would their criticisms hold?), and accord them the respect
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
that such reasonableness warrants. This impor-
believers must recognize as one option that
tant discussion is aimed at persuading the book’s
sincere, intelligent, and honest people could
primary intended readership – believers unsym-
adopt after a competent and thorough examina-
pathetic to atheists, essentially – to view atheists
tion of the evidence and arguments”. Given the
more charitably. But it’s also directed at the New
numerous arguments in their book, however,
Atheists and their followers (given their oft-
this will come across, even to those untrained in
adopted confrontational, schoolyardish stance),
philosophy, a bit like an artist who insists that her
and indeed at anyone concerned with the debates
aim isn’t to make a painting but rather to demon-
on religion.
strate her artistic talent, which she proceeds to
Aikin’s and Talisse’s book is chock full of argu-
do by making a painting. Of course the authors
ments. There are two against unsophisticated
are making a case in their book against theism
versions of the cosmological and teleological
and for atheism, even if it is not, as they say, their
arguments, which is excusable if the authors are
“full case”. After all, it is only by presenting a
right that these versions are popular with their
case for a view that one can hope to make such a
target theist audience. There’s a useful critique
view appear reasonable to someone who doesn’t
of the New Atheists’ appalling treatments of the
hold it. It may be that the authors get themselves into
attempt to construct an ontological argument
this minor muddle because they insufficiently
against theism. The authors’ discussion of evil,
appreciate how difficult it is to make sense of
while admittedly inconclusive, illustrates well
mutually recognised reasonable disagreement.
the enormous challenge this problem presents
The authors appear to believe – and with this I
for the theist. Their discussion of the Euthyphro
sympathise – that it must be possible somehow
dilemma, however, wholly ignores a standard way
for participants in a debate to view each other,
of navigating through the horns of the dilemma
not only as reasonable people, but as reasonably
by locating goodness in God’s nature rather than
holding their opposing views. In recent years,
outside of God. The book contains many other
however, epistemologists have found it exceed-
discussions, several interesting, centred on the
ingly difficult to show how this can be possible.
concepts of worship, hell, religion and politics,
I won’t suggest anything here, other than to
among others. Even if these fail to convince, they
say that the answer can’t involve participants in
will challenge the book’s intended readership,
disputes claiming that they aren’t trying to argue
and help show that atheists can be reasonable,
for their views.
intelligent, moral, respectable individuals.
review/atheism
ontological argument, and a less-than-impressive
Philosophically unsophisticated believers who
But there’s an odd tension running through
see atheists as irrational and amoral are unlikely
Reasonable Atheism. The authors repeatedly
to be disturbed by this issue, even if they have
claim that their aim is not to present a case
some vague awareness of it. Mainly, the book’s
either against religious belief or for atheism.
arguments will challenge their worldview, and
Rather, they “aspire to demonstrate that atheism
illustrate the manner of respectful debate the
is a reasonable position, a view that religious
authors are urging us to engage in.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
109
Under the truth table STEVEN HALES RAISES A GLASS TO PUB PHILOSOPHY Philosophy on Tap: Pint-Sized Puzzles for the Pub Philosopher, by Matt Lawrence (Wiley-Blackwell) £ùú.āā/$ùā.āý (pb)
review/beer
P
hilosophers are of mixed minds about
Matt Lawrence knows how to hook his
popularisers. On the one hand there
audience. Perfect for loquacious imbibers,
are periodic complaints that contem-
Philosophy on Tap consists of forty-eight short
porary philosophy, especially the
chapters, each pairing a beer with a specific phil-
analytic strain, is too hermetic; disconnected
osophical problem. There’s plenty of scaffolding
from a wider world, it is seen as an obsolete
to help the neophytes along, including thought-
parlour game for logic-chopping eggheads. On
provoking questions at the end of each chapter, a
the other hand those who do attempt to bring
tasting chart for each beer, and plenty of graphics
philosophy to a popular audience are derided as
and illustrations.
unserious TV dons. It’s a classic catch-22. What’s
The questions and conundrums are largely
more, it is the rare scholar who knows how to
drawn from Western philosophy, from the
convey complex ideas to a wider audience; the
ancient Greeks up to contemporary analysis. Yet
finest philosophical minds rarely have a knack for
other traditions get a fair showing too. Chuang
popular communication.
Tzu’s butterfly dreaming that he is a man gets a chapter, as do Buddhism’s notions of anatta (no self), the ideas of nirvana and the Enlightenment, Zen koans, and even Taoist non-being. Sartre’s
110
Steven Hales is professor of philosophy at Bloomsburg University and editor of Beer and Philosophy (Wiley-Blackwell)
bad faith and Nietzsche’s eternal recurrence also rate chapters. Lawrence does a good job of demonstrating the breadth of philosophy by
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
including posers from logic (the liar paradox),
puzzlers, there is no sense that there is any struc-
philosophy of time and even race theory. The
ture to what philosophers do, no feeling that there
book does seem a little heavy on philosophy of
are specific areas of study. Nor is there a hint that
religion, but questions about God, souls, intel-
a solution to one puzzle might bear on another
ligent design, divine command theory and so
topic. If we have no free will (chapter 12) that
on occur to people with no philosophical back-
definitely puts a damper on the free will solution
ground and are a good way to draw them in.
to the problem of evil (chapter 28). Yet Lawrence
Even better, Lawrence does know his beer.
doesn’t draw out this connection. Philosophy is
As an American author his beer choices are
not just a random collection of brain teasers, but
weighted heavily towards American microbrews; not necessarily a bad thing, as America brews the greatest variety of beer and is the most open to experimentation. But he also includes fine beers from the UK, Belgium, India, Mexico, Canada, Germany, Ireland, Japan, Australia, Greece and even Tibet. This reviewer was sold on his beer acumen when he mentioned the legendary, and
If a pint spills in a forest and there’s no one there to hear it, does it make a sound?
near-mythical, Westvleteren 12. Some of the discussions work better than others and lend themselves to the beer and pub
is a systematic field of inquiry. It would be nice to get even a rudimentary sense of that. There are also occasional odd turns. One
pickings, but Lawrence also gives an amusing
chapter addresses the question of if a pint spills in
lesson on how to get out of buying a round with
a forest and there is no one there to hear it, does it
logical dilemmas. Tell your mates that you’ll buy
make a sound? A perfectly fine question to raise,
another round of beer, if and only if they can
but Lawrence uses it to jump into a discussion
guess correctly whether you’ll do so or not. If they
of Berkeley’s idealism, which is a curious choice.
guess that yes, you’ll buy, then inform them that
The reality of unheard sound should lead into a
they guessed incorrectly. You weren’t planning to
discussion of secondary qualities, which can be
buy a round. Since they got it wrong, you’re off
better motivated than by Berkeley’s unintuitive
the hook. If they guess that you won’t buy, then
view. For example, does ultraviolet light have a
tell them that you were in fact planning to buy
colour? If the answer is no, because no one sees
a round, but since they guessed incorrectly, you
ultraviolet light, then surely the spilled pint in the
can’t do so after all. This sort of thing explains
forest is soundless by the same reasoning.
why philosophers get out of paying for drinks
Overall Philosophy on Tap is a pint of Sharp’s
(remember Socrates ever picking up the tab at a
Doom Bar bitter for a Carling lager drinker. It is
symposium?), but also why we aren’t very popular.
a worthy and engaging first step for a newcomer
There are some ways in which the book
not yet ready for Three Floyds Oak Aged Dark
could be improved. Since the topics are random
Lord Russian Imperial Stout.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/beer
theme more readily. Aesthetics questions are easy
111
Metaphysics at the multiplex AMY KIND ON A FILM WITH A PHILOSOPHER AT THE HELM Source Code is directed by Duncan Jones, written by Ben Ripley, and stars Jake Gyllenhaal, Michelle Monaghan and Vera Farmiga
review/source code
H
ollywood has offered up many phil-
Jones’s first film, Moon, picked up on themes
osophical movies in recent years,
relating to selfhood and the nature of mind that
and the release of Source Code this
he first explored in an undergraduate paper enti-
past spring brings even more meta-
tled “How to Kill Your Computer Friend: An
physics to the multiplex – this time, with a bona
Investigation of the Mind/Body Problem and
fide philosopher at the helm. Having graduated
How It Relates to the Hypothetical Creation of a
from the College of Wooster with a bachelor’s
Thinking Machine”. In many ways, Source Code
degree in philosophy, director Duncan Jones
picks up right where Moon leaves off – playing
spent two and a half years in a doctoral program
on the idea that your true identity may be quite
at Vanderbilt University before deciding that
different from what you realise, a theme that has
movie-making was his true calling. In abandoning
long captivated Jones.
the academic pursuit of philosophy, however,
As the film opens, Army Captain Colter Stevens
Jones by no means abandoned the subject alto-
(Jake Gyllenhaal) is jolted awake to find himself on
gether. He now teaches philosophy to the masses
a Chicago-bound train. He has no idea how he got
through his movies.
there; his last memories are of a helicopter mission in Afghanistan. Surrounded by people he doesn’t know, he soon realises that he’s also in a body he
112
Amy Kind is associate professor of philosophy at Claremont McKenna College
doesn’t recognise, that of teacher Sean Fentress. As the train approaches Chicago exactly eight minutes later, it explodes and kills everyone aboard
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
– everyone, that is, except Stevens, who regains
make a film that resolved all of the philosophical
consciousness to find himself in what appears to
paradoxes that it raised; as the Times’s reporter
be some kind of military escape pod.
described it, Jones “obsessed over crafting the
We soon learn that Stevens’s presence on the
end of Source Code to make sure that every loose
train was a virtual one, facilitated by a mysterious
end came together in a way that even a philosophy
new military technology known as “source code”.
professor couldn’t question”. Although Jones fares
According to its creator Dr Rutledge (Jeffrey
better at this task than most directors – and his
Wright), source code allows a person to trans-
concern to treat philosophical problems seriously
port into the consciousness of someone who has
is evident throughout the movie – I’d hesitate to
recently died and replay the last eight minutes of
pronounce Source Code an unqualified success on
their life. By utilising this technology, Rutledge
this score. To mention just a few questions that
hopes that Stevens will be able to uncover the
remained in this philosophy professor’s mind at
identity of the train bomber and thereby prevent
the movie’s end: why eight minutes? If Stevens is
a second, more deadly attack that is yet to come.
connected to the events on the train via Fentress’s
The captain is thus sent back to the train, again
consciousness, how could source code give him
and again, each time for the same eight minute
access to aspects of the past that Fentress himself
period, and each time gathering more and more
never experienced? And – although this question
clues to the bomber’s identity. (If I had to summa-
is hard to state clearly without spoiling too much
rise the movie in five words or less, I’d describe it
of the movie – how are we supposed to understand
as Avatar meets Groundhog Day.)
Stevens’s ability to “travel” between the different
Rutledge is insistent that source code cannot
universes in the multiverse? Still, I’m not sure we should worry too much
mission is to gather information that will change
about Jones’s inability to meet his own goal, for
the future, not the past. Source code, according
the goal itself strikes me as unrealistic. Won’t
to Rutledge, does not allow for time travel but
there always be something for a philosophy
rather for time reassignment. But as each eight-
professor to question? Even the most influen-
minute foray into Fentress’s consciousness plays
tial philosophical texts in the canon have loose
out slightly differently, Stevens starts to suspect
ends that philosophers continue to pick at, so it’s
that source code doesn’t work exactly as its crea-
hard to imagine that a Hollywood film is going
tors envisioned. From here, the movie takes
to succeed where philosophers such as Plato,
considerable twists and turns, and I’ll refrain from
Descartes and Kant have failed. And loose ends
detailing them in the hopes of avoiding unneces-
aside, Source Code is an impressive film – it’s fun,
sary spoilers. With each twist and turn, however,
it’s engrossing, it’s well-acted, and it’s intelligent
the audience is confronted with a new philosoph-
without being inaccessible. It certainly deserves
ical conundrum, and the issues raised range from
to be grouped among the top philosophical films
personal identity to free will to multiverse theory.
of recent years, and I’d recommend it to anyone
In an interview with the Los Angeles Times
who wants to be served up a dish of philosophy
last spring, Jones expressed his determination to
along with their popcorn.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/source code
prevent the train from exploding. Stevens’s
113
Q&A
CAROLYN KORSMEYER’S GUT REACTION What is aesthetic disgust?
Usually when we find something disgusting, our
What do you mean when you say that disgusting objects “can sometimes exert a grisly allure”?
review/q&a
response is recoil and rejection – almost entirely negative. But when works of art adroitly exploit
Disgust alerts us to things that are noxious, infec-
the arousal of disgust, the response becomes
tious, putrefying – things that we want to avoid.
appreciative. The term “aesthetic disgust” is
At the same time, sometimes there is a paradox-
shorthand for the appreciative response to
ical tendency to seek out the objects that revolt,
aspects of art that arouse disgust. In these circum-
perhaps to discover more about them, even to
stances disgust is not so much rejection as visceral
dwell momentarily on the feeling. The second
recognition of something significant. Disgust is a
look that one might be tempted to take at a
strongly physical emotion, so its aesthetic mode
squirming nest of worms would be an example. I
is especially powerful – literally a gut response.
endorse the perspective of the phenomenologist Aurel Kolnai, who recognised an approach-
What truth is apprehended in the experience of aesthetic disgust?
There is no single truth, but insofar as it registers decay and corruption, disgust is a compelling means by which we recognise material vulnerability and mortality.
avoidance element in disgust. It must be stressed, however, that the avoidance factor is considerably stronger! What do you say to the thought that disgust is relative to culture, and therefore there’s not much that’s philosophically interesting about it?
Cross-cultural studies indicate that disgust
114
Savoring Disgust: The Foul and the Fair in Aesthetics by Carolyn Korsmeyer is published by Oxford University Press at £ùĀ.āā, $úā.āý (pb)
is recognised in most – maybe all – cultures, although the particular objects that fall into disgusting categories vary. Most emotions are
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
taken seriously for the insights they afford.
to rage. “Disgust” is usually employed – at least
Fear informs us of danger, sorrow of loss and so
in English – only to refer to extreme revulsion.
forth. Disgust, however, is an emotion that lots
But there are many more nuanced varieties of
of people want to disclaim as only the result of
the emotion as well. A lot of what I defend as
contingent education and culture.
aesthetic disgust comes in relatively subtle forms.
To my mind, this tendency is misguided.
An example of what I mean is presented by
Disgust is uniquely sensitive to certain impor-
Emily Dickinson’s poem that begins “I heard a
tant truths about life and death, and without it
fly buzz when I died …”. The combination of the
we would lose a dimension of understanding.
carrion fly and the fate of a corpse resonates with
As for philosophical importance: emotions in
disgust, and yet the poem is elegant. One might
general are salient modes of knowing and valuing.
object that the poem is not disgusting at all, but
They have a place therefore in epistemology,
I think that part of its power derives from the
ethics, and aesthetics, not to mention philosophy
fact that a potentially revolting scene is rendered
of mind. Disgust figures in all of these areas.
with such delicacy. The visceral response may be slight, but it delivers indispensable insight.
How might one take pleasure in disgusting art?
I continue to refer to such milder forms of the
The concept of pleasure at work in aesthetic
affect as “disgust” in order to foreground the
contexts is very complex. Think of art that is
intensity that they contribute to the experience
uncomfortable and demanding, such as a tragedy
of art.
or a war narrative. Such works often present illness, grievous injury or cruelty in graphic
Is disgust incompatible with beauty?
Most traditional aesthetic theories have held
extremely important for the effect of the work.
that disgust completely interrupts the experi-
The emotions aroused by such works – and there
ence of beauty. Certainly if a disgusting piece
are many in such subtle forms that it is hard to
of art is also beautiful, it would be a difficult
name them precisely – can be painful to experi-
sort of beauty. In the book, I try to extend the
ence. And yet without them, we would not grasp
understanding of disgust to include certain
the insight that the work offers. Is this pleasure?
works that we would also consider beautiful.
It is certainly a positive and valuable experience.
The Dickinson poem I just mentioned might be
Disgust plays a role within the panoply of such
a candidate for a work that combines a disgust
emotions, usually in concert with other affects,
quotient with beauty. Other examples might
with which it often blends.
come from the many Renaissance and Baroque
review/q&a
ways that are disgusting and horrid but are also
paintings of Judith beheading Holofernes, Most people think disgust is an extreme emotion – why do you think it’s more subtle than that?
such as those by Artemisia Gentileschi or
Emotion types possess variations in strength;
But their paintings are good candidates for a
anger, for instance, varies from mild irritation
difficult kind of beauty as well.
Caravaggio. A murder is a terrible sight, and these artists spare none of the gore and horror.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
115
Jean Kazez
imagine that
Balloon World
review/imagine that
A
t the Nasher Sculpture Center in
all. Each explorer was alone to make something
downtown Dallas, the British artist
of the situation, and make their own plans. My
Martin Creed had an entertaining
immediate instinct was to go all the way to the
installation over the summer – a
edge of this alien universe. After much accidental
large room filled with 9,000 gold balloons (Work
walking in circles, I made it to the outer limits,
No. 1190: Half the Air in a Given Space, 2011).
and the terrible truth was revealed: a white wall.
Lovely to behold through one glass wall, the real
The installation couldn’t have been more simple,
treat was being inside balloon world. A guard
but the resulting brain whirr was immediate and
opened the door and we quickly squeezed our
delightful.
way in, as balloons started to float out. I was
Another part of the show was equally
instantaneously an explorer in another universe,
elemental. Creed had covered the elegant steps
pushing my way through light mega-molecules
down to a lower-level gallery in musical carpeting.
that surrounded me. Within seconds I had lost
A trip down the steps played a descending major
my two kids, but could still make verbal contact
scale. So? The so is that the sounds seem to
above the din of collisions. Who knew balloons
tell us about ourselves and others. My descent
could be so noisy … and so clingy? Moving a few
sounded plodding, I have to admit. We care-
feet took much flailing and battling, despite each
fully arranged ourselves on the steps so that
obstacle being light as a feather.
we’d create harmony as we walked back upstairs.
The balloon universe was isolating, but also
Would other visitors cooperate and wait until we
connecting. A push by one person (how many
got to the top? Our harmony was quickly messed
were in the room?) was a gentle shove against
up, giving us instant aural evidence about human nature. A month later, I ran into the ultimate in minimalism at the Museum of Modern Art in New
116
Jean Kazez is the author of The Weight of Things: Philosophy and the Good life, and Animalkind: What We Owe to Animals. She teaches philosophy at Southern Methodist University.
York, or rather, I didn’t run into it, because a guard stood by, protecting a thick splat of white paint, about 10 inches in diameter, fused onto the gallery floor. This was a 1968 artwork with
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
the unpoetic title Gloss white lacquer, sprayed for 2 minutes at 40lb pressure directly, by American artist Lawrence Weiner. The best part of viewing the work was talking to the guard (not part of the installation). “You could be guarding the Mona Lisa, but you’re guarding a splat”, I observed. He said he didn’t mind, and actually enjoyed the conversations he had all day. The splat is renewed every six months, he told us. What the museum owns is the concept, the detailed instructions. I promise I never said “My kid could
be paid for their minimal productions, and others not. Why is the splat worth guarding, but not a little pile of Cheerios I could pour on the gallery floor? Surely we’re supposed to ask that question, it’s part of the artist’s intention. What – as
Photographer: Kevin Todora
make this splat!” but I did find myself pondering what entitles some people to
Martin Creed, Work No. 1190: Half the Air in a Given Space, 2011 (detail), Nasher Sculpture Center, Dallas
The night before, I wondered about this in
A Nasher Center publication helps the visitor
a room just off the observation deck at the top
find meaning in minimalism by saying Creed’s
of the Rockefeller Center, where I was lingering
work is about “dichotomous physical states: pres-
because of my not minimal fear of heights. The
ence versus absence, being versus nothingness,
ceiling and walls were covered with arrays of
and doing versus not doing”. I prefer what the
coloured lights that were responsive, in strange
artist says in text art at his website (martincreed.
and indirect ways, to the motion of people in the
com): “I don’t know what I want to say, but, to try
room. Motion also triggered bell-like sounds,
to say something, I think I want to try to think. I
giving the visitor an interestingly heightened self-
want to try to see what I think. I think trying is a
awareness. The thing is, though, this was billed as
big part of it, I think thinking is a big part of it,
fun for the kids, not as Art, so there wasn’t quite
and I think wanting is a big part of it, but saying
the same cascade of meanings, which comes
it is difficult, and I find saying trying and nearly
about as the visitor tries to make sense of this
always wanting. I want what I want to say to go
thing (whatever it is) being located in a deluxe
without saying” (Work No. 267: I Don’t Know
and prestigious art museum.
What I Want to Say).
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/imagine that
they say – is art?
117
An explorer who has yet to leave the coast RODGER JACKSON ON WHAT THE CRITICS SAID
threshold where he does already limits our obliJustice for Hedgehogs by Ronald Dworkin (Harvard University Press) £úü.āý/$ûý (hb)
gations to others; it strikes me as not limiting them very much.” Unfortunately, there isn’t an adequate theory
O
ver thirty leading scholars couldn’t
for how to set those limits – “we can only know
wait for Dworkin’s Justice for
when we are displaying contempt for their lives if
Hedgehogs to hit the bookshops,
we first know what we owe them. Dworkin’s view
so they put together a symposium
presupposes an account of what we owe, it does
review/round-up
on it and published the proceedings as a special
not generate one.”
issue of the Boston University Law Review.
Russ Shaefer-Landau has a similar on-the-
While they all respect the depth and breadth of
one-hand approach, although with regard to
his project, most also have a bone to pick with
Dworkin’s treatment of scepticism. “Dworkin’s
him.
discussions of error skepticism are lively and
Kwame Anthony Appiah “admires and
wide-reaching. But I think that they can be
accepts” Dworkin’s general strategy for balancing
improved in certain ways, and since I am on his
the duties we have to ourselves and to each
side in this respect, I would really like to see these
other. However, he writes, “you cannot live a
improvements incorporated to make the case
life of dignity – a life in which the central ethical
against error skepticism yet more compelling.”
facts about you are properly acknowledged – if
Others, like A C Grayling, agree with his
you are scrambling for subsistence from day to
defence of moral objectivism. In the New York
day, uncertain where the next meal will come
Review of Books, he writes, “His argument is
from for you and your family. I know this. So do
novel, but I find it convincing. If he is right, we
you. Dworkin appears to think that setting the
cannot sensibly ask for a neutral, morally uncommitted account of what makes one moral or political judgment right and others wrong.”
118
Rodger Jackson is associate professor of philosophy at Richard Stockton College
Although Simon Blackburn, writing in the Guardian, professes to admire Dworkin’s writing, he’s alarmed at his over-reliance on the law. “It
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
cc
Calle Eklund/V-wolk
Further, he appears not fully to appreciate that the interior of this vast continent he is mapping may be at war.” Anthony Gottlieb, in the New York Times, might seem likely that even such moral and political ideas as are visible in the better parts of that law are absent in the worst parts … Although it has been the crux of his attack on ‘positivism’, in this work Dworkin simply sidesteps the issue, urging that the problem of bad law is ‘of almost no practical importance’, and that whether we say that bad laws are no laws at all is ‘sadly close to a verbal dispute’. Sadly too, I suppose, when Sophocles wrote Antigone he mistook this for a real problem.”
praises his ability to translate the results of his research into “lively treatments of three areas in which Ramachandran has himself done pioneering work: visual perception, pain in amputated ‘phantom’ limbs, and synesthesia”. In spite of these gifts, or perhaps even because of them, Gottlieb says the research is never clearly developed into a coherent thesis. Part of the problem is that since he is “an exceptionally inventive researcher who tosses off suggestions at a dizzying pace, readers may sometimes lose track of what is firmly established, what is tentative and what is way out there. His fondness for
The Tell-Tale Brain: A Neuroscientist’s Quest for What Makes Us Human by V S Ramachandran (Norton) £úø/$úþ.āý (hb)
evolutionary explanations can be particularly freewheeling.” Colin McGinn raises a similar concern in the New York Review of Books. “There are
I
times when the impression of theoretical over-
and largely unmapped mental continent about
qualify his more extreme statements by assuring
which, he admits, ‘we still have precious little
us that he is only proposing part of the full story,
understanding’. With its 100 billion nerve cells
but there are moments when his neural enthu-
and infinite array of pathways, the human brain is
siasm gets the better of him.”
casts the author of The Tell-Tale Brain “as
reaching is unmistakable, and the relentless
a cross between Sherlock Holmes and Dr
neural reductionism becomes earsplitting. This is
Livingstone”. Ramachandran is “a behav-
progressively the case as the book becomes more
ioural pioneer exploring the mysteries of a huge
ambitious in scope. Ramachandran will often
capable of making more connections than there
Still, McGinn sees the book as having signif-
are particles in the universe. How can we chart
icant merits. “His writing is generally lucid,
it?”
charming, and informative, with much humor
But it’s not a particularly successful expedi-
to lighten the load of Latinate brain disquisi-
tion. “Ramachandran wanders along intriguing
tions. He is a leader in his field and is certainly
neural pathways, pausing to investigate strange
an ingenious and tireless researcher. This is the
disorders, but he leaves the impression that he
best book of its kind that I have come across for
is an explorer who has yet to leave the coast.
scientific rigor, general interest, and clarity.”
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
review/round-up
n the Telegraph, Nicholas Shakespeare
119
MY PHILOSOPHY “We shouldn’t be scared of philosophy. Ideas are always in charge, we might as well get self-conscious about what they are.”
Taking the BS out of The Big Society JESSE NORMAN MP TALKS POLITICS WITH JULIAN BAGGINI
I
last words/my philosophy
“
don’t think the electorate is stupid at
Over tea at Portcullis House, Parliament’s
all. I think the electorate is very smart.”
smart contemporary annex, Norman told me
When a politician says something like
about his first brushes with philosophy, which
this, you know that they’ve either
were typical for people of his generation:
completely rejected Machiavelli or embraced him
watching Brain Magee’s television series, Men
very closely indeed. In our sceptical age, it would
of Ideas, and reading Bertrand Russell’s The
seem naive to believe the former, but having met
Problems of Philosophy and his pot-boilers of
the member of parliament for Hereford and
the 1950s and 1960s, such as Why I am not a
former philosophy lecturer Jesse Norman, and
Christian. His interest was piqued but he didn’t
read his work, I’m inclined to give him the benefit
fall in love with the subject until, when staying
of the doubt. After all, anyone who gave up a
with a friend in Greece, he discovered a summary
high-flying career at the age of 35 to do a PhD on
of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. “I fell on it like
Euclid’s geometry can hardly be accused of being
a thirsty man in the desert on a glass of water”,
a cynical career climber.
he says. “That lit a fire which then took me about twenty years to discharge.” That discharge turned out to be slow and
120
Julian Baggini is editor-in-chief of tpm and author of The Ego Trick: What Does it Mean to be You? (Granta, úøùù)
intermittent. He went to Merton College, Oxford to read classics, which had a strong philosophy component. Still, it was not yet his prime focus,
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
and after graduating he went to live in America
What is unusual about these interests is the
for six years, first setting up a company dealing
pairing of the very formal, rigid mathematical
with shareholder rights and corporate govern-
thinking of logic and geometry with a conserva-
ance, then working on Wall Street, and finally
tive approach to politics, which completely rejects
running a charity setting up free institutions and
any attempt to order society by appeal to first
giving away medical textbooks in Eastern Europe,
principles, rooting itself instead in the often hazy
before and after the fall of communism.
wisdom of experience and practice. This is no
Having worked his way up the east coast and
paradox, however, if you take on board the central
realising “another job would have landed me in
idea of praxeology, that “there is a particular kind
St John, Newfoundland or Nova Scotia or some-
of practical reasoning which is related to how
where” he returned to Britain in 1991 to work
you take action, and that’s categorially distinct
for Barclays BZW, “because I thought at that
from reflection about subjects that aren’t action-
point, what eastern Europe really needed was not
guiding. But, as it were, you can have a view of the
philanthropy but commercial advice and money”.
whole landscape while being sensitive to which
The CV fits Norman’s advocacy in his later
part of the landscape you’re in. And so thinking
political life of “Compassionate Conservatism”,
about formal reasoning in different ways is indi-
the title of his 2006 Policy Exchange pamphlet.
rectly a way of getting to understand a part of a
Most of his projects were in the private or volun-
landscape which might then help you to under-
tary sector but with a clear social benefit purpose.
stand a rather radically different part.” This reminds me of Aristotle’s famous remark
actually want to go and do piece of philosophical
about how the mark of the trained mind is to
work”. So he went to University College London
expect of any given subject matter only that degree
to do an MPhil, followed by a PhD entitled “Visual
of precision which it allows, no more and no less.
Reasoning in Euclid’s Geometry: An Epistemology
“Yes I love that as well, I totally agree. It’s
of Diagrams”, which he completed in 2004. By
rather connected to that lovely idea which you
that time he had been teaching and lecturing for a
find in Keats of negative capability. You know,
few years and even had a PhD student of his own.
the ability not to rush to judgement, to hold a
Norman’s switch from the very practical to the
topic in front of you until its lines becomes clear
abstractly theoretical looks like a dramatic mid-
and until it becomes intellectually or practically
life U-turn. In fact Norman had for a long time
tractable. Of course, at the moment there is an
maintained his theoretical and practical interests
enormous array of incentives which range from
in parallel. In 1998, for instance, he organised a
the economic to the psychological to cut too early
conference at the Polish Academy of Sciences, on
and you constantly see this mistake being made.
the Polish idea of praxeology, addressed by the
It’s a very rare person who has the intellectual self
“legendary” leader in the field, Kotarbinski. And
discipline and the practical authority to be able to
when Michael Oakeshott died in 1990, Norman
maintain that distance.”
edited a book of obituaries, The Achievement of Michael Oakeshott.
But how on earth is it possible to maintain that distance in the hurly-burly of front-line politics, >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
last words/my philosophy
However, in 1997, he said to himself, “sod that, I
121
with the necessity of making decisions now and
good at spotting phoneys. And actually TV is often
the pressures to get things done, and seen to be
a good way of helping them to spot phoneys and
done?
our collective ability to detect insincerity has gone
“It’s almost worse than that because to make
last words/my philosophy
a really big mistake you need a kind of theory,
122
up over the last few years as we’ve become slightly more socially wise.”
but you don’t need a big theory to make a lot of
Talk of social wisdom and collective abilities
stupid, small mistakes. All you need is a kind of
reflects his conservative trust that the institutions
rationalising ideology or assumption, and the
and practices we inherit contain a value that we
rationalising assumption is that you have to feed
may not be able to defend from first principles
a media machine that is a 24-hour beast.” So how
or even properly explain rationally. However, as
do you resist getting sucked in? “I’m not senior
Norman himself explains in his book, there is a
enough in politics to have had those pressures.
difference between a true wisdom of crowds and
I’m a first-term backbencher. I’m the lowest form
a pernicious group-think, whereby false ideas are
of life in the political pond, but I do think it isn’t
reinforced by the mere fact that they become the
perhaps quite as difficult as people think it is. One
accepted norm. That’s how slavery and the disen-
of the simple rules is: don’t be a phony, stick to
franchisement of women could persist for so long
what you know and don’t get pulled into having to
when to contemporary eyes they are so obviously
say something prematurely.”
unjust. So how does a conservative distinguish
The comments about the press were particu-
between those parts of the inherited tradition
larly apt given that we were talking just as three
which are ripe for reform and those which express
of the most powerful people in the newspaper
a deep wisdom, when the whole point is that this
industry – News Corporation’s James and Rupert
wisdom may not be evident to us?
Murdoch and Rebekah Brooks – were being
“It’s certainly true that there’s no sure-fire way
questioned in the very same building about their
of distinguishing between idiotic received opinion
papers’ role in phone hacking and other illegal
and a widely shared common view that comes
practices. Norman says he doesn’t know if this
from the wisdom of crowds”, he concedes, before
marks the moment when senior politicians finally
providing his answer in the form of an anecdote.
realise they do not need to pander to the press as
“When Isaac Newton was asked how he came to
much as many have done in the recent past. What
write Principia Mathematica, he paused and said
he does think is that this error has been fed by a
‘by thinking very hard’.”
“pathology”, namely “the idea that the electorate
As an example of this, he cites moves to
is stupid, that voters are like cattle and that they’re
replace the unelected second chamber of the
really only shaped by the impressions they receive
British parliament, the House of Lords, with an
from the news media, and in particular the press,
elected one. This is an idea which he believes “has
because the press is less neutral than the broad-
enormous plausibility for many people, because
casting media. I just don’t think that’s true at all.
they think of all legitimacy as being through
I think people have fantastically well-developed
the ballot box”. But “it really takes a great deal
bullshit detectors built into them and they’re very
of thought to see, while reform is undoubtedly
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
think there is a recipe for determining truth from
to have reflected on different kinds of legitimacy
falsehood here. I think it requires a reflection and
and how the British constitution preserves those
it requires being imbued in our culture and in our
– what you might call the fixed versus the moving
institutions. But then I’m a conservative. I don’t
parts of the British constitution. You have to have
think there’s a universal mechanism for anything.”
reflected on the evolution of the Lords as an insti-
To understand where this kind of conservatism
tution; you have to have thought about what the
comes from philosophically, you have to consider
conventions are that govern the more powerful
two fundamentally different ways of thinking
lower house from the less powerful upper house
about politics and ethics that go right back to
and how those would be changed if you had a
ancient Greece.
directly enfranchised upper house. This is not
“If you look at Plato you have in the Republic
an easy thing, and you can see how people who
a class of rulers distinguished by their knowl-
just thought everything ought to be elected if you
edge of abstract universals whose knowledge is
want to have legitimacy might buy that. So I don’t
attained through a parable of revelation. That >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
last words/my philosophy
needed, that is a profoundly bad idea. You have
123
last words/my philosophy 124
very much fits with what then becomes thought
draws a distinction between what you might call
of as what Pascal would call l’esprit géométrique,
natural or metaphysical rights and rights as they
the geometrical idea that somehow political ideas
are actually expressed in common law and in prac-
are a priori workings out of a certain rational
tice. Those things might look the same to people
ideal through human action. Then you have the
who haven’t really thought about it, and they
Aristotelian idea, which is much less abstract,
might have the same names, but they turn out
descriptively anchored and therefore very open
to be radically different. So what knits together
to criticism from the Platonic side as being poten-
Burke’s position on the American Revolution
tially merely adventitious. But actually if you look
and the French Revolution is that Burke was
at the issue of how to govern, it turns out that the
hostile to the assertion of abstract rights in defi-
Aristotelian approach is a far better one.”
ance of established order though liberté, égalité
He gives several examples of the kind of
and fraternité in the French case, and he was
thinking from first principles that has disas-
also hostile to the British government’s asser-
trous political conclusions, one of which is “this
tion of the abstract right to govern the colonies
Hobbesian social-contract notion, which is a way
in America in defiance of the actual ability to
of taking a very thin set of assumptions about
enforce it, or to recognise the facts on the ground,
human motivation – people really just care about
or to acknowledge the claims of the colonists to
the fear of violent death – and extracting from
degrees of self-determination in areas of taxation
that a gigantic rabbit from a hat, which is a theory
etc. So there is a deep coherence in Burke’s view,
of legitimate government”. Then there is neoclas-
and people who think that, as many people did,
sical economic theory, which “suggests that
that somehow he was in favour of the American
people are as oriented towards gain as they are
Revolution, therefore he must be in favour of
averse to loss. It turns out that’s not true. They’re
the French Revolution, completely misunder-
roughly twice as averse to loss as they are in favour
stand the character of his thought. It is to Burke’s
of gain. Once you understand that, you can under-
enormous credit that because his conceptual
stand why it would have been a good idea to have
repertoire was so well developed, he had thought
more regulation of these low-load mortgages
so deeply, he was instantly able to see this and
which give you 2% mortgage and then 10% for
prophesy accurately the disaster of the terror as
the back 15 or 20 years. So these things have prac-
arising out of the destruction of the established
tical consequences. So I would argue myself that
order.”
provided that it doesn’t become merely a series of
This set Burke against “all those bien
just-so stories about how you were right all along,
pensant intellectual right-thinking types such as
which is always the danger of a muddling through
Wordsworth, Coleridge and Mary Wollstonecraft,
approach, I think Aristotelian approaches offers
who’d absolutely embraced the French
you a much richer repertoire for government.”
Revolution. To his credit, Wordsworth comes
A rather nice example of how the two
back afterwards and acknowledges that Burke was
approaches can have subtle but important differ-
right. Of course Burke was dead by that point, but
ences comes from Burke’s views on rights. “Burke
he was bloody well right.”
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Although this kind of conservatism is similar to the one advocated by another philosopher, Roger
conservatism as such, is specifically the father of that line of thought.”
Scruton, it is not really a philosophy or ideology
Within this strand, several things generally
at all, but a “disposition”, to use Oakeshott’s term,
assumed to be of the left can be seen as being
“to conserve what is good. And because what we
equally at home with conservatism, perhaps most
have at the moment is an inheritance, it sets up a
surprisingly, cooperatives. “The line of thought
relationship of trust between those who currently
that might make you think they were intrinsi-
enjoy the inheritance, those who gave it to them
cally of the left is essentially Marxism. If you
and those who will receive it from them.”
see everything as the expression of a primeval
However, this doesn’t seem to have been the
struggle between capital and labour, then it looks
conservatism of the British Conservative party in
like co-ops and mutuals are expressions of a kind
its recent history, particularly during the Thatcher
of labour solidarity because they tend to be very
years.
heavy on working capital, i.e. people’s nous and
“It certainly has been my criticism of
energy, and very light on finance capital and
Conservative parties in the past at times that they
industrial capital. But that line of thought isn’t
have been inadequately conservative”, he says.
really very plausible. What’s more plausible is to
But this Burkean brand of conservatism is only
see co-ops and mutuals as very local expressions
one of three “at least three relatively clearly defin-
of a desire for people to control their own destiny,
able strands within conservatism”. One other is
to be able to build something, a little platoon in
“what you might call a libertarian strand which
their right. Even to say this creates a very clear
came out with Mrs Thatcher”, while the third is
linkage to Burke, because it’s in living the little
“a more paternalistic strand which came out with
platoon that we express our identity as Britons.” Suggestions like this reflect a broader truth
tive writings of politicians in the 1940s and 1950s,
that we live in an interesting time for political
some of them you can imagine being dictated by
ideas, because it’s no longer clear what views one
the Central Presidium of the Communist Party
should associate with left and right.
of the Soviet Union. They’re all about how poli-
“That’s right and that’s what’s rather good.
ticians are on the bridge of the ship of state and
We’ve moved away from a rather boring period
their job is to pull the levers to make the economy
of cluster thinking in which you could allegedly
go forward. Meanwhile the working man strives in
know what someone thought overall by knowing
the factory to make …” The sentence is left to tail
one view about them.”
off disdainfully. “This is nonsense, a completely
Norman seems to be genuinely trying to
false conception of how people actually are.”
address this new complexity with the length
Nevertheless, Norman is optimistic that what is
and subtlety of thought required. Hence he says
often called the “one nation” strand, which “does
of The Big Society, “Hopefully it’s a one line of
think very deeply about social cohesion, is the
thought book, but not a one idea book. One of the
one that I think is uppermost at the moment. I
problems we have in this country is that we have
take it that Burke, as well as being the father of
too many ideas and not enough viewpoints, and so >>>
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
last words/my philosophy
Macmillan. If you had looked at many conserva-
125
about that. My view is, I’m a philosopher: these things are what they are. As my children insist on saying to me, in the words of Bishop Butler, everything is what it is and not another thing.” Whatever you think of his politics, Norman’s willingness to very overtly discuss numerous philosophical ideas in his book is refreshing for a serving MP, and stands in contrast to the approach of another former lecturer, Oliver Letwin, who once told me that being seen as a philosopher was a “massive” disadvantage in politics and “I do my best to conceal it.” Norman is careful not to criticise his colleague’s desire to keep his philosophical hat off in public, saying, “I think everyone has their own style and of course the British public is famously nervous about what it sees as abstract ideas or academic talk.” Perhaps this is down to a political idea tends to be something that is here
loyalty: Norman helped Letwin campaign in the
and gone in just a few hours sometimes, and I’m
2005 election, although they didn’t discuss philos-
not that interested in those. But I do think elabo-
ophy because “You never talk about anything in a
rating a viewpoint is rather important.”
political campaign, because there is just no time
last words/my philosophy
The book certainly does real philosophical
126
at all.”
work: drawing out assumptions about ideas and
However, he does maintain that “we shouldn’t
how people think, trying to question them, and
be scared of philosophy. Ideas are always in charge,
then suggest a better set to work on. But it is
we might as well get self-conscious about what they
striking that although it illustrates his point that
are. Part of the problem in politics is that there
you need a great deal of thought to work any idea
isn’t quite enough understanding of where people
through, it remains true that in the absence of a
are coming from intellectually or what animates
simple definition of what the big society means,
them, and that’s one of the reasons why politicians
the public and press end up saying it’s a vacuous
have a poor reputation, because sometimes – not
idea.
always – there is rather an interesting core of ideas
“That’s right, they do”, he agrees, but insists,
expressing itself. One needs to be sensitive to what
“I don’t think it’s the worst thing in the world for
those are, and if people understood them better
an idea to be slow in getting to its elevator pitch.
they would be more sympathetic.”
The problem with the world is not that there are
Norman’s book has certainly made it easier for
too many deep ideas lacking a snappy summary,
people to understand Conservatism and the big
it is that there are too many shallow ideas with
society better. Whether that makes them more
a snappy summary. I’m not particularly worried
sympathetic remains to be seen.
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
Wendy M Grossman
the skeptic Messy science
W
hen I was a child, I read many
Last year, The Atlantic ran a lengthy profile of
stories of scientific discovery
Greek researcher John Ioannidis, whose studies
– the medical detective stories
of medical journal articles discovered that the
of Berton Roueche, Paul de
effects found in as many as half of randomised
Kruif’s The Microbe Hunters, Crick and Watson’s
controlled studies are later contradicted or signifi-
The Double Helix – clear-cut triumphant tales.
cantly reduced
Like the Hollywood historical dramas of the
In December, the New Yorker followed up
day, the heroes were heroes and everything was
with “The Truth Wears Off”, in which writer
very clean. Today, just as contemporary histor-
Jonah Lehrer discussed the “decline effect”.
ical dramas make a point of showing dirt and bad
Over successive studies, he said, positive research
teeth, science is a lot messier.
results drop off, so that (for example) drugs whose
Consider a spate of recent articles which seem to show that the practice of science is not working
effects look good in initial clinical trials seem to become less effective in subsequent trials. “It’s as if our facts were losing their truth”, Lehrer wrote, going on to note the decline
Proving the Obvious”. Writer Eryn Brown found
effect’s presence in multiple fields from medi-
a mix of reasons, from the need to repeatedly
cine to ecology. “If replication is what separates
hammer home the message to policy-makers to
the rigor of science from the squishiness of pseu-
a bias among funders toward timid, incremental
doscience, where do we put all these rigorously
research.
validated findings that can no longer be proved?”
Also in May, Popular Science ran a top-ten
Lehrer went on to examine the effect from
list of studies testing the (it-seemed) obvious.
all angles, largely concluding that the “decline
Again, influencing policy-makers by producing
effect” is in fact a “decline of illusion”.
last words/the skeptic
the way we think. In May, the LA Times ran “‘Duh’ Science: Why Researchers Spend So Much Time
>>>
hard numbers was a theme; but the scientists approached by writer Laura Allen also said they don’t assume anything, even the apparently obvious, but test it. That is, of course, exactly how
Wendy M Grossman (pelicancrossing.net) is founder and former editor (twice) of The Skeptic Magazine (skeptic.org.uk)
scientists are supposed to think.
4TH QUARTER 2011
tpm
127
Long contact with scepti-
c r y p t o g r a p h y. M e r k l e
cism makes it easy to think of
set about submitting the
plenty of reasons why further
resulting paper, only to
research might dilute the
meet two years of rejec-
effectiveness found in earlier
tion, usually on the grounds
studies. The whole article
that it did not fit in with the
discusses many of them. But
then-current thinking on the
if you read only the begin-
subject. Several more years
ning, your first reaction
passed before Whitfield
might be that the “decline
Diffie and Martin Hellman
effect” sounds uncomfortably like parapsychology’s “shyness effect”: that trained observation seems to deter psychic
Merkle says that the way overworked reviewers
phenomena from appearing. Lehrer doesn’t
screen ideas for both journal publication and
mention this, but parapsychology – J B Rhine’s
grant funding favours easily understandable,
studies of ESP – does lead him to regression to
incremental advances rather than radical new
the mean – that running more tests enlarges the
approaches. Public key cryptography was a revo-
sample, smoothing out clustering effects.
lution in that field (and a successful one: you use
last words/the skeptic
His bigger issues are selective reporting and
128
published similar ideas; both now give Merkle equal credit.
it every time you buy something online).
publication bias. Both funders and editors want
One of the consequences of all this is a notice-
positive results, a bias first noted as long ago as
able growth in what’s known in US academic
1959. The basis of science is supposed to be inde-
circles as the “least publishable unit”. The
pendent replication. But Lehrer quotes several
tenure track’s demand for a steady stream of
journal editors who are reluctant to publish
publications seems to leave most people two
reports of replication failures, and several scien-
alternatives. Either you take a major piece of
tists who aren’t interested in replicating others’
work and sequentially publish small pieces of it
work but rather in doing their own. According
or you come up with lightweight ideas that can be
to Nature, Lehrer says, a third of science papers
studied relatively quickly and easily and that have
never get cited, let only replicated. And if you
mass appeal. The former isn’t objectionable; the
are a scientist whose career was made by a single
latter is unnerving. I am not a scientist, and yet I
startling finding, trying to replicate it represents
find myself reading research papers that even I
a significant risk.
can tell are thin.
Curiously enough, some researchers say that
Ultimately, Lehrer’s goal, as he writes in a
journals and grant funders also tend to reject ideas
follow-up response, was to look at the messy
that are too radical. Ralph Merkle, for example,
reality of science: truth is slippery. He concludes,
as a late-1970s cryptography-obsessed graduate
“Just because an idea is true doesn’t mean it can
student came up with one of the earliest imple-
be proved. And just because an idea can be
mentations of what is now known as public key
proved doesn’t mean it’s true.”
tpm 4TH QUARTER 2011
London
New York
www.continuumbooks.com
Think Philosophy, Think Continuum
CONTINUUM COMPANIONS Practical and comprehensive, refine your research with Continuum’s flagship reference works. Our Continuum Companions series offer the definitive guide to key areas of contemporary philosophy and to key philosophical thinkers. In specially commissioned essays by teams of international experts, the books cover all the fundamental areas of the subject – topics that have continued to attract interest historically as well as topics that have emerged more recently as active areas of research. The essays reveal where important work continues to be done in the area covered and, most valuably, the exciting new directions the field is taking. Volumes feature a range of indispensable research tools, from A to Zs of key terms and concepts to detailed lists of resources and bibliographies. Some volumes also feature companion websites or other online resources to further enhance understanding.
Continuum Companion to Ethics
Continuum Companion to Existentialism
Continuum Companion to Pragmatism
Christian Miller September 2011 • 480 page HB • 9781441121752 • £100.00
Felicity Joseph, Jack Reynolds and Ashley Woodward August 2011 • 416 pages HB • 9780826438454 • £100.00
Sami Pihlström June 2011 • 336 pages HB • 9780826442246 • £100.00
Continuum Companion to Philosophical Logic
Continuum Companion to Hume
Continuum Companion to Spinoza
Leon Horsten and Richard Pettigrew June 2011 • 656 pages HB • 9781441154231 • £100.00
Alan Bailey and Dan O’Brien December 2011 • 464 pages HB • 9780826443595 • £100.00
Wiep van Bunge, Henri Krop, Piet Steenbakkers and Jeroen M.M. van de Ven March 2011 • 400 pages HB • 9780826418609 • £100.00
Stay up to date with all of Continuum’s philosophy news at our philosophy blog http://continuumphilosophy.typepad.com Follow us on Twitter http://twitter.com/ContinuumPhilos Find us on Facebook Search for the ‘Continuum Philosophy’ page
For more information on any of our titles, including previews where available, visit our website at www.continuumbooks.com
NEW FROM ACUMEN
APING MANKIND
NEUROMANIA, DARWINITIS AND THE MISREPRESENTATION OF HUMANITY RAYMOND TALLIS HARDBACK
üøø PAGES
úûü X ùýþMM āÿĀ-ù-Āüüþý-úÿú-û
£úý.øø
“With erudition, wit and rigour, Tallis reveals that much of our current wisdom is as silly as bumps-on-the-head phrenology.” JANE O’GRADY, THE OBSERVER In a devastating critique Raymond “A major and erudite statement of a position that is intellectually, morally and spiritually of the Tallis exposes the exaggerated ¿rst importance to us living now.” claims made for the ability of ROGER SCRUTON neuroscience and evolutionary theory to explain human con“A splendid book. Tallis is right to say that current attempts to explain major elements of human life by brain-talk are fearfully sciousness, behaviour, culture and misguided. He is exceptional in having both the philosophical society. The belief that human grasp to understand what is wrong here and the scienti¿c beings can be understood essenknowledge to expose it fully. He documents the gravity of this tially in biological terms is a serious menace with real ¿re, venom and humour.” obstacle, argues Tallis, to clear MARY MIDGLEY thinking about what human beings “A wonderful book and an important book, one that are and what they might become. all neuroscientists should read. Tallis’s fearless criticism of We are infinitely more interesting the work of some distinguished contemporary academics and complex than we appear in the and scientists and the rather ludicrous experimental mirror of biologism. paradigms of fMRI work needs to be made.” Combative, fearless and SIMON SHORVON, UCL INSTITUTE OF NEUROLOGY always thought-provoking, “There are few contemporary thinkers who possess either the Aping Mankind is an important breadth of Ray Tallis’s knowledge or the depth of his scholarship. book, one that scientists, cultural There are fewer still who can write so cogently and insightfully commentators and policy-makers about the human condition.” KENAN MALIK cannot ignore.
Acumen
www.acumenpublishing.co.uk