Only Connect
1
Pleasure Ground
Only Connect 2
five exercises in aesthetics
Christophe Van Eecke
Lokaal 01
‘Verweile nur! Du bist so schön’ Goethe, Faust, Part II
4
5
‘Once I could speak joyfully of beautiful things, thinking to be understood; now I cannot anymore; for it seems to me that no one regards them. Wherever I look or travel in England or abroad, I see that men, wherever they can reach, destroy all beauty.’ John Ruskin
TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction, 9 Chapter One: Better Living Through Art War and Resentment, 24 The Power of Vision, 34 Divine Substance, 39 The Therapeutic Fallacy, 43 Narrative Didactics, 47 Feeling and Form, 56 Virtual Spaces, 70 Fields of Vision, 80 Virtual Life, 90 Against Form, 98 Genius Redeemed, 104 Inventing the Human, 109
6
Chapter Two: Artworld Inc. Art Criticism After the End of Art, 122 Skirting Langer, 131 A Short History of the Avant-Garde, 140 Kondylian Combinations, 145 Art and Philosophy, 154 Beauty and Ugliness, 163 Killing Art, 169 Avant-Garde After the End of Avant-Garde, 177 Radical Chic for Chic Radicals, 184 Chapter Three: Getting Physicals A Body of Art, 193 From Performance to Concept, 199 Engaging the Audience, 204 Lethal Objections, 214 The Meating of Porn and Art on a Dissecting Table, 219 Do Androids Wank to Electric Wet Dreams?, 228 Mathesis Sexualis, 238 Scientia Sexualis, 243 Pleasure Machines, 251 Bodice Rest and Motion, 259 Moving Towards Stillness, 268 The Belly of a Dyslectic, 277
Chapter Four: Engaging The World Making the World, 289 Unmaking the World, 299 The Brutality of Fact, 304 The Quickening, 312 The Order of Things, 321 Dionysian Mysteries, 329 Cleansing Cleanliness, 339 Irreligious Rituals, 348 Lost in the Stars: A Materialist Manifesto, 354 Demonic Time, 357 Comes Undone, 364 Chapter Five: Frail Gazing Pathetic Fallacies, 371 Having the World, 378 Doubling, 386 Body Doubles, 389 Pictures Imperfect, 392 Scattergorising the World, 404 Optics of Desire, 410 Imagining Petals, 416 Living Memory, 422 Inner Space, 432 Magmatic Poetics, 441 Perchance to Dream, 445 Soft Sightings, 450 Cinechroma, 459 Gardens of the Underworld, 467 Into the Garden, 473 Bibliography, 482
7
Introduction
This book takes its title from the epigraph of E.M. Forster’s novel Howards End (1910) and takes as its own epigraph a phrase from Goethe’s Faust that is meant to recall 8
Immanuel Kant’s idea of purposiveness without purpose in the experience of art. As such, the title really does say it all. It is the project of this book to present, in a series of interconnected essays, a philosophy of art that seeks to demonstrate how art is one of the primary ways in which human beings express their connectedness to the world. The book was developed out of a series of four essays written for the exhibition project Pleasure Ground at Lokaal 01 in Breda, The Netherlands, in the Spring of 2010. A brief look at this exhibition and the way the essays were linked to it will help explain the book, its structure, and its content. ——— Pleasure Ground was meant as an investigation of the relationship between an art institution and the artists it chooses to exhibit. Lokaal 01 made an engagement to support
9
10
the artists they selected in any way possible to realise their
far as to put their own body into play for their art. This essay
projects within the exhibition. But the exhibition itself did
dealt extensively with issues of body art and performance art.
not have a theme. There was no curator to decide what
The fourth essay tried to look out at the world through art:
the exhibition would be about. The idea was to have the
how does art mould the relationship between man and his
artists create a series of four presentations with the total
world? These four core questions came about very early in the
commitment of Lokaal 01. This way, the engagement implied
process, and as I started to sketch what the contents of the
in the relationship between institution and artists became the
essays should be it immediately became clear that the issues
main focus of the exhibition, which was really about a process
touched upon were huge. The possibilities for exploring these
and about questioning certain power structures inherent
topics were endless. But at the same time it was also clear to
in the artworld. Curators often have tremendous power in
me that many of these topics were linked to issues I had been
deciding how art will be presented, how it will be read, and,
addressing in essays published elsewhere. Hence, Pleasure
most importantly, which artists will be shown and which will
Ground offered an opportunity to bring all this material
not be exhibited. In the Pleasure Ground project, this power was
together in a more systematic form. And as soon as this was
surrendered to the artists themselves, who had to assemble
clear, the possibility of bringing the four essays together in
the presentations among themselves. My task as philosopher
book form naturally presented itself.
in residence at Lokaal 01 consisted in framing this exhibition
As soon as the overall idea for the essays and the book were
process with four essays that would investigate several
in place, I took the project and ran with it; a kidnapping
aspects of commitment or engagement in art. These essays
operation that was most graciously tolerated and even
were published in ThRu, the theoretical journal published by
encouraged by everyone at Lokaal 01. Engagement became the
Lokaal 01.
starting point for a series of philosophical explorations that
It soon became clear that the four essays would have to
gave me an opportunity to think through issues I had long
focus on four different aspects of engagement. The first essay
wanted to address. Once the project was underway, however,
approached the topic from the point of view of society at
there were only four weeks to prepare each new essay, which
large: what kind of moral commitments are required from
is alarmingly little time by any standard. The only reason I
artists? The essay focused especially on the supposed moral
felt it could be done was that much of the material I wanted
and social responsibility of the artist in society. The second
to incorporate was already present on my computer and in
essay dealt with the relationship between artists and the
my notes. To a large extent, writing the essays was a matter of
artworld at large. How do artists position themselves in
bringing together research that had been done in the previous
relation to the artworld and what kind of commitments does
years. Also, it was agreed that the four essays as published
that imply? The third essay looked at the most personal and
in ThRu would be temporary versions and that I would
intimate kind of engagement, dealing with artists who go so
afterwards take several months to edit them, to add material,
11
rearrange arguments, and do whatever I felt was required
helpful. But apart from that, feel free to pick and choose. Is
to mould them into a book. As such, the four original essays
my treatment of Early German Romanticism a bore? Don’t
form the basis of the present book in the form of chapters
complain about it, go read about pornography in Chapter
one through four, albeit in heavily edited form and with much
Three! Not keen on Jarman? Get a life! And some taste in
material added. The long fifth chapter is entirely new. It grew
films! Go read a booklet on Spielberg!
out of the fourth chapter and brings together many themes
For me, as a writer, this patchwork structure of the book
and topics raised in the course of the book.
meant that I did not have to kill my darlings. I know that there is a law of the literary land which states that you need
———
an editor to tell you what you should cut and what you should keep in a book. But I have always felt that editors are
12
Although the book tells a story that moves from a to b (and
a frustrated breed of people who are incapable of writing
back again!), the five chapters can be read as self-contained
good books themselves and who get off telling other people
pieces. Every chapter in turn consists of a series of sections
how to write theirs to compensate. I also suspect that there
that develop its argument. But many of these sections could
is a conspiracy of philologists at work here. First, they get
also be read as self-contained essays. This applies especially
themselves a job editing your texts into something entirely
to the sections that offer an extended analysis of the work
at odds with your intentions. Then, forty years on, if you
of one individual artist. As such, Chapter Three ends with
happen to have become famous, they get themselves another
a very long discussion of the films of Andy Warhol, the first
job editing the critical edition of your works, restoring the
chapter contains a discussion of David Hockney, and the
text to resemble “the author’s original intentions”. But since
fourth deals at some length with Francis Bacon. So the reader
you had those intentions to begin with, why tamper with
should feel free to browse. If the size of the book seems rather
them? Given that the public is volatile, an author’s idea of
intimidating but you have a liking for Warhol, you might
what a book should be like has just as much chance of being
simply read those sections and hopefully be triggered by that
successful than an editor’s (after all, an editor is just a person,
discussion to find out how my approach to Warhol’s films is
not some kind of god). Since it’s the author who is authoring
embedded in the philosophical discussions elsewhere in the
the book, he or she should get to edit it. Would we require a
book. So the reader should feel free to dip in as if this were
painter to submit his painting to an editor and then make
a banquet of essays. But readers who wish to browse would
the recommended changes to his canvas? Would we require
in any case be well-advised to first read the sections dealing
Rodin to lose the thinking person on his already alarmingly
with Susanne K. Langer in the first chapter. Since Langer
overcrowded Gates of Hell? I don’t think so. Filmmakers have
provides the philosophical foundations on which this book
to deal with this kind of shit all the time because film is all
is built, some knowledge of her insights will in any case be
about investors and money and stupid people crunching
13
popcorn and spilling drinks in the aisles but usually history
connections (Camille Paglia’s reference to William Blake’s
proves the director’s cut right. Obviously, any intelligent writer
poem ‘London’ appears twice, once at the beginning of
will be open to constructive criticism. But if and how he or
the book, and again at the very end, which should tell you
she deals with it is entirely his or her affair. So don’t kill your
something). This intricate web of connections also means that
darlings. As Nigella knows, ‘in cooking, as in writing, you must
the reader is invited and even encouraged to constantly make
please yourself to please others’ (Lawson 1998: viii).
such connections, also to things that are not in the book. That is the point of Only Connect.
———
But now, for an overview. Chapter One, Better Living Through Art, starts with controversy. It takes the so-called “culture
14
Given the structure of the book and the many excursions and
wars” in America as a starting point for a discussion of the
diversions that people it, it seems sensible to provide a more
artist’s relationship to the larger community. This is an old
detailed overview of the several chapters, so that the reader
philosophical question, at least as old as Plato’s Politics: does
may know what can be found where and how it should all be
the artist have some kind of moral or social responsibility
connected. Since the book is dense with information such a
or not? Those who feel that art does have a role to play in
brief layout might also do good service as a point of reference
our moral well-being are guilty of the “therapeutic fallacy”.
for the reader who is making his or her way, chapter by
Several sections of the chapter sketch a brief outline of the
laborious chapter, from start to finish. There are many threads
history of the therapeutic fallacy, specifically in American
running through the several chapters and I trust the reader
art, where art has often become very politicised. There is a
will often be triggered to connect (details in) discussions in
brief detour through German Romantic philosophy which will
later chapters with elements encountered in earlier chapters.
prove useful further in the book, where we will hark back to it.
It is impossible (and tiresome) to constantly point out such
This discussion of the therapeutic fallacy finally leads into a
possible links. Reading the book several times will certainly
critique of Martha Nussbaum. She makes several claims about
help bring out the connections. Among our constant concerns
the moral value of art, especially literature, but we will argue
are the relationship between feeling (or meaning) and form,
that her claims are not very persuasive. The major part of the
the transformation of commonplace objects, voyeurism,
chapter is devoted to a discussion of Susanne K. Langer, who
fetishism, pornography, creation or world-making, and the
gives a much more persuasive account of how art works. In
burden of identity. What Danto calls the transfiguration of
fact, it is the most persuasive philosophy of art I know. But
the commonplace returns in our discussion of alternative
we do not simply stick with philosophy: Langer’s ideas are
geographies in the fifth chapter, where the entire world
illustrated with, among other things, a section on the work
lies metamorphosed. Certain images, references, and
of David Hockney. Langer’s views on literature are discussed
quotes return at different places in the book, bookmarking
in direct opposition to Nussbaum. Finally, at the end of the
15
16
chapter, we return to Early German Romanticism to find there
what its distinctive features might be. This soon leads us
the roots of our postmodern concept of the self, which is also
into a discussion of the body as a mechanical sex object. We
illustrated in an extended discussion of Shakespeare.
trace part of the history of this concept, which allows us to
The second chapter is called Artworld Inc. and it seeks
celebrate the Marquis de Sade in an entire section devoted
to illustrate the way the larger artworld influences our
to his divine godless universe. This chapter also contains
relationship with art. The artworld is peopled with what
elements of a philosophy of voyeurism and fetishism. The
Robert Hughes now calls “VARPs” or “Vaguely Art-Related
final sections of the chapter are devoted to a monographic
People”. They are a pest and this chapter is against them!
study of the work of Andy Warhol, whose work is of cardinal
An important element in our discussion is the influence
importance to the issues raised in the previous discussion.
of philosophy on the way we perceive and judge works of
Especially his film work comes under scrutiny.
art. Most of the chapter is devoted to a heroic attempt at
With Chapter Four, Engaging The World, we start our swerve
refuting the work of Arthur C. Danto and his ideas on the
away from politicised art and we venture out in search of
transfiguration of the commonplace in art. But we also take
beauty. Our guide on this search is the American philosopher
issue with the emergence of the PhD in the arts. Along the
Elaine Scarry. There are two major parts in her work (at least
way we sketch two histories of the avant-garde that are
from the perspective of our concerns): a discussion of pain
at odds with Danto’s account of the avant-garde. One of
and a discussion of beauty. These two, apparently opposite,
our counterexamples is the German philosopher Panajotis
concerns are linked in her work. So if we want to get at
Kondylis, whose concept of postmodernism will stay with us
beauty, we must first deal with pain. The structure of the
for the rest of the book. Finally, we will also address the issue
chapter runs as follows: if we live in a world of alienation
of the avant-garde after the end of avant-garde. Since both
(and we claim, along with Marx, that we do) then we must
history, art, and the avant-garde have been pronounced dead
first get through this alienation before we can engage in
quite a few times, it is interesting to see how the artworld
a new relationship with the world. The work of Hermann
tries to maintain an air of progressive avant-gardism in the
Nitsch serves as a gateway to such a rebirth, explaining
view of this tragic demise.
how masochistic rituals (a continuation of themes from
The third chapter, Getting Physcials, is devoted to the body,
the previous chapter) can be an incentive to a more intense
which is put into play in performance art and pornography.
awareness of the world. By way of finale we offer an extended
There are two main themes running through this chapter.
analysis of Béla Tarr’s film Sátántángo, which is all the
First, it attempts to provide a definition of what performance
metaphysics we need today.
art actually is (surprisingly, such a definition is rather hard
Elaine Scarry is also our guide in the fifth and final chapter,
to come by in existing discussions of performance art);
Frail Gazing, which seeks to substitute what I call the “frail
second, it tries to define what kind of art pornography is and
gaze” for that ocular monster, the “male gaze”. Looking at
17
beautiful things is a wonderful pastime and the entire chapter
not be accomplished before deadline. Also, I regret I had to
is a defence of this much-maligned practice. We start our
jettison, for reasons of organisation (sometimes you just can’t
discussion with John Ruskin’s notion of the pathetic fallacy,
harmoniously squeeze into a book what you’d like to squeeze
which forbids us to see the world as animated. It soon
in), sections on Coil, Oleg Kulik, and many others. Readers
becomes clear that the general trend of the present book is
who want the shortest possible introduction to the experience
quite at odds with this idea, although we do reclaim Ruskin
of masochism as discussed in this book should watch director
for beauty. After that, it’s beauty all the way. The long chapter
João Pedro Rodrigues’ mighty O Fantasma (2000).
is a tapestry of interrelated discussions of artists that take up many topics from the earlier chapters. Animism, beauty,
———
memory, fetishism, and the joys of looking are several of the
18
themes that are traced through the work of Apichatpong
Finally, some notes on the material that is usually gathered
Weerasethakul (but because his work seems so personal
under the heading ‘Preface’. These are the thank you notes
and so engaging, I take the liberty of simply calling him
and the references to material published before elsewhere.
Apichatpong), Wolfgang Tillmans (who takes us back to our
Much of the material in this book draws on essays published
discussion of voyeurism and fetishism), Nan Goldin, Pier Paolo
in the last five years. Since I did not think it appropriate to
Pasolini, John Boorman, Jesús Franco (an unusual suspect for
make endless references to my own work in the text, I have
a philosophy of art), and Derek Jarman, who closes the book.
simply listed the most important items in the Bibliography.
Along the way, many other artists are discussed. We end, I
My discussions of the PhD in the arts, Anthony Goicolea, and
hope, in beauty, in Derek Jarman’s garden.
Terence Davies draw on pieces published in rekto:verso. If I
Several recently published books came to my attention too
manage to slip in my own definition of the sublime in the
late to include them in my discussion. But as they seem to
very last paragraph of the book, this is entirely due to the fact
be of great interest for the topics raised in Only Connect, I
that I have previously elaborated on it in that same journal
feel I should point the reader to them. Armando Maggi’s The
in a piece on “cinetrauma”. My discussions of voyeurism and
Resurrection of the Body (2009) covers much of the ground on
masochism, along with some material on Rorty and Goldin,
Pasolini’s late work from a point of view that seems similar to
were first essayed in Streven. Discussions of Warhol, Pasolini,
mine (I first published my extensive discussion of Pasolini’s
Boorman (and affiliated films), and Tarr draw on material
Saló in the Summer 2007 issue of Cinemagie). I love Richard
published in a series of essays for Cinemagie. The discussion
Sennett’s The Fall of Public Man (1977) and regret I did not come
of radical chic for chic radicals draws on material presented
across The Craftsman (2008) sometime sooner. Hermann Nitsch
in Metropolis M. The material on Nitsch was first presented,
recently published his magnum opus, the massive, three-
in a somewhat briefer incarnation, as a public lecture at
volume Das Sein (2009). Reading it is a month’s work and could
OFFoff in Ghent in 2009. The audience at OFFoff also got a
19
20
preview of my musings on the link between performance art
to be thanked for reading earlier versions, correcting my
and pornography just before the book went to press. These
mistakes, or thinking in my stead. However, over the course
earlier texts have not been copy-pasted together to create the
of the years I have benefited from repeated discussions with
semblance of a book. Rather, I have relied on them as sources
(in alphabetical order) Antoon Braeckman (who pointed me
of information and have restated their arguments, or parts of
towards Kondylis and Manfred Frank, how can I thank him?),
them, within the fabric of new arguments. The earlier texts
Jean-Marie Bytebier, Wim Christiaens, Bert Frings, Linda
were treated as research to feed on, not sources to copy. Only
Hoo Hui Lan, Sander Jongen, Warre Mulder, Nele Tas, Kris
on a very few occasions have I scavenged my own earlier
Van Dessel, Karel Van Haesebrouck, Tom Van Imschoot, Sofie
essays and excerpted longer pieces of text. This applies
Verdoodt, and Frederik Vergaert. I hope I haven’t overlooked
especially to the discussion of Early German Romanticism
anyone. Finally, but not in the least, I dedicate this book to
in Chapter One and the discussion of Scarry and Marx in
Kris, my partner, who has had to live with it for the better part
Chapter Three. These sections reproduce, in sometimes
of our relationship. He has also created my website (www.
heavily edited form, material published in two booklets that
christophevaneecke.be) and is the cause of a certain obsession
are available online from Lokaal 01: Absolute Beginnings (2009)
with Nigella.
and Stock Footage & Shock Tactics (2009). Finally, then, for the many thanks due to others. First and
21
———
foremost, I would like to thank the crew at Lokaal 01 for supporting and publishing this book. I would like to thank
For ease of reference I have introduced a number of sigla
the editors of rekto:verso, Cinemagie, Streven, and Metropolis M
to refer to books and sources that are frequently referred
for so often giving me carte blanche in the choice of topic
to. They are listed here. Full bibliographical details can be
and the mode of analysis in the essays they always (but no
retrieved in the Bibliography.
doubt sometimes grudgingly) published. These essays were an excellent playing ground to try out ideas and approaches that I hope have come to some kind of fruition in this book. Especially my work at rekto:verso was good learning. I can
TC Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace PDA Danto, The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art AEA Danto, After the End of Art
all those essays they will now have to suffer through an
PNK Langer, Philosophy in a New Key FF Langer, Feeling and Form PA Langer, Problems of Art MI Langer, Mind. Volume I
entire book containing more of the same and composed
OMT Nitsch, Das Orgien Mysterien Theater
without editorial restraint! My research wasn’t subsidised by
PJ Nussbaum, Poetic Justice
only imagine my friends’ dismay when they hear that after
any research grant, so I ain’t thankin’ no government. Since I have no scientific community to bask in, nobody needs
BP Scarry, The Body in Pain BBJ Scarry, On Beauty and Being Just DB Scarry, Dreaming by the Book
Chapter One
BETTER LIVING THROUGH ART 23
When Plato designed his ideal state, he felt the poets should be kept out. They were an unruly lot who threatened the moral fabric of the polity by presenting misleadingly immoral images of the gods. Poetry, to be permissible, must strengthen morale. In the Sophist it is the visual artist who comes under attack. Plato thought that the material world was only an imperfect copy of an ideal world of ideas. An image made by an artist was therefore a copy of a copy of reality and could only lead to falsehood and misrepresentation. Plato was no friend to the arts. Many centuries later Friedrich Schiller also mused on the morality of art in his letters on the aesthetic education of man, published in 1795. Schiller wasn’t quite as pessimistic as Plato and he believed that the theatre, which (as a dramatist) was his favoured art, could provide the public with moral lessons attractively packaged in entertaining sto-
24
ries. In that way the theatre could be an invaluable contribu-
Arts (NEA), which is to say that it was partially paid for with
tion to public morality and education. The idea that art can
taxpayers’ money. However, the hullabaloo over Serrano’s
and should somehow help us become better people has been
picture was to become part of a much larger controversy that
at the heart of aesthetics and morality for centuries. More
focused on a major Robert Mapplethorpe retrospective (Bau-
often than not art is attacked or defended on the grounds of
erlein 2009: 89-95). On December 9, 1988, the Mapplethorpe
its supposed moral effects and not on grounds of aesthetic
retrospective The Perfect Moment opened at the Institute for
achievement. In recent times we have seen an upsurge of
Contemporary Art (ICA) in Philadelphia. It would later travel
moral concern with the arts, as in the so-called “culture
to Washington and Cincinnati. The exhibition showed a wide
wars” that have ravaged American artistic life since the late
selection of photographs, including the infamous X Portfolio,
1980s. Both opponents and defenders of the arts argue from
a series of thirteen images showing men involved in extreme
the idea that art has moral effects on the public, desirable
acts of sadomasochism. This exhibition had also been partial-
or undesirable effects depending on which side of the politi-
ly funded with an NEA grant. Both Serrano’s and Mappletho-
cal spectrum a person chooses to locate herself. In this way
rpe’s work came under attack from the American Family
the debate on both sides implies that artists have some sort
Association, who alerted D’Amato to the scandal. On May 18,
of social responsibility: voices from the Right feel art should
1989, thirty-six senators signed a letter demanding changes
bolster traditional values, voices from the Left feel art should
to the NEA policy so ‘that shocking, abhorrent and completely
speak for the oppressed. Neither party seems to believe that
undeserving art would not get money’ (Morrisroe 1995: 372).
it is the foremost business of art to be beautiful or of out-
On June 12, 1989, it was announced that the Corcoran Gallery
standing aesthetic value. All these questions, however, raise a
in Washington D.C. had decided to cancel the Perfect Moment
much more fundamental issue about the nature of art: what
exhibition in view of the controversy. This caused outrage in
is it? How does it work? What does it do? Such questions
the art community and on June 30, a protest was organised
must be dealt with before we can say anything about the way
outside the Corcoran with protesters projecting slides of
art functions in society.
Mapplethorpe’s works onto the facade of the building. To Camille Paglia, who commented on the events in an essay, this
War and Resentment
protest represented what she called ‘Mapplethorpe’s essence,
The culture wars officially started on May 18, 1989, when
his spectral identity as a suffering Romantic artist forever
Republican Senator Alfonse D’Amato tore apart a reproduc-
outside the pale. The demonstration ingeniously replayed,
tion of Andres Serrano’s Piss Christ (1987) on the Senate floor.
without knowing it, the cinema of Blake’s great poem “Lon-
Serrano’s photograph showed a plastic crucifix immersed in
don,” where solitary, excluded voices smear or mar the cold
the artist’s own urine and had been shown in an exhibition
stone walls of society’s institutions’ (Paglia 1993: 41).
partially funded through the National Endowment for the
On July 26, the Senate approved restrictions proposed by Jesse
25
Helms, Republican senator for North Carolina. These restrictions demanded that the NEA would not ‘promote, disseminate or produce’ a veritable catalogue of offensive materials, namely: ‘(1) obscene or indecent materials, including but not limited to depictions of sadomasochism, homo-eroticism, the exploitation of children, or individuals engaged in sex acts; or (2) material which denigrates the objects or beliefs of the adherents of a particular religion or non-religion; or, (3) material which denigrates, debases, or reviles a person, group or class of citizens on the basis of race, creed, sex, handicap, age or national origin’ (Hughes 1994: 163). Much could be said about this amendment, first and foremost the fact that it casts its net so widely as to become virtually useless. Anything could be objected to by just about anyone according to 26
the phrasings of this text. What, for instance, could conceivably be meant by someone’s ‘religion or non-religion’? And would Helms support the suppression of religious speech that reviles homosexuals on the grounds that it denigrates on the basis of sex? In the end, it didn’t really matter because the Senate voted the restrictions down on September 29. But that was not the end of the controversy, for in March 1990 The Perfect Moment, by now surrounded by a heady atmosphere of scandal and prurience, opened at the Contemporary Arts Center in Cincinnati, where obscenity charges were lodged against Dennis Barrie, the Center’s director. On October 5, 1990, however, both Barrie and the CAC were acquitted by a jury because the prosecution had failed to show that Mapplethorpe’s work lacked artistic merit. ‘The jury was unanimous in deciding that Mapplethorpe’s pictures appealed to a prurient interest in sex, and that they were patently offensive, but they couldn’t agree that they lacked artistic merit’
27
28
(Morrisroe 1995: 375). This in effect sunk the prosecution’s
lieved that art history was written by and for men and sought
case, for the three counts must be fulfilled in order to deem a
to redress the imbalance by recovering female artists from
work legally obscene.
the mists of the past. This research has brought to light some
The Perfect Moment controversy was a highly publicised case,
interesting women artists but it has not changed the general
but it was only one in a series of conservative attacks on the
outline of art history.
arts and the media. But the Left has been just as repressive
Parallel to the rise of gender feminism the 1980s also saw the
and many leftists, especially militant feminists (but also sev-
rise of so-called “issue-based art,” which is a highly politi-
eral other groups, notably gay activists), have made concerted
cised form of art about social oppression. In no particular
efforts to police public speech, education, the arts, and the
order this movement yielded feminist art, gay or lesbian
media in similar ways. The 1980s saw the rise of so-called
art, African-American art, and any kind of minority art one
“gender feminism”. Gender feminists are not ordinary femi-
cares to imagine. This vogue was born from ‘the notion that
nists. The tradition of feminism as it was conceived in the
one of the specific tasks of the contemporary artist was to
nineteenth century finds its expression in what is called “eq-
give a voice to groups that in some way saw themselves as
uity feminism”: the demand for equal rights and freedoms
disadvantaged’ (Lucie-Smith 2001: 207). Most issue-based
for women, but with no demands for special treatment and
art was dull and preachy and barely bothered to rise above
without rancour or hatred towards men. Gender feminism
the level of public whining. But there was no need to rise
is much more radical and displays an outspoken hostility
because feminists had made the idea of aesthetic quality
towards men. Christina Hoff Sommers has called it a ‘femi-
subservient to social concerns. A work could become valid as
nism of resentment that rationalises and fosters a wholesale
art on the strength of its being an expression of the suffer-
rancour in women that has little to do with moral indigna-
ing of the oppressed. According to Robert Hughes, who was
tion’ (Hoff Sommers 1995: 41). Gender feminism is a kind of
severely critical of this development, issue-based art led to
identity politics that claims that women have been, and still
‘the belief that mere expressiveness is enough; that I become
are, oppressed and abused by a patriarchy that condones
an artist by showing you my warm guts and defying you to
and even encourages violence against women. The mission
reject them. [...] I am a victim: how dare you impose your
of gender feminism is not simply to do away with the many
aesthetic standards on me?’ (Hughes 1994: 188). Feminists
grievous discriminations women face in the world, which is a
believed they had to police the arts for offensive materials,
project that no sensible person could oppose, but to create a
very much in the way that conservatives wanted to keep
rift between men and women. They are at war with the pa-
publicly funded art clean from immoral elements. Porn came
triarchy and seek to denounce, shame, and, if at all possible,
heavily under attack, especially from latter-day Puritans like
censor all utterances, writings, opinions, or works of art that
Catharine MacKinnon. Male artists such has Picasso became
they deem offensive to women. Gender feminists further be-
virtual untouchables in women’s studies because of their per-
29
30
ceived sexism and were replaced with the work of oppressed
approach considered to be unacceptable because it implicitly
women and with the joys of quilt-making, which became the
denigrates those who are given lesser status. The very idea of
ruling feminist metaphor for art in the new, liberated mode.
“genius” is regarded with suspicion as elitist and “masculin-
One of the most saddening aspects of the feminist hysteria
ist”’ (Hoff Sommers 1995: 64-65). The second response was of-
was its attack on beauty itself, lead by Naomi Wolf’s book The
ten used to buttress the first and relies on deconstruction in
Beauty Myth (1990), which claims that beauty is an ideological
the New Historicist mode: by “demonstrating” that works of
tool instilled in women as a form of self-surveillance. Beauty
art are mere “effects” of “social energies,” the idea of the in-
was perceived as making women complicit in their own sub-
dividual artist as a creative genius could be done away with.
ordination. Also, beauty, and especially physical beauty in
Thus, the death of the author was cheerfully proclaimed. Ob-
women, was guilty of inviting the male gaze, an objectifying
viously, there is nothing wrong with contextualising works of
way of looking that reduced beautiful women to mere sex
art to enhance understanding. But to see works of art as mere
objects in the eye of lascivious beholders of evil intent.
effects of anonymous social energies, about which very little
In literature departments the canon came under attack. If
can be proved (the idea of social energies is just as ephemeral
art history was a male conspiracy to keep women back, then
and metaphysical as Freud’s subconscious or the argument
the history of literature was the work of “dead white Euro-
from design in religious circles), is quite something else. Har-
pean males”. This diagnosis elicited two responses. The first
old Bloom opposed New Historicism and pointedly remarked
was the substitution of contemporary minority literature of
that ‘William Shakespeare wrote thirty-eight plays, twenty-
questionable literary quality for the more canonical texts that
four of them masterpieces, but social energy has never writ-
were read in the traditional curriculum. This was euphemisti-
ten a single scene. The death of the author is a trope, and a
cally called an “expansion” of the canon. Such an expansion
rather pernicious one; the life of the author is a quantifiable
might be marginally tolerable if the substitutes were works of
entity’ (Bloom 1994: 37).
literary merit, but, as Harold Bloom points out, ‘the “expan-
Bloom famously baptised these trends in feminism, minority
sion of the Canon” has meant the destruction of the Canon,
thinking, and New Historicism the “School of Resentment”:
since what is being taught includes by no means the best
fuelled by a misguided sense of egalitarianism and social
writers who happen to be women, African, Hispanic, or Asian,
justice they reject any kind of greatness and desperately try
but rather the writers who offer little but the resentment
to drag everything down to their own level. ‘Originality is the
they have developed as part of their sense of identity’ (Bloom
great scandal that resentment cannot accommodate’ (o.c. 25).
1994: 7). Christina Hoff Sommers remarks that the gender
Talent and genius are denied, standards of quality and excel-
feminists ‘challenge the very idea of “great art,” “great litera-
lence are jettisoned as oppressive tools of discrimination,
ture,” and [...] “great science.” Talk of “greatness” and “master-
and politics takes the place of aesthetics because beauty is in
pieces” implies a ranking of artists and works, a “hierarchical”
the gaze of the rapist. And so extremes meet in the American
31
32
culture wars. Both the Right and the Left have tried to censor
the new edition, leaving some pages virtually blank. This kind
art and language. The Right wants to censor anything that is
of ‘pre-emptive self-censorship’ is made necessary because,
offensive to their religious, patriotic, or other moral beliefs,
as Waugh dramatically but entirely justifiably claims, ‘we fear
the Left would like to censor anything that transgresses
for our livelihoods and our freedom and safety, as well as,
the norm of political correctness. So common sense, art,
more pragmatically and importantly, for the ability to distrib-
and education get stuck between what Robert Hughes has
ute this edition’ if such possibly offensive images are left in
called the two PCs: Patriotic Correctness and Political Cor-
(Falkon 2006: 21).
rectness (Hughes 1997: 619). In both cases the censorship is
The third example of PC censorship is taken from my own
founded on the belief that art has a public role to fulfil and
experience. Like many of my friends, I have a Facebook page.
that this role is somehow moral in nature. Art educates, art
One day I decided to create ‘The Aiden Shaw Appreciation
makes us better people. According to your definition of what
Society’ as a fan page for the now-legendary gay porn star.
constitutes a “good” human being you can write your own
It was meant in a tongue-in-cheek way, as the name of the
catalogue of unwanted expressions, language, art-works,
page suggests. There was no offensive material on the page,
ideas, television programs, and so on. This wave of Political
only a picture of Shaw’s bare chest (with pants on) and a brief
Correctness resulted in a series of cases of actual censorship
text extolling his fine physique. The page only had a hand-
that were often so bizarre that they could have been funny
ful of fans, since my stock of Facebook-friends is limited to
if the situation wasn’t so desperately depressing. In a much-
people I actually know, many of whom are not even gay. On
publicised case, Nancy Stumhofer, an English instructor at
January 31, 2010, I received a warning from Facebook that
Pennsylvania State University, pressured administrators into
my Appreciation Society had been removed because it vio-
removing a reproduction of Goya’s The Naked Maya from a
lated the Terms of Use, which forbid groups that are ‘hateful,
classroom because it created “a hostile work environment”
threatening, or obscene’. Since the page was in appreciation
(Hoff Sommers 1995: 270-271; Paglia 1995: 50). The sheer force
of a person, I assume it wasn’t hateful or threatening. So it
of the PC movement, and the very real dangers of legal ac-
must have been obscene, despite the fact that there were no
tion it entails, often resulted in self-censorship by authors
offensive pictures or foul language on it. Therefore, I must
and artists. This was the case when scholar Thomas Waugh
assume that the very fact that Shaw is a gay male porn star
edited what he diplomatically calls ‘a “reasonably faithful”
was deemed obscene and offensive by Facebook. At the same
facsimile edition’ of Felix Lance Falkon’s classic book of gay
time, however, several politicians from the (extreme) right
graphic art, Gay Art. A Historic Collection, originally published
maintain Facebook pages without interference, regardless of
in 1972. This book collected homo-erotic drawings from the
the fact that they stand for hateful, racist, and often threat-
sexual underground and contained several images that sug-
ening ideologies. Apparently, a gay male porn star is obscene
gested sex with minors. Several such images were cropped in
per se, but right-wing racists are not. This gives an idea of
33
the kind of PC democracy and freedom Facebook stands for.
was considered by many to be the Second Coming. By con-
Finally, the e-mail closed with the warning that ‘further she-
sequence, Shaker beliefs allowed great equality between the
nanigans wit’in Ye Olde Facebook’s borders mayhapse cause
sexes, as God had become manifest both through Jesus Christ
ye arrrrrcount t’ be used fer cannon fodder!’ There is some-
and through Ann Lee. But Lee also held strict views on world-
thing unsettling about this phrase. Its jocular tone suggests
liness. Of jewellery and decoration she said: ‘You may let the
that I’ve really just been a very bad boy and should know
moles and bats have them; that is, the children of this world;
better by now. It treats the whole affair as a quibble among
for they set their hearts upon such things; but the people of
friends. But where’s the joke in censorship?
God do not want them’ (Kirk 1997: 52). However, in his fine study of Shaker art and culture, James T. Kirk rightly points
34
The Power of Vision
out that the Shakers were ‘not against beauty, but against
The idea that art has a moral role to play in society is at the
ostentation’ (o.c. 54) and that they ‘usually sought to expunge
heart of the American concept of art and can be traced back
unnecessary details from thoughts, daily living, and designs’
to the historical roots of the republic. The three most impor-
(o.c. 37). As a consequence, Shaker culture has created objects
tant religious sects to seek refuge in America from religious
of great economy but splendid beauty. Several Shaker phrases
intolerance in the Old World, namely Puritans, Quakers, and
give us insight into the principles they used when creating
Shakers, disapproved of art to a great extent. The 17th century
objects for use, in the first instance architecture and furni-
New England Puritans had a profound distrust of the image.
ture: ‘Regularity is beautiful’; ‘There is great beauty in har-
This distrust extended to religious art because it fell under
mony’; ‘Order is the creation of beauty’; ‘Beauty rests on util-
the ban on graven images in Deuteronomy. And since the
ity’. So Shaker culture does not reject beauty, but for Shakers
Puritans did not approve of excessive worldliness the idea of
beauty ‘has to do with order [and] is judged by perception of
painting a landscape for the sake of a landscape was equally
unity and appropriateness’ (o.c. 55).
anathema. The only kind of painting they did commission
American attitudes towards art would change with the ad-
was portraiture, which had no “expressive” goal but simply
vent of Romanticism, not because the religious ideas behind
served to preserve a person’s features for posterity (Hughes
the dislike disappeared, but because Romanticism offered
1997: 32). The Quakers were in some respects the opposite
a concept of art, and especially of landscape painting, that
of the austere Puritans, for they celebrated ‘unstructured,
was commensurable with the religious ideas of Puritans. The
ecstatic, spirit-led relationships with God’ (Kirk 1997: 11). But
Romantics started to explore the relationship between man
just like the Puritans they disapproved of worldliness. The
and nature and saw nature as a guide to divine presence in
Shakers evolved out of the Quakers and were especially noto-
the material world. But the rise of landscape painting as the
rious for the ecstatic dancing during their religious services.
quintessential American genre did not happen overnight. In
Their most important early spiritual leader was Ann Lee, who
the early decades of the republic portraiture dominated the
35
36
visual arts to the extent that it became a burden on artists’
influences on health, morals and politics’ (o.c. 127). As John
ability to develop their craft: artists were so dependent upon
Armstrong points out, ‘the belief that it makes a difference
commissions that they had to devote most of their attention
what you contemplate relies upon the assumption that what
and energy to portraits. There was a group of artists, how-
you contemplate somehow gets inside you; contemplation
ever, who were fortunate enough to have wealthy families or
is the spiritual analogue to eating’ (Armstrong 2000: 99-100).
patrons who could afford (and were willing) to finance a trip
People become infected by what they see. An interesting
to the Old World in order that the artist might study the art
effect of this new moral perspective on art was ‘increased
of Europe. When these artists returned to the United States,
respect for mind and artistic creativity. Uncontaminated
they found that the European aristocratic approach to art
nature, the standard of perfection for Americans at home,
was at odds with the American perception of artists as crafts-
developed a competitor. God revealed His true greatness not
men. For Americans, painting was a trade like any other. But
through His own works, but through the man-made objects
as art-historian Neil Harris explains in his study of The Artist
which He inspired.’ From now on art could no longer be seen
in American Society (1966), the artists who had sojourned in
simply as a trade because ‘art’s triumphs were also nature’s,
Europe ‘had spent years developing techniques to differenti-
but nature ripened and extended. [...] True masterpieces were
ate themselves from mere visual craftsmen, and they did not
distinguished not by manual tricks or sleight of hand, but by
even consider surrendering their hard-won technical mastery
a grandeur of mind. [...] The purpose of painting, therefore,
and their intellectual objectives to straightforward record-
was not to imitate nature’s beauties but to present a great
ing of the ordinary. Higher, more transcendental goals alone
and original concept. “The great artists do not give us nature,
could justify their sacrifices and trials. Art was “divine,” and
but give us themselves,” wrote James Freeman Clarke. [...] The
divinity precluded compromises with vulgar needs’ (Harris
artist’s primary function was to be true to his own concep-
1982: 87).
tualisations, enriching natural views with personal insights’
Soon, American artists and critics ‘produced grandiose
(Harris 1982: 131).
conceptions of art as a moral and political instrument, and
The aesthetic experiences of Americans abroad often took
a panacea for human ills’ (o.c. 124). It is difficult to over-
on a near-religious intensity. This rapture was shared by the
estimate the importance of the Amercian artists’ travels
many clergy who travelled to Europe and who returned to
through Europe for this shift of perspective. As Neil Harris
the homeland to testify to the transforming power of the
has pointed out, ‘it is impossible to accept the continual
visual arts. One of the reasons the clergy became convinced
emphasis on the moral efficacy of art objects, as threats or
of art’s moral power was the fact that the Catholic church
bulwarks to the established order, unless it is understood
had for centuries been the most important patron of the arts
that the art experience of many travellers was so traumatic
in Europe. Aesthetic rapture was most often experienced
that they believed vision could exert permanent and radical
in front of Renaissance and Baroque saints in transports of
37
ecstasy. The very force of these works made it clear that art
the landscape experience was that of God as supreme artist,
could be a powerful ally for any religion and it seemed a pity
it need only be a short step to the idea that artists were seers
that American Puritans had denied themselves the benefits
or priests. [...] They were trained to read the Book of nature,
of such a valuable tool. From the 1830s on Americans began
in which God’s will was inscribed, as surely as in the Bible’
to look favourably upon such new ideas imported from the
(Hughes 1997: 138-139).
Old World. The idea of art as religious revelation pleased
38
Americans because there had always been an element of
Divine Substance
pantheism in Puritanism, which tended to see ‘evidence
But the Transcendentalists did not think of all this on their
of divine planning in natural disasters and windfalls’ (o.c.
own. In fact, much of their philosophy was also a European
171). This mystico-religious approach to nature was made
import. It was very close to German idealism, and especially
explicit in the philosophy of the Transcendentalist move-
to Schelling’s philosophy of Nature. Schelling had in turn
ment, whose most famous representatives were Ralph Waldo
been profoundly influenced by the work of Spinoza, who was
Emerson (1803-1882) and Henry David Thoreau (1817-1862).
generally held to be responsible for reintroducing the her-
Transcendentalism was the philosophy of the worship of
esy of pantheism into modern thought. The concept of the
Nature. As Neil Harris explains, ‘Transcendentalists held
American Sublime, the American brand of landscape painting
that material objects were significant only as emanations of
with its heroic concept of the artist and his relation to nature,
Spirit, the world being [...]. It was vital for man to understand
is very much a continuation of ideas that were at the heart
his proper relationship with the external world, for strang-
of Romantic philosophy in Europe. So it is useful to briefly
ers to nature were alienated from God. The energy of the
look at this history and see where Emerson and his kind got
Supreme Being, what Transcendentalists called “Spirit,” lay
their metaphysical ideas. It is a fascinating story that starts,
behind and throughout all material objects. All matter was
for our purposes, with Baruch de Spinoza (1632-1677), who
therefore good in the sight of God, and all of nature deserved
at the dawn of the eighteenth century was the world’s most
reverence’ (o.c. 172-3). This way, Transcendentalism ‘opened
despised philosopher because he had published a tract in
the door to art appreciation, but also constrained it. [...] Art’s
defence of religious tolerance and because his concept of God
only importance lay in its representation of nature’ (o.c. 173).
was felt to be nihilistic, pantheistic, and atheistic. Spinoza
Transcendentalism therefore provided the key element in the
saw God as infinite substance, an all-encompassing entity in
transition from Puritan suspicion of art to a celebration of
which all events were linked in an endless chain of causality.
art as the seat of moral and religious sentiment. ‘If American
God therefore is nature. But this was a tricky idea, for if the
nature was one vast church,’ Robert Hughes remarks, ‘then
world consists of a series of tightly connected causes, then
landscape artists were its clergy. This changed the status of
this raises the obvious question of the final cause: if every
American artists themselves. [...] If the presiding metaphor of
cause is in turn explained by another cause, this leaves the
39
40
problem of what caused the first cause, and whether a first
die Lehre des Spinoza (1785), which would become immensely
cause, namely God, can exist at all. Therefore, materialism
influential among young Romantic philosophers. Jacobi’s
and the denial of God’s existence were felt to be but a breath
book is a messy affair, a collage of fragments and snippets
away and Spinoza was duly condemned for his unorthodox
from letters. Mendelssohn was shocked and dismayed by it,
views. Henry More even called him ‘the most impudent of
especially since Jacobi had not bothered to ask permission
mortals’ (Israel 2001: 229). Within less than a century, how-
to publish extracts from Mendelssohn’s letters. Mendelssohn
ever, Spinoza would rise to prominence again thanks to Ger-
felt he should respond and soon a major philosophical con-
man Romantic philosophy. And it is one of those subtle iro-
troversy was in the making, with arguments being made for
nies of history that one of the chief thinkers responsible for
and against Lessing’s alleged Spinozism by both the original
this revival was a man who heartily disliked Spinoza. Moses
contenders and several other philosophers who felt the need
Mendelssohn (1729-1786) was profoundly critical of Spinoza
to contribute to the debate. In the end, the controversy would
but became an unwilling participant in Spinoza’s comeback
claim Mendelssohn’s life. Rushing to get the manuscript of
at the hands of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (1743-1819), one of
An die Freunde Lessings, his final rebuttal to Jacobi, to his pub-
the first German Romantic philosophers.
lisher on December 31, 1785, the coldest day of the year, Men-
Jacobi claimed that Gotthold Ephraim Lessing (1729-1781) had
delssohn forgot to put on his coat, fell seriously ill, and died
told him that ‘there is no philosophy other than Spinoza’s’
within days on January 4, 1786 (o.c. 74). Jacobi was widely
(Beiser 1987: 66). Lessing is now chiefly remembered as the
held to be responsible for Mendelssohn’s tragic and untimely
author of a famous essay on Laokoön oder über die Grenzen
demise. The controversy itself would continue a while longer,
der Malerei und Poesie (1766) but he was a man of formidable
but the main effect was that the name of Spinoza was now
stature in the eighteenth century and a personal friend of
once again foremost in philosophers’ minds. And no Roman-
Mendelssohn’s. Jacobi’s claim about Lessing’s supposed Spi-
tic philosopher would be more deeply influenced by Spinoza
nozism was not an unlikely suggestion since between 1774
than Schelling.
and 1778 Lessing had published the Wolffenbüttler Fragmente,
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling (1775-1854) was one of
selections from the Spinozist writings of one H.S. Reimarius.
the many young Romantic philosophers who read Jacobi’s
Lessing’s commentary on these fragments was widely felt to
book with passionate interest. He would go on to become the
be too impartial and not sufficiently critical of Spinoza. When
quintessential Romantic philosopher and is primarily re-
Mendelssohn heard about Jacobi’s intent to disclose Lessing’s
membered as the author of an ambitious philosophy of na-
Spinozism, he felt he should defend his friend’s posthumous
ture in a Spinozist vein. Schelling’s clearest statement of this
reputation and started to exchange letters with Jacobi on the
Romantic philosophy can be found in his System des transzen-
matter. Eager to make his case, Jacobi assembled a selection
dentalen Idealismus (1800). Schelling sees Nature as a produc-
from their correspondence and rushed it into print as Über
tive force that constantly creates itself. It is infinite self-real-
41
42
isation. Nature brings itself into being, which is reminiscent
man Romantic philosophers. Novalis had also claimed that
of Spinoza’s idea of God as perpetually creative substance (in
‘the sense of poetry has much in common with mysticism.
fact, Schelling’s philosophy on this point was also profoundly
[...] It sees the invisible, feels what cannot be felt [...]. The
influenced by Johann Gottlieb Fichte, who in the early 1790s
poet is truly out of his senses – that is why everything is in
was a terrific philosophical presence in Jena, where Schelling
him. [...] The sense of poetry is closely related to the sense of
studied). All the natural phenomena, be they plants, animals,
clairvoyance and to the religious, in fact to the art of the seer.
minerals, or human beings, are products of this process of
The poet establishes order, unites, chooses, creates – and yet
self-realisation. The end of the process is mankind because in
it is unclear to him why things must be so and not otherwise’
man Nature has generated something that is similar to itself:
(Frank 1989: 174). Robert Rosenblum has suggested that many
a being that wants to realise its own goals in nature. Just like
of the ideas about art and nature expressed in these philoso-
Nature, humans engage in self-realisation by transforming
phies could also be found in the art of Romanticism, and he
the world around them to suit their purposes. That is why
has pointed to the work of Caspar David Friedrich (1774-1840)
Schelling saw man as a microcosm: the basic dynamic of
as the clearest representative of this trend, which he has
Nature is also at work in man. With man, Nature has reached
called the Northern Romantic tradition. Rosenblum also sug-
the end of its self-realisation because, in a sense, it has recre-
gests that there is a link between this European tradition in
ated itself, or its double. Man is Nature’s crowning achieve-
landscape painting and a similar tradition in America, exem-
ment. And of all man’s endeavours, the greatest and most
plified by Frederick Edwin Church (1826-1900), but he offers
divine is the creation of works of art through which man
no proof of this link. It seems possible, however, that the lines
expresses himself in the external world.
of influence can be traced through the Transcendentalists’
Schelling is a cardinal figure in the history of the philosophy
enthusiasm for German philosophy.
of art because he created the stereotype of the Romantic artist as a genius inspired by higher forces. In his System
The Therapeutic Fallacy
des transzendentalen Idealismus Schelling writes that genius
The idea of nature and the artist as gateways to the divine
is possible only in the arts, where he famously found ‘the
had important consequences for American art. For one thing,
expression of tranquillity and quiet greatness’ (‘der Ausdruck
the new concept of landscape and of landscape painting
der Ruhe und der stillen Grösse’; Schelling 2000: 291). And the
became linked to the idea of Manifest Destiny, which is ‘the
artist, in creating the work of art, is unconsciously driven by
belief that westward colonisation of America was not only a
a desire to fulfil an irrepressible natural urge within himself.
right but a sacred duty’ (Hughes 1997: 157). To the American
The artist’s genius is a gift from nature, granted at birth. Al-
mind, the continent was a land of plenty, most of which as
though Schelling is the locus classicus for this concept of the
yet unexplored, which had been created by God to be ex-
artist, such ideas were common currency among Early Ger-
plored, settled, and cultivated by the brave frontier man. If
43
44
the material world could be read like the Bible, then the mes-
sive book Kosmos was published in 1845. On the basis of
sage written down in it seemed to have been lifted straight
his wide-ranging research, supported by a global network
out of Genesis: submit the earth. In the name of Manifest
of correspondents and scientists who forwarded him their
Destiny explorers set out from the East coast to cross the
measurements of temperature, barometric pressure, rainfall,
continent, claiming the land they found and driving the Indi-
and other phenomena, Von Humboldt had reached an all-
ans before them. The classic formulation of Manifest Destiny
encompassing vision of the universe as one huge organism in
was written by the journalist William Gilpin and read to the
which everything is connected, a cosmos where, in his own
U.S. Senate in 1846: ‘The untransacted destiny of the American
words, there ‘is a unity in diversity of phenomena: a harmo-
people is to subdue the continent – to rush over this vast field
ny, blending together all created things, however dissimilar in
to the Pacific Ocean – to animate the many hundred mil-
form and attributes; one great whole animated by the breath
lions of its people, and to cheer them upward... to teach old
of life’ (o.c. 158). This inspired in him a great respect for all of
nations a new civilisation – to confirm the destiny of the hu-
nature which would become the root of the environmentalist
man race... Divine task! Immortal mission! Let us tread fast and
movement in America, where the English translation of Kos-
joyfully the open trail before us! Let every American heart
mos, published in 1848, was a huge success. As Aaron Sachs
open wide for patriotism to glow undimmed, and confide
remarks, Von Humboldt ‘cared about each element of nature
with religious faith in the sublime and prodigious destiny of
because every weed, stinging insect, and poisonous snake
his well-loved country’ (Hughes 1997: 190). The West, to the
played a crucial role in what he came to think of as particular
Americans, was a Promised Land that was there for the tak-
ecosystems, all of which seemed to thrive on biodiversity’
ing, a divine gift to God’s new chosen people.
(Sachs 2006: 52).
Not everyone agreed with this vision. A major dissenter was
Von Humboldt’s success coincided with the rise of Transcen-
the German explorer and scientist Alexander von Humboldt
dentalism and his influence on Thoreau was massive. What
(1769-1859), who was a great admirer of the young Ameri-
made Von Humboldt especially attractive to Transcenden-
can republic but never tired of castigating it for what he
talists was the fact that he saw man as an element in the
considered its two greatest moral blights: slavery and the
cosmos. This meant that man was not immune to changes in
oppression of indigenous Indian cultures. Von Humboldt
the ecosystem: there was an intrinsic link between man and
had become very famous for his expedition, in the company
his world. It also meant that the experience of nature could
of Aimé Bonpland, to South- and Central-America between
transform men, not only in a physical, but also in a spiritual
1799 and 1804. At the end of his journey Von Humboldt was
way; and that man could relate this spiritual renewal to his
received by president Jefferson and the two men would keep
fellow men. One of the ways this spiritual experience could
in contact through correspondence. Von Humboldt reached
be communicated was through landscape painting. Its great-
a new level of global fame when the first volume of his mas-
est American exponent was Frederick Edwin Church, who
45
46
painted huge canvases of sublime American nature that
political in character’ (o.c. 103). It included a series of badges,
carried the force of revelation. But this was not the end of
created by Daniel Martinez, that bore part of the slogan “I
art’s moral mission. By the 1880s art as religion had begun
can’t imagine ever wanting to be white”. Every visitor was
to mutate into something only slightly less transcendent in
issued such a badge at the admission desk. Another “work”
nature: art as therapy. This change profoundly affected the
on display was the infamous video of the Rodney King beat-
shape of a new American institution, the museum. The earli-
ing, showing Los Angeles police officers kicking a black man.
est American museums originated from private collections.
The question whether such works were art at all (a question
As Robert Hughes explains, these museums were supposed
that is especially salient in the Rodney King tape, which was
to ‘create zones of transcendence within the society’ (Hughes
not made as a work of art but filmed by a man who happened
1994: 180). The museum was conceived of as a kind of health
to be on the scene with a camcorder), let alone good art, took
spa, a space where nervous conditions could be soothed.
a back seat to their political and emotional urgency: the only
This idea was born from the fact that many collectors had
thing that mattered was their ability to raise consciousness
turned to collecting for personal comfort. ‘Some of them,
among the public about social injustice. Similarly, in the Sep-
notably Charles Freer and Isabella Stewart Gardner, were
tember 26, 1993 issue of The Washington Post, Camille Paglia
deeply neurasthenic creatures who looked to art to cure their
wrote that when she and artist Alison Maddex ‘toured the
nervous afflictions and thought it could do the same for the
Whitney’s rape exhibit this summer, we were appalled and
less well off’ (o.c. 181). This attitude was heavily influenced
incredulous. Visitors were wandering around with tears in
by yet another European import: the psychoanalysis of Sig-
their eyes, as rape victims recited their sorrows on a video
mund Freud, where art was seen as symptom, the sublimated
monitor. When the offerings of a major museum are indistin-
expression of suppressed desires and drives. But it resulted
guishable from the victimisation soap opera of television talk
in a concept of art that is still pervasive in American culture
shows, art has ceased to exist’ (Paglia 1995: 114). It certainly
and which Robert Hughes has called ‘the therapeutic fallacy,’
does seem to be the case that such exhibits transgress the
namely the idea that ‘works of art were moral in themselves
boundary that separates art from non-art. It is part of the
because, whether you knew it or not at first, they pointed the
business of this chapter to explain why and how.
way to higher truths and so did you good’ (o.c. 183). It is essentially this approach to art that fuelled the politically
Narrative Didactics
correct backlash against “offensive” art and the promotion of
The locus classicus for art as therapy is obviously Aristotle’s
issue-based art in the 1980s and 1990s. According to Arthur
Poetics. In the sixth chapter of this book, which has only been
C. Danto the 1993 Whitney Biennial was ‘a high-water mark
partially transmitted, Aristotle writes that ‘a tragedy is an
of the politically tumultuous 1980s’ (Danto 2003: 106). ‘The
imitation of an action which is serious and, having grandeur,
work presented was for the most part accusatory, and angrily
complete in itself, done in language seasoned with embel-
47
lishments, each appearing separately in different parts of the work, in dramatic rather than narrative form, accomplishing by way of pity and fear the catharsis of such feelings’ (Barnes 1995: 276). The idea of catharsis has proved very enduring. In ancient Greek it could mean two things, either the purgation of the body through laxatives and emetics or ritual purification in religion. In his discussion of tragedy Aristotle suggests that in a good play a similar catharsis can be accomplished for feelings like fear and pity: we are purged of them by seeing them represented. This, in essence, is the root of the therapeutic fallacy: the notion that art can somehow “cure” us of something. As Jonathan Barnes points out, there is much uncertainty about how this “purification” should be understood. The idea of art as catharsis also raises many objections, and the most important is that ‘to suppose that the primary rea-
48
son, or even a main reason, for encouraging productions of Oedipus is that they clean up our feelings is to turn art into emotional therapy’ (o.c. 279). But that is exactly the approach to art that underlies the culture wars, both on the Right and on the Left: art is supposed to be good for us. It is something to help us deal with the perplexities of life, or at least to help us become better citizens. As literary critic Kenneth Burke assures us, ‘poetry is produced for purposes of comfort, as part of the consolatio philosophiae’ (Burke 1973: 61). In recent philosophy about art and its social uses and effects several influential theories have been put forward that seem to fit into the tradition of the therapeutic fallacy. In Contingency, irony, and solidarity (1989), Richard Rorty claims that all people have what he calls a “final vocabulary”. This vocabulary is ‘a set of words which they employ to justify Arthur C. Danto
their actions, their beliefs, and their lives’ (Rorty 1989: 73).
49
50
God, justice, nature, our nation, or decency, along with a host
ways possible, books can suitably substitute for actual people.
of other words, can all function as parts of a final vocabulary:
Martha Nussbaum has addressed similar issues and is equal-
they are the words in the name of which people take moral
ly persuaded of literature’s ability to alter our relationships
stands. Such a final vocabulary ‘is “final” in the sense that if
with other people. In Love’s Knowledge (1990) she suggests
doubt is cast on the worth of these words, their user has no
that books can be “friends” to us in a way similar to our hu-
noncircular argumentative recourse. Those words are as far
man friends. She illustrates this with an example from her
as he can go with language; beyond them there is only help-
own personal history as ‘a child whose best friends were, on
less passivity or a resort to force’ (ibid.). Rorty further intro-
the whole, novels’ (Nussbaum 1990: 11) and with the fictional
duces a type of person whom he calls an “ironist,” namely
example of David Copperfield, who also turns to books for
someone who ‘has radical and continuing doubts about the
companionship. Nussbaum next asks ‘what kinds of “people,”
final vocabulary she currently uses, because she has been
as friends, novels are’ (o.c. 236). She has tried to answer that
impressed by other vocabularies’ (ibid.). So Rorty implies that
question in a series of books that argue for a philosophy of
our final vocabulary is not fixed: although we might cling
the emotions that also allows for a theory of the social uses
to it and defend it with great passion, to the point of being
and effects of the novel. She has developed the arguments
willing to give up our lives for the ideals expressed in it, the
for literature most clearly in Poetic Justice (1995), where she
contents of our vocabulary may shift throughout our life as a
explains how reading novels can be useful to reach con-
result of inner changes, emotional growth, or through contact
sidered judgements in the courts or in our dealings with
with other people’s vocabularies. The ironist is someone who
other people about whom we know very little and towards
accepts this fluidity and might even go one step further: the
whom we might otherwise feel distrust. This argument was
ironist is not unlikely to go out into the world to meet new
then further elaborated in Cultivating Humanity (1997), where
vocabularies to make sure that there is not some vocabulary
Nussbaum wants to ‘ask about the relationship of a liberal
out there that might be more worthwhile than the one she is
education to citizenship’ (Nussbaum 1997: 8). She feels that
currently living in.
the global and multicultural character of contemporary soci-
Considering the ironist’s quest for a more suitable vocabulary
ety requires future students of the world to be able to tackle
Rorty claims that ‘our doubts about our own characters or
the many differences between people and cultures they are
our own culture can be resolved or assuaged only by enlarg-
bound to encounter. To this end she argues for an educa-
ing our acquaintance. The easiest way of doing that is to
tion that ‘liberates the mind from the bondage of habit and
read books’ (o.c. 80) because in books we can find a ‘detailed
custom, producing people who can function with sensitivity
description of what unfamiliar people are like’ (o.c. xvi). To
and alertness as citizens of the whole world. This is what
enlarge our acquaintance with other vocabularies we should
Seneca means by the cultivation of humanity’ (ibid.). Such
ideally meet as many people as we can. Since this is not al-
an education must foster ‘the capacity for critical examina-
51
52
tion of oneself and one’s traditions’ (o.c. 9) and train people
of the kind of reasoning that a judge should engage in when
‘to see themselves not simply as citizens of some local region
judging criminals. The novel teaches us that ‘governments,
or group but also, and above all, as human beings bound to
wherever they are, should attend to citizens in all their indi-
all other human beings by ties of recognition and concern’
viduality and variety, responding in a sensitive way to histori-
(o.c. 10). At the heart of this educational enterprise lies what
cal and personal contingencies’ (PJ 45). Just like the charac-
Nussbaum calls ‘the narrative imagination. This means the
ters in a novel, citizens and criminals have a personal history
ability to think what it might be like to be in the shoes of a
that is entirely unique and that should not be set aside when
person different from oneself [and] to be an intelligent reader
judging their actions. In this sense Nussbaum sees the liter-
of that person’s story’ (o.c. 10-11). And what better way for
ary artist as ‘the equalizer of his age and land,’ a description
students, and citizens in general, to learn to read other peo-
she borrows from Walt Whitman (PJ 4): the literary artist who
ple’s stories than by reading novels, which are the paradigm
writes a novel or a poem (for Nussbaum stresses that her
of such human narratives?
views also apply to poetry) makes us aware of the fact that
Nussbaum suggests that the distinguishing feature of the
other people, no matter who they are, are very similar to us
novel is its close attention to the intricacies of individual
in their vulnerability and in the things they care about or the
lives and the complex contexts in which they are situated.
ways they care about them.
Novels help us understand the particular lives of particular
But the question this raises and that interests us most is how
people by giving us detailed insight into their daily doings,
this comes about. Nussbaum talks of ‘modes of interaction’
their ways of expressing themselves, and even their deepest
that are at work in the novel and that can fundamentally
thoughts and feelings. According to Nussbaum the novel is
change readers’ outlook on the world. Nussbaum claims that
‘a morally controversial form, expressing in its very shape
‘good literature is disturbing’ and that it ‘summons power-
and style, in its modes of interaction with its readers, a nor-
ful emotions, it disconcerts and puzzles. It inspires distrust
mative sense of life. It tells its readers to notice this and not
of conventional pieties and exacts a frequently painful con-
this, to be active in these and not those ways. It leads them
frontation with one’s own thoughts and intentions’ (PJ 5). But
into certain postures of the mind and heart and not others’
what are those ‘modes of interaction’? Nussbaum explains
(PJ 2). Novels stress how differences in education or social
that they have to do with the style of the novel and illustrates
circumstances form a person’s character and their actions. By
this elaborately with the example of Charles Dickens’ novel
sketching such a broad context for human action the novel
Hard Times (1853). Nussbaum describes how Dickens manipu-
is ‘a paradigm of a style of ethical reasoning that is context-
lates our experience as readers through his style and choice
specific without being relativistic’ (PJ 8). In this respect the
of words. By presenting one character in an ironic manner
novel is a fine example of the kind of thinking governments
and another character in a sentimental way, he directs our
should deploy when dealing with their citizens and especially
sympathies and instructs us about which characters and
53
54
actions to approve of and of which to disapprove. In fact,
pact that reasons sometimes have on us as feeling persons.
‘the structure of the novel – its ways of presenting the world
We feel the force of reasons’ (Siegel 1997: 48) and this force
to us and its enticements to identify ourselves with certain
in turn moves us in a dual way: first, felt reasons “move” us
characters rather than others – set us up, if we respond to
in the sense that they are emotionally gripping; but second,
them, in a posture of the heart and mind that is not one of
they also “move” us in the sense that they can cause us to
sceptical indifference, that does not feel that anything at all
act in a certain way, literally putting us into motion to act. It
that happens to these people is as good as every other thing’
is clear that there is a degree of similarity between Rorty’s
(PJ 83). But this does not really explain anything. The effect
final vocabularies and Siegel’s felt reasons: in both cases we
that the novel has upon the reader is explained in terms of
are dealing with a kind of reasons for our actions that can-
certain stylistic strategies cunningly deployed by the author.
not be fully explained with reasons. We cannot argue for our
But a more fundamental explanation would make us under-
final vocabularies. Similarly, a felt reason is a reason with a
stand how such strategies and stylistic devices come about
surplus of visceral power that is itself not subject to reason: it
and why they are at all successful. Nussbaum does not really
is a feeling that attaches itself to the reason. But Siegel ap-
explain, she simply describes, albeit in great detail and with
pears to be aware of the fact that to simply speak of felt rea-
much sensitivity, the literary strategies the effectiveness of
sons without any further explanation is unsatisfactory for at
which needs to be explained. To say that the novel (or art in
one point he exclaims: ‘But what are “felt” reasons? Are they
general) moves us because the author (or any artist) has used
some weird sort of abstract entity, altogether different from
a series of stylistic devices designed to elicit certain emo-
more garden variety sorts of reasons?’ Clearly, they are not:
tions, feelings, and evaluations in the reader is circular. It
‘Felt reasons [...] are ordinary reasons whose power to move
begs the question what it is about these stylistic devices that
people is made obvious or manifest by the way in which
makes them effective. Why does art move us?
those reasons, and the person for whom they are reasons,
A similar problem arises in the work of another, less well-
are portrayed. Felt reasons are not a different kind of reasons:
known, philosopher. In Rationality Redeemed? (1997) Harvey
they are rather a particular kind of presentation of reasons’
Siegel makes a plea for rational education. Siegel feels a
(o.c. 52). But this simply begs the question: if felt reasons be-
good education should equip young people with the skills
come powerful through the way they are presented or pack-
they will need to reflect upon and justify their choices and
aged, we should like to know what it is about this packaging
beliefs in life. Siegel also feels that novels have an important
that makes these ordinary reasons so much more powerful
part to play in this project. To explain how novels do this he
as to pack an emotional wallop. This is a problem similar to
introduces the concept of “felt reasons”. Despite their ratio-
the one we found in Nussbaum. Both Nussbaum and Siegel
nal nature reasons sometimes have a visceral quality: their
claim that the emotive force of the novel and felt reasons
urgency can be deeply felt. This visceral quality is ‘the im-
respectively has something to do with the form in which they
55
are presented. Neither explains how and why these forms,
In Philosophy in a New Key (1942) and especially in Feeling and
these stylised presentations, are at all effective. Or, to put it
Form (1953) Langer proposes that we see art as a form of sym-
in a more general way: what is it about art that moves us?
bolisation: ‘Art is the creation of forms symbolic of human
And how does this come about? What does art (the novel, the
feeling’ (FF 40). But this definition immediately entails a new
poem, the special presentation of reasons) do to move us?
question, for what is a symbol? ‘A symbol,’ Langer states, ‘is any device whereby we are enabled to make an abstraction’
56
Feeling and Form
(FF xi). So works of art are manmade objects that present us
The question of the nature of art was of central concern to
with an abstraction of human feeling. How must we under-
Susanne K. Langer (1895-1985) and her philosophy of living
stand this? Langer explains that symbols are ‘vehicles for the
form is a very good point of reference for the kind of discus-
conception of objects’ (PNK 60-61). She distinguishes concep-
sion upon which we are about to engage. In fact, Nussbaum
tions from concepts. ‘Concepts are abstract forms embodied
herself at times comes very near the kind of reasoning we
in conceptions; their bare presentation may be approximated
find in Langer. In Love’s Knowledge she states that it is one
by so-called “abstract thought,” but in ordinary mental life
of her central claims ‘that there is, with respect to any text
they no more figure as naked factors than skeletons are seen
carefully written and fully imagined, an organic connection
walking the street. Concepts, like decent living skeletons,
between its form and its content’ (Nussbaum 1990: 4). Nuss-
are always embodied’ (PNK 61). So conceptions would seem
baum has stressed this organic connection repeatedly, as
to be more elaborate presentations of concepts. ‘A concept
when she claims that ‘in the reading of a literary text, there
is all that a symbol really conveys. But just as quickly as the
is a standard of correctness set by the author’s sense of life,
concept is symbolised to us, our own imagination dresses
as it finds its way into the work’ (o.c. 9). Unfortunately Nuss-
it up in a private, personal conception’ (PNK 71-72). If, for ex-
baum never really thinks through the organic metaphor for
ample, we think of a circle, we do not think of a concept (all
the way art works. Neither does she give a very satisfactory
the points in a field that are at the exact same distance from
account of how a “sense of life” may be present within a work
a given point) but we usually imagine a specific circle. The
beyond her claims about the stylistic devices used by authors
circle I have in mind may be smaller than the one you have
to steer the reader’s mind and feelings in a desired direction.
in mind, it might be drawn in a different colour than yours or
But these are exactly the kinds of issues Langer’s work does
against a different background, but whatever its imaginary
clarify. One of Langer’s central questions is how art moves
properties, it will still be a circle according to its geometrical
us. What kind of objects are works of art? What is their logi-
definition. The same thing applies when we think of the con-
cal structure and how does this structure affect the spectator
cept of a house. ‘Consider a photograph, a painting, a pencil
or reader? To answer these questions is to enter into a fresh
sketch, an architect’s elevation drawing, and a builder’s dia-
relationship with works of art.
gram, all showing the front view of one and the same house.
57
58
With a little attention, you will recognise the same house in
a periodic measure: it is the perceived connectedness of suc-
each representation [because] each one of the very different
cessive events. Langer now suggests that works of art ‘bear
images expresses the same relation of parts, which you have
a close logical similarity to the forms of human feeling’ (FF
fastened on in formulating your conception of the house. [...]
27), which are rhythmic in the sense just explained. Langer’s
Likewise, another person’s conception of that same house
preferred example to illustrate this is music, which shows
will agree in its essential pattern with the pictures and with
us ‘forms of growth and of attenuation, flowing and stow-
your conception, however many private aspects it may have’
ing, conflict and resolution, speed, arrest, terrific excitement,
(PNK 71).
calm, or subtle activation and dreamy lapses – [...] the great-
So works of art are abstractions or symbols of conceptions of
ness and brevity and eternal passing of everything vitally
human feelings. To explain this Langer famously introduced
felt. Such is the pattern, or logical form, of sentience; and the
the term “living form”. Human life and feeling are filled with
pattern of music is that same form worked out in pure, mea-
movement. ‘All life is rhythmic’ (FF 126) and is subject to
sured sound and silence. Music is a tonal analogue of emotive
processes of flowering and decay, birth and death, and all
life. Such formal analogy, or congruence of logical structures,
physical and mental developments in-between. Langer here
is the prime requisite for the relation between a symbol and
makes very specific use of the word “rhythm,” which she de-
whatever it is to mean. The symbol and the object symbol-
fines as ‘a functional involvement of successive events’ (PA
ised must have some common logical form’ (ibid.). Living
52). This means that ‘a rhythmic pattern arises whenever the
form ‘expresses life – feeling, growth, movement, emotion, and
completion of one distinct event appears as the beginning of
everything that characterises vital existence’ (FF 82). As these
another. The classic example is the swinging of a pendulum.
statements suggest, ‘the word “feeling” must be taken here
The momentum of its drop drives the weight upward in the
in its broadest sense, meaning everything that can be felt, from
opposite direction, and builds up the potential energy that
physical sensation, pain and comfort, excitement and repose,
will bring it down again; so the first swing prepares the sec-
to the most complex emotions, intellectual tensions, or the
ond; the second swing was actually begun in the first one,
steady feeling-tones of a conscious human life’ (PA 15).
and similarly, after that, each swing is prepared by the one
Langer’s concept of living form invites two remarks. First, it
before. The result is a rhythmical series’ (PA 51). But rhythm
might seem questionable to define feeling in such a broad
need not be serial or periodic. Whenever an action or move-
way. But this is necessary to the enterprise, for since art can
ment seems to beget another, a sense of rhythm manifests
be and is about everything that falls within human experi-
itself. All succession is rhythmic, even if it is not periodic.
ence, any theory that tries to say anything about art will have
This explains ‘why a tennis player, a wheeling bird, and a
to embrace the full scope of human experience. It will be up
modern dancer who does not necessarily repeat any motion
to the subsequent theory to specify this in view of the indi-
may exhibit rhythm, too’ (PA 52). So the rhythm of life is not
vidual kinds of art. Second, it is of vital importance to stress
59
60
that Langer speaks of a logical similarity between life and art.
art, but not abstract art, is a contradiction in terms’ (HC 323).
This means that the relationship between art and the feel-
Obviously, Arendt was not writing about Expressionism as
ings it expresses is a formal relationship. This formal aspect
a movement in the history of art, but about expressiveness
brings up the question of expression. If art expresses human
in the literal sense of venting one’s emotions in an immedi-
feeling, we must understand what “expression” means here.
ate way. What is created in art is not self-expression (which
It is a common mistake to think that art is a direct expression
does not require creation or art at all) but expressive form,
of the artist’s personal feelings. When Langer claims that art
‘perceptible forms expressive of human feeling’ (PS 84). The
works are symbols and therefore abstractions, she introduces
artist has conceived of human feeling and found a form that
an element of distance. The artist does not express his feel-
expresses this feeling.
ings directly but seeks a formal analogue for them. He steps
Langer was not entirely original in her use of the term “living
back, contemplates the feeling he wants to express in his
form”. She explicitly conceives it as a further development
work and then sets about finding a fitting form. ‘What art
and refinement of Clive Bell’s infamous “significant form” (FF
expresses is not actual feeling, but ideas of feeling; as lan-
31-33). But the term “living form” itself already appears in the
guage does not express actual things and events but ideas of
work of Friedrich Schiller, who introduces it in the fifteenth
them’ (FF 59). So we must be wary of ‘the confusions between
letter of his epistolary treatise Über die ästhetische Erziehung
feeling shown and feeling represented, symptom and symbol’
des Menschen (1795). Schiller’s thoughts on art are structured
(FF 184). It is of paramount importance to keep in mind ‘that
dialectically. He conceived of humans as beings with two
the feeling in a work of art is something the artist conceived as
basic but conflicting drives, the material or “sense drive”
he created the symbolic form to present it, rather than some-
(‘Stofftrieb’) and the rational or “form drive” (‘Formtrieb’). The
thing he was undergoing and involuntarily venting in an ar-
sense drive spurs man towards life in its organic and sensual
tistic process’ (FF 176). This act of conceiving transforms the
sense. It is also linked to individual existence and concerns
feeling from something experienced into something represent-
everything that has to do with our own particular experience
ed. ‘But as soon as an expressive act is performed without in-
of being alive. The form drive, on the other hand, represents
ner momentary compulsion it is no longer self-expressive; it is
the universal element within us, the reason that is common
expressive in the logical sense. It is not a sign of the emotion
to all human beings. These two drives are in constant dynam-
it conveys, but a symbol of it; instead of completing the natu-
ic intercourse with each other, seeking the balance of human
ral history of a feeling, it denotes the feeling, and may merely
life to make sure that our lives are neither too focused on one
bring it to mind [...]. When an action acquires such a meaning
or the other. For Schiller, art has an important role to play in
it becomes a gesture’ (PNK 152). Hannah Arendt was point-
this balancing act because it always presents us a message
ing in the same direction when she declared, in a footnote in
(which pleases the rational form drive) in an attractive shape
her great book The Human Condition (1958), that ‘expressionist
(which is agreeable to the sense drive). As such, art is “living
61
62
form” (‘lebendige Gestalt’): a fusion of mind and matter, of rea-
present’ (PA 66). In her Introduction to Symbolic Logic (1937)
son (and morality) with sensuality (or beauty). This dialectic
Langer had also spoken of ‘logical intuition’ as ‘the power of
of feeling (sense experience in a broad sense that comes very
discovering analogies’ (Innis 2009: 14). This formulation is
near Langer’s) and form (the higher meanings for which the
a clue to the fact that Langer’s concept of intuition is much
sense experience of the work of art is the vehicle) is the main
indebted to Gestalt psychology, which holds that ‘when sen-
theme throughout all of Schiller’s writings. It would also
sory elements are combined, they form some new pattern of
influence Hegel’s philosophy of art. And as we shall see in
configuration. Put together a group of musical notes, [...] and
Chapter Two, Hegel’s dialectical worldview resurfaces in Ar-
something new – a melody or a tune – emerges from their
thur C. Danto’s notion of “the transfiguration of the common-
combination, something that did not exist in any of the indi-
place,” which states that objects become works of art because
vidual elements (the notes). Stated succinctly: The whole is
meanings are embodied in them.
different from the sum of its parts’ (Schultz and Schultz 1996:
Langer calls the expressive form ‘an apparition given to
322). That is why Langer can say that we know the import of
our perception’ (o.c. 86). This takes us to the heart of what
a work of art by an act of intuition: the work of art is a Gestalt,
is at stake in her work. To make this clear we must turn to
something immediately perceived as a whole. In the first vol-
Langer’s concept of intuition. As early as The Practice of Phi-
ume of Mind she writes that a work of art ‘presents the sem-
losophy (1930) Langer wrote that intuition ‘is not a method,
blance of feeling so directly to logical intuition that we seem
but a natural phenomenon. It occurs; it cannot be invoked or
to perceive feeling itself in the work’ (MI 67). She even claims
taught. Moreover, its result is not knowledge, but that fun-
that ‘artistic import requires no interpretation; it requires a
damental experience which knowledge is about [...]. It is our
full and clear perception of the presented form’ (MI 84).
source of direct contact with the world’ (Innis 2009: 13-14).
It is a core tenet of Langer’s philosophy that ‘a work of art is
As Robert E. Innis explains in his survey of Langer’s work,
always a prime symbol,’ (FF 369) which is ‘the expression of
intuition ‘supplies us with the given in experience’ (o.c. 14).
human consciousness in a single metaphorical image’ (PA
This means that Langer conceives of intuition as our source
53). This symbol could ‘be analysed, in that its articulation
of felt experience. In the first volume of Mind (1967) she calls
may be traced and various elements in it distinguished; but
it ‘the basic intellectual function’ (MI 128) and compares it
it can never be constructed by a process of synthesis of ele-
to Locke’s ‘natural light’. In Problems of Art (1957), here she
ments, because no such elements exist outside it. They only
also refers to Locke, she calls it ‘the fundamental intellectual
occur in a total form’ (FF 369). Speaking of books Langer says
activity, which produces logical or semantical understand-
that they are ‘like a life: all that is in it is really of a piece’
ing. It comprises all acts of insight or recognition of formal
(PNK xi). ‘A work of art is a single, indivisible symbol,’ writes
properties, of relations, of significance, and of abstraction and
Langer, ‘although a highly articulated one; it is not, like a
exemplification. [...] Intuition is not true or false, but simply
discourse (which may also be regarded as a single symbolic
63
64
form), composite, analysable into more elementary symbols
ing that is not analysable into atomic parts. Put another way,
[...]. It may, indeed, be analysed, in that its articulation may
Langer is challenging the early Wittgenstein’s picture theory
be traced and various elements in it distinguished; but it can
of language and transforms it from the inside out. That is
never be constructed by a process of synthesis of elements,
why Robert E. Innis writes that Langer’s work deals with
because no such elements exist outside it. They only occur
‘meaning after language’ (Innis 2009: 48), although I would
in a total form’ (FF 369). Every good work of art is of a piece.
modify the expression to “meaning beyond language” because
This is related to the aspect of perception that is tradition-
Langer does not give up on language (after all, literature is
ally called hololepsis, the seizing of the whole that turns a
one of the great arts) but tries to show that meaning is pos-
work into something more than ‘a mere aggregate of separate
sible, and logically possible, beyond the limits of discursive
items’ (Armstrong 2000: 92). As John Armstrong explains,
language. To accomplish this, she broadens Wittgenstein’s
‘there is no sense in which a heap can be complete’ because
picture theory. Simply put, Wittgenstein’s theory says that
‘nothing in its own nature determines [its] maximum’ (ibid.).
sentences are propositions that logically represent a state of
To be complete, a work must have an internal dynamic that
affairs in the world. In this sense they are a logical picture
determines its limits. This is essentially what Aristotle meant
of reality. Words are names of things and sentences describe
when he said a good play should have a beginning, a middle,
how these things are related to each other. The truth-value
and an end. ‘His concern is with the way in which features
of a proposition depends upon the question whether a state
of the work can be seen to have internal qualities of develop-
of affairs in the outside world corresponds to its structure.
ment – a development which can be seen to start and can
Sentences that do not represent such a picture of the world
reach a conclusion. When the end does come, it has the char-
are essentially senseless. This means that all evaluative and
acter of finishing something rather than of being an arbitrary
expressive language, including ethics, aesthetics, religion,
halt. The end, as it were, makes sense in relation to what has
and metaphysics, are beyond the pale of meaning. In fact,
come before. Equally, the opening is not just a chance start
the only meaningful propositions are those of the natural
but seizes the origin of the process to be followed through’
sciences, which cannot say anything about what is really
(o.c. 93). As we shall see in a subsequent chapter, even works
important in life: love, art, religion. That is why Wittgenstein,
of art that are (partly) improvised or open-ended adhere to
after finishing the Tractatus (1921), felt he was through with
this structure because they are conceived to be improvised
philosophy, which was really a lot of talk about nothing. The
or open-ended. This is why a film indeed need not, as Godard
final proposition of his book famously states that ‘whereof
once quipped, produce beginning, middle, and end necessar-
one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent’ (Tractatus 7;
ily in that order.
Sluga and Stern 1996: 11). Not because such things are not
Seeing the art symbol as a prime symbol means that Langer
important, but because language simply fails to communi-
accepts the possibility of a logical representation of mean-
cate anything meaningful about them. Langer would prob-
65
66
ably have amended this final proposition to ‘whereof one
not determined yet, because there are many possible ways of
cannot speak, thereof one must make religion, ritual, and,
developing the composition’ (FF 121). This development, the
most essentially, art’. Langer agrees with Wittgenstein that
composition of the work itself, will often be a process of trial
the human mind creates a picture of the world and that this
and error. But the commanding form will guide this process
picture is logical. But the logic that guides Langer’s idea of
as a kind of blueprint because it is ‘the general Gestalt [that]
picture-making is not the discursive logic of science, but the
serves as a measure of right and wrong, too much and too
symbolic logic of living forms. What cannot be said in discur-
little, strong and weak’ (FF 122). In this sense, the work of
sive language can be expressed metaphorically, in ritual and
art enforces its own rules. Writers sometimes speak of the
art. A work of art is also a picture of the world, but it is not a
universe of their novel and of the fact that this universe does
scientific picture. As Robert E. Innis has stated, ‘a picture for
not allow them to write whatever they please. This is exactly
her is a symbol, not a duplicate. It shares only “salient fea-
the kind of restriction the commanding form would impose
tures” with what it is a symbol of (PNK 68), a “certain propor-
upon an artist. Sometimes the artist will simply have a nag-
tion of parts” (69). Saliency is contrasted with irrelevancy’ (Innis
ging feeling that something about the work is not right and
2009: 40). There are many essential things in the world and in
will keep tinkering with it until this feeling is dispelled. Very
life which discursive projections cannot adequately express
often the commanding form will command the artist to “kill
or convey. These things open up the ‘unexplored possibility of
his darlings” in order to make the living form reach its full
a genuine semantic beyond the limits of discursive language’
potential. I suggest that it is something like the commanding
(PNK 86). Where language fails, man will look for other means
form that Nussbaum was referring to when she wrote about
of expression. Therefore, ‘the field of semantics is wider than
‘a standard of correctness set by the author’s sense of life, as
that of language’ (PNK 87).
it finds its way into the work’ (Nussbaum 1990: 9). But instead
Speaking of works of art as prime symbols, or Gestalten, im-
of looking for this standard of correctness within the formal
plies an organic view of their form. This view is obviously also
character of the work of art, Nussbaum tried to find it in the
present in Langer’s discussion of the creation of works of art.
supposed discursive nature of narrative.
To explain how works of art come about Langer introduces
Such a confusion of art with discourse as we find in Nuss-
the notion of “commanding form”, which is ‘the fundamental
baum is a common error. Art shares its symbolic nature with
feeling to be explored and expressed. This is “the work of art
language, but at the same time there is a profound difference
in the artist’s head.” As soon as he conceives this matrix of the
between language and art. Every language has a vocabulary
work-to-be, he knows what must be its general structure, its
and a syntax. Within the vocabulary words have fixed mean-
proportions, its degree of elaboration’ (FF 389). Once this com-
ings that can be retrieved in a dictionary. If we apply the
manding form has been conceived, the work of art ‘is implicit
rules of syntax we can combine the smaller symbols that are
there, although its final, completely articulate character is
words into larger symbols that are propositions. Any proposi-
67
68
tion or sentence is in turn a single symbol and may be taken
also explains why it is impossible to translate a work of art
to symbolise or refer to a state of affairs in the world. A third
into another medium. There are no basic elements like words
characteristic of language, based on the first two of vocabu-
and no syntax. Therefore one cannot translate a painting into
lary and syntax, is its translatability. It is possible to translate
a poem, a novel into a sculpture, or a musical suite into prose.
a proposition into another language by substituting the cor-
There is, however, one art form that does seem to translate
rect words and applying the appropriate syntactic rules in the
works of art in a successful way and that is the cinema,
other language. Neither of these three features applies to the
where films are often based on novels or plays. This is un-
arts. Art, as we saw, does not have discriminate constituent
derstandable since novels, plays, and cinema share the abil-
parts analogous to words. To be sure, a picture, like language,
ity to tell a story in a quasi-discursive way. These arts allow
‘is composed of elements that represent various respective
of progressive narrative exposition. Art forms where linear
constituents in the object; but these elements are not units
narration is less prominent are not usually made into films.
with independent meanings’ (PNK 94). A line or a blot of co-
One rarely hears, for instance, of poems being filmed. Obvi-
lour may signify something in a work of art, but taken in iso-
ously, cinematic variations on poetry or visual poems have
lation it is meaningless. A patch of brownish paint may sug-
been a stock in trade of the experimental cinema for decades,
gest a figure in the background within the painting, but seen
but such works are rarely narrative. In fact, when the main-
in isolation it is simply an indiscriminate patch of brownish
stream cinema does translate poetry to the screen, it is usu-
paint. As regards syntax, there are no rules one can follow to
ally narrative poetry such as the Odyssey, the Iliad, Le Morte
create a work of art. There are certainly techniques one can
d’Arthur, or even The Raven. But nobody has yet attempted
learn to master, but there is no guidebook or recipe to help
the cinematic version of Emily Dickinson’s verse. However,
you make a good work of art with these techniques. That is
most films that adapt literary sources have to simplify and
why Langer speaks of the creation of works of art rather than
reduce the scope of the original work to an extensive degree
of merely making them. ‘The difference between creation and
and end up being little more than illustrations of the story
other productive work is this: an ordinary object, say a shoe,
that was told in more depth in the original work. But illustra-
is made by putting pieces of leather together; the pieces were
tion is an applied art and it is typical of the applied arts that
there before. [...] A picture is made by deploying pigments on
form is a function of content. The function or the message
a piece of canvas, but the picture is not a pigment-and-can-
of the object is primary and the form has been designed to
vas structure. The picture that emerges from the process is a
facilitate the function in the smoothest and most agreeable
structure of space, and the space itself is an emergent whole
way possible. The form is shaped as a vehicle for function or
of shapes, visible coloured forms. Neither the space nor the
meaning. That does not mean illustration can never rise to
things in it were in the room before’ (PA 28).
the level of the creative arts; it can, but to do so it would need
Finally, the total reference of works of art as prime symbols
to retain its expressive power outside the context for which
69
70
it was created. That is probably why we now value as art all
in art, is fictional. What is created in the visual arts is an im-
kinds of well-designed furniture and tools from the past, be
age of space. ‘This virtual space is the primary illusion of all
it Art Deco chairs, Biedermeier furniture, or space-age lamps
plastic art. Every element of design, every use of colour and
from the not-so-distant psychedelic 1960s: these objects
semblance of shape, serves to produce and support and de-
are now appreciated mainly for their form and not for their
velop the picture space that exists for vision alone. Being only
practical use. They have become objects to look at rather than
visual, this space has no continuity with the space in which
objects to use.
we live’ (FF 72). This last point is of cardinal importance. Art is
Virtual Spaces
about creating an illusion, an image. Art is fiction and noth-
In Feeling and Form Langer systematically addresses each
ing in it is real. The characters in a performance of Hamlet die,
of the arts to define its primary illusion, which is the basic
but not the actors performing them. The pasture captured in
way in which living form is expressed in that form of art.
paint is not an actual place, it is a painted image. A bronze
The primary illusion of an art form is the basic structure of
figure of a king is not the king himself but his likeness.
expression that all instances of that art have in common. So
We shall return to the importance of the fictional in art in a
it is necessarily a very general description of what unites all
subsequent chapter, but for our present purposes it is impor-
instances of that form of art. But at the same time it must be
tant to stress that what is represented in a work of art is not
sufficiently specific to clearly tell this art form apart from all
coextensive with the real world. A painting is not a window
the others. The primary illusion is the basic structural way
with a view of the world. It is a representation and interpre-
in which a given art form communicates its message. And
tation of the world. It is an image of the world seen. ‘Virtual
before we return to our discussion of Nussbaum we shall
space, being entirely independent and not a local area in ac-
look at the primary illusion of the visual arts. ‘The purpose of
tual space, is a self-contained, total system. [...] If, therefore,
all plastic art is to articulate visual form,’ Langer writes, ‘and
the artist presents semblances of objects, people, landscapes,
to present that form – so immediately expressive of human
etc., it is for their visual values as portions of perceptual
feeling that it seems to be charged with feeling – as the sole,
space’ (FF 75). In fact, all the elements that an artist intro-
or at least paramount, object of perception. This means that
duces in his image of space ‘have the purpose of making space
for the beholder the work of art must be not only a shape
visible and its continuity sensible. The space itself is a projected
in space, but a shaping of space – of all the space that he is
image, and everything pictured serves to define and organ-
given’ (FF 71). The visual arts, which are painting (and draw-
ise it. Even representation of familiar objects, if it occurs, is
ing), sculpture, and architecture, create what Langer calls
a means to this end’ (FF 77). It is clear that virtual space is
virtual space, which is not experiential space (namely space as
always subjective, experienced space. Even figurative art is
it is physically present around us) but a visual representation
never simply about presenting a representationally accurate
of space. The space created in a work of art, like everything
image of what it represents. All art, including representa-
71
72
tional art, expresses a way of seeing the world, or a mode of
ture, windows, etc. Very few pictures are so large as to fill our
experiencing space, and hence the vantage point of a sub-
physical field of vision completely at normal distance, i.e. at a
ject. Taking Cézanne as her example Langer writes that ‘the
distance that lets us see the forms presented in them to best
transformation of natural objects into pictorial elements took
advantage. Yet a picture is a total visual field. Its first office
place in his seeing, in the act of looking, not the act of paint-
is to create a single, self-contained, perceptual space, that
ing. Therefore, recording what he saw, he earnestly believed
seems to confront us as naturally as the scene before our
that he painted exactly what “was there”’ (FF 78). This means
eyes when we open them on the actual world. That is to say,
that art aims at truthfulness not in the sense of representa-
the illusion created in pictorial art is a virtual scene. I do not
tional fidelity but in the sense of a truthful representation of
mean a “scene” in the special sense of “scenery” – the picture
what our lived experience feels like. Rather than simply pro-
may represent only one object or even consist of pure decora-
vide us with a carbon copy of reality, art shows us reality as it
tive forms without representative value – but it always cre-
is perceived. For the visual arts this means that they show us
ates a space opposite the eye and related directly and essentially to
not simply space but how we perceive and experience space.
the eye. That is what I call “scene.”’ (FF 86). We shall elaborate
This is especially clear in the case of Modernism, which was
this concept of scene in the next section, but before we turn
an explosion of individual movements that sought the basic
to that discussion we must briefly address the primary illu-
elements that would allow of a faithful representation of
sion of sculpture and architecture. ‘Sculpture,’ Langer writes,
the world. Impressionism and Post-Impressionism sought to
‘even when it is wedded to a background as in true relief, is
accurately represent the way we actually perceive colour and
essentially volume, not scene. The volume, however, is not a
shapes. And Cubism is essentially about the perception of
cubic measure, like the space in a box. It is more than the
objects in space, as David Hockney pointed out when he said
bulk of the figure; it is a space made visible, and is more than
that Cubism was ‘about saving the possibility of figuration [...] at
the area which the figure actually occupies. The tangible form
the moment of its greatest crisis, what with the onslaught of
has a complement of empty space that it absolutely com-
photography with all its false claims to be able to accomplish
mands, that is given with it and only with it, and is, in fact,
such figuration better and more objectively. It was about as-
part of the sculptural volume. The figure itself seems to have
serting all the things photography couldn’t capture: time,
a sort of continuity with the emptiness around it, however
multiple vantages, and the sense of lived and living experi-
much its solid masses may assert themselves as such. The
ence’ (Weschler 2008: xix).
void enfolds it, and the enfolding space has vital form as a
Langer describes the primary illusion of each of the three
continuation of the figure’ (FF 88).
main plastic arts. The primary illusion of painting is what
Where a painting is framed in the sense that it is a total visu-
Langer calls “scene”. ‘Physically, a picture is usually one of
al field upon itself, regardless of its surroundings, a sculptural
several things in our sight; it is surrounded by a wall, furni-
work ‘is a centre of three-dimensional space. It is a virtual
73
74
kinetic volume, which dominates a surrounding space, and
We can profitably illustrate Langer’s idea of the ethnic do-
this environment derives all proportions and relations from
main with what Christopher Alexander has called The Time-
it, as the actual environment does from one’s self. The work
less Way of Building (1979), which takes “pattern languages” as
is the semblance of a self, and creates the semblance of a
the key to architecture. Just like Langer, Alexander puts the
tactual space’ (FF 91). Sculpture is the centre of its space in
human experience at the heart of architecture. The timeless
the same way that we, as subjects, are the centre of our expe-
way of building is ‘a process which brings order out of noth-
riential space. We are the perceiving subject that is aware of
ing but ourselves’ (Alexander 1979: 3). This process ‘lies deep
an object world that surrounds us. But all perception is fo-
in us: and only needs to be released’ (o.c. 14). That is why it
cused in us, the subject at the centre of experience. Sculpture
can be called timeless: it is inscribed almost in our genetic
is an image of this experience of selfhood, commanding the
make-up because it is a way of building that arises out of our
space it inhabits from its centre. This engagement with the
being and our needs as human beings who are alive in the
surrounding space is taken a step further in architecture. ‘As
world. Rather than build from the requirements of a mod-
scene is the basic abstraction of pictorial art, and kinetic volume
ern society that seeks to make optimal use of the minimal
of sculpture, that of architecture is an ethnic domain. Actually,
amount of space to store people in boxes that harbour them
of course, a domain is not a “thing” among other “things”; it
while awaiting the next day of work, the timeless way of
is the sphere of influence of a function or functions’ (FF 95).
building seeks to conceive of buildings and towns from the
This introduction of function into a discussion of architecture
needs of human being. The quality that distinguishes such
should not mislead us into thinking Langer was an adherent
timeless places (and place, for Alexander, encompasses ev-
of functionalism in architecture. The functions that she aims
erything as small as a room or a doorway and as large as a
to highlight are quite simply the vital aspects of human liv-
house, a town, or a major city) is that ‘they live’ (o.c. 9). Alex-
ing. ‘A culture is made up, factually, of the activities of human
ander suggests several ways of describing the timeless way,
being; it is a system of interlocking and intersecting actions,
but in the final reckoning it seems to be about ‘our liveliness’
a continuous functional pattern. [...] The architect creates
(o.c. 122) in a decidedly Langerian sense: a timeless place is
its image: a physically present human environment that
a place that is expressive of life entirely felt. The structure,
expresses the characteristic rhythmic functional patterns
or what Alexander calls the pattern language, that underlies
which constitute a culture. Such patterns are the alternations
a place that is alive ‘covers the whole of life’ (o.c. 230) and is
of sleep and waking, venture and safety, emotion and calm,
‘a tapestry of life’ (o.c. 347). To determine whether a building
austerity and abandon; the tempo, and the smoothness or
is alive and fit for human living all we have to do is consider
abruptness of life’ (FF 96). In this sense architecture is ‘a uni-
its effect upon our feeling. It is feeling and feeling alone that
verse created by man and for man,’ it is ‘the spatial semblance
determines whether a place is alive. ‘We can always ask our-
of a world’ (FF 97).
selves just how a pattern makes us feel. And we can always
75
76
ask the same of someone else. [...] It is not the same, at all,
stress of failure, of not being good enough, of never being al-
as asking someone his opinion. [...] It is also not the same as
lowed to be oneself. One must always check one’s behaviour
asking for a person’s taste. [...] And it is also not the same as
and be aware of the fact that the world is looking in. This is
asking what a person thinks of an idea. [...] It simply asks for
incredibly stressful, up to the point that it can make a person
feelings, and for nothing else’ (o.c. 290-291).
depressed. In any case, it will have a negative effect upon a
Since it is our feeling that determines aliveness, it is a quality
person’s performance, because people who are ill at ease are
that we can all recognise in buildings. For example, schools
never happy workers.
often make us feel uncomfortable and ill at ease just being
What kind of structure must a place have to be in any sense
there. This is often due to the fact that many schools were
alive rather than dead? Alexander claims that ‘every place
never built or designed for human living but for purposes of
is given its character by certain patterns of events that keep
surveillance, conditioning, and the inhibition of free move-
on happening there’ (o.c. 55). This reads like an almost literal
ment. Many schools are built to expose their inhabitants to
rendering of Langer’s principle of an ethnic domain, which is
the gaze of power. This often happens, quite perversely, in
determined by ‘characteristic rhythmic functional patterns’
the name of transparency or a sense of community. For ex-
(FF 96). And a building’s character is essentially determined
ample, many classrooms, especially in older school buildings,
by what happens there most often. For example, the structure
still have windows along the corridor, so that anyone pass-
of a family home should be determined by the rhythms of
ing in the hallway can see everything that happens within
family life, which includes such everyday acts as sleeping,
the classroom. This kind of transparency can put enormous
eating, resting, living together, taking showers, doing laundry,
stress, if not on the students, then on the teacher, who might
cooking, doing homework, repairing a bike, etc. Any build-
live with the daily fear of being exposed if a class is difficult
ing or town that is alive is thus created from the ‘fabric of
to handle and anyone passing can see their inability to keep
relationships’ that runs through them. This fabric ‘is the stuff
the group in check. The terror of visibility is built into many
that actually repeats itself’ in that place (Alexander 1979: 89).
schools, as it is built into many public buildings (just think
For a town or larger city this means that the structure and
of working environments where individual offices have glass
width of streets will be determined by their organic function
walls, making them look like cabinets or small cages in which
in the greater whole. Some roads are veritable arteries within
people seem to be both trapped and exposed). This is the
the fabric of a city, whilst others are simply narrow streets
inhumanity of much public building: instead of sheltering
lined with grocery shops. Similarly, on the small scale of the
us, it exposes us to something much more damaging than
family home, the kitchen should be structured around the
the natural elements, namely human cruelty. To be exposed
recurrent relationships between cooking, eating (and how
at all times to the gaze, and especially to the judging gaze,
we eat), being together for meals, and the storage of food,
of others and of one’s superiors, is to live under the constant
amongst others. The relationships that determine the alive-
77
78
ness of the kitchen are simply the activities that happen
to spend time with her children. The result of such situations
there most often and recurrently. These activities determine
is misery and unhappiness. A vivid memory I have of being
the quality (the sense of aliveness) of the place. And the
home sick from school as a child, is the silence in the neigh-
place will only feel alive as a kitchen if its structure allows of
bourhood and the occasional sounds of my mother’s pres-
all these activities. It will not do to simply cramp a stove, a
ence in the house. Otherwise, nothing could be heard. During
sink, some cupboards, and a table into a small room to pro-
the daytime, whole neighbourhoods seem to be deserted
duce a kitchen. For every place ‘there is a fundamental inner
areas. Homes are left abandoned, empty places that simply
connection between each pattern of events, and the pattern
spend the day waiting for someone to come home again. Be-
of space in which it happens’ (o.c. 92). Thus, every building,
cause such neighbourhoods are designed for the sole purpose
every neighbourhood, and every city is defined, ‘in everything
of providing “pleasant housing” (whatever that may be) for
that matters, by the patterns which keep on repeating there’
families, they end up being excluded from the fabric of every-
(o.c. 95).
day life. Every day people have to make the excursion to the
Our sense of life and our sense of well-being are determined
centre of town to do the shopping. Such towns are compart-
by the surroundings in which we have to (or may be doomed
mentalised. Furthermore, the crucial human activity of work
to) live out that life. ‘The specific patterns out of which a
has often been excised from them and transplanted to the
building or a town is made may be alive or dead. To the ex-
bigger cities, abandoning life in the town (or in the suburbs)
tent they are alive, they let our inner forces loose, and set us
to diurnal dreariness.
free; but when they are dead they keep us locked in inner
But the deadness or aliveness of a place is not simply deter-
conflict’ (o.c. 101). In fact, ‘a person is so far formed by his
mined by such macroscopic elements. The smallest structural
surroundings, that his state of harmony depends entirely on
detail of a place is crucial. A fine example are windows. Imag-
his harmony with his surroundings’ (o.c. 106). For instance,
ine an apartment bedroom with only one window looking out
in towns ‘where work and family life are physically separate,
into an air-shaft. All one sees are brick walls and other dreary
people are harassed by inner conflicts which they can’t es-
windows with the curtains drawn. No natural daylight ever
cape’ (o.c. 107-108). A person who lives in a neighbourhood of
enters the room, which is dark and damp, a dreadful place
family houses, such as many suburbs or small communities,
that is hardly conducive to a good night’s rest. Such windows
must commute to work and will come home at night feeling
are not windows at all: they are simply holes in the wall. A
tired and stressed. Children come home from work to find
crucial pattern in the pattern language of the home is there-
the house empty, and when their parents do arrive, they are
fore “the light on two sides pattern,” which says that any
irritable, stressed, and pressed for time. Similarly, a woman
room should have at least two windows in opposite walls, to
who wants to be a working mother will find herself having to
assure a continual presence of natural light in the place. ‘At
make impossible choices between her career and her desire
one time,’ Alexander writes, ‘it would have been unthinkable
79
to build any room, except a stable or a workshed, without
ing in particular, modern art is essentially about representing
windows on two sides. In our own time, all knowledge of
subjective point of view. And as David Hockney pointed out, it
this pattern is forgotten. Most rooms, most buildings, have
is Cubism that was probably most successful at this because
light from one side only. And even a “great” architect like Le
it let go of one-point perspective. Kepler reportedly once said
Corbusier, builds whole apartments, long and narrow, with
that painters are ‘educated into blindness’ through linear
windows only at the narrow end [...] with terrible glare and
perspective because it is an unnatural way of looking (Hyman
discomfort as results’ (o.c. 234-235). In fact, Alexander more
1998: 159). Hockney would certainly concur. Nobody in the
than once offers Le Corbusier as an example of how not to
real world ever perceives the world the way it is in a Vermeer
build housing. ‘Le Corbusier’s radiant city [...] actively makes
painting. We are constantly passing through the world and
us feel bad. It may excite our intellect, or our imagination; but
our vantage point is constantly shifting. Moreover, the field
when we ask ourselves how we shall feel in a place which is
of focus of our eyes is limited, which means that our eyes
really built like this, we know again, that it will not make us
are constantly moving about and bringing new details of the
feel wonderful. Again, our feeling is the way our knowledge of
world into focus. Just put two pens in front of you on the ta-
its functional emptiness presents itself to us’ (o.c. 289).
ble, about twenty centimetres apart. Then try looking at them
Fields of Vision
pen and then jump to the other. This is the way we perceive
What ties the three modes of virtual space together is the
and it is this mode of perception that was being expressed in
structurally implied point of view. Scene, kinetic volume,
Cubism, which tried to bring together in a two-dimensional
and ethnic domain are all organised from the point of view
plane the many aspects and acts of perception that consti-
of a subject, a perceiver. This is the human point of view, the
tute our integrated sense of the world.
human measure of things. In architecture it is the functions
This means that the supposed distortion we find in Cub-
of human life that organise the domain. In sculpture the
ist painting is not distortion at all: it is a profound form of
structure of the piece functions as a semblance of selfhood,
realism, very true to life in its expression of sight and of
structuring space around it as we structure the space around
our experience of space. ‘People complained about Picasso,’
us through our sentient presence in it. And painting always
Hockney told Lawrence Weschler, ‘how he distorted the
represents point of view because something is always shown
human face. I don’t think there are any distortions at all.
from a vantage point. Even if the work is abstract, this ab-
For instance, those marvellous portraits of his lover Marie-
straction is always the result of a process of reflection on how
Thérèse Walter which he made during the thirties; he must
we perceive, on what are the essentials of perception, or even
have spent hours with her in bed, very close, looking at her
on how we would perceive (and therefore can conceive of)
face. A face looked at like that does look different from one
the sublime, the divine, the metaphysical. Looking at paint-
seen at five or six feet. Strange things begin to happen to the
both at the same time. You cannot. Your eyes first look at one
80
81
82
eyes, the cheeks, the nose – wonderful inversions and repeti-
the experience of space,’ (o.c. 112) he said about these works. A
tions. Certain “distortions” appear, but they can’t be distor-
point of departure for a discussion of this aspect of his work
tions because they’re reality. Those paintings are about that
might be Santa Monica Blvd. (1979), a huge canvas that was
kind of intimate seeing. [...] Analytic Cubism in particular [...]
left incomplete. In it Hockney tried to paint the panorama of
was about perception – about the difficulty of perception. I’ve
what one could see cruising down Santa Monica Blvd. The
recently been reading a lot of books about Cubism, and I keep
driver moving at a slow pace through the streets is like a
coming upon discussions of intersecting planes and so forth,
latter-day version of Baudelaire’s flâneur, taking in the sights
as if Cubism were about the structure of the object. But re-
from his crib of chrome with leather furnishings. The paint-
ally, it’s rather about the structure of seeing the object. If there
ing itself is a collage of sights and details that Hockney had
are three noses, this is not because the face has three noses,
photographed and then collaged together to make one inte-
or the nose has three aspects, but rather because it has been
grated painting. But he was displeased with the result. When
seen three times, and that is what seeing is like’ (Weschler
he returned to the motif of the visual cruise through scenery,
2008: 22-23). Pierre Bonnard, although not a Cubist, is a great
the results were quite different. The expansive Mulholland
master in this rendering of the searching eye. Consider the
Drive: The Road To The Studio (1980) has let go of traditional
many paintings of his wife Marthe, made within the enclo-
one-point perspective and shows the landscape as it pre-
sure of their home (due to illness, Marthe was confined to
sented itself to Hockney on his daily drive to his studio. It is a
the house for the better part of twenty years). Especially the
collage of aspects and vistas that are assembled next to each
paintings made in the bathroom show Bonnard looking for a
other in a Cubist manner. Hockney has stressed that this way
vantage point that captures the experience of being in there
of painting is ‘more realistic than you might think. When
with her. In an impressive series of three late Baignoires the
you look at Mulholland Drive – and “Drive” is not the name
bathroom is almost reduced to an abstract play of colours
of the road, but the act of driving – your eye moves around
and forms. Perspective is constantly being anamorphosed
the painting at about the same speed as a car drives along
and distorted, being painted from impossible bird’s-eye view
the road’ (Hockney 1993: 67). Just like Picasso and Bonnard,
or from distances that appear unreal within the confines of
Hockney is trying in Mulholland Drive to convey the constantly
a room. Bonnard abandons linear perspective and paints the
shifting field of vision of the eye in movement. The result is
actual experience of looking, the way the eye roves through
in a very literal sense a field of vision, flattened out, almost
space and registers details that are then assembled into our
the way a child might draw a street, with houses flat along
experience of that space. Eyesight is never linear, it is always
both sides of the street, or with several aspects of a building
warped.
piled one on top of the other. Hockney produced several other
In his paintings and photographic collages of the 1980s David
pieces conveying this sense of actual perception. A Visit with
Hockney undertook a similar project. ‘I’m trying to convey
Christopher and Don, Santa Monica Canyon (1984), for example,
83
84
takes us on an experiential tour of the home of Christopher
experience of the world’ (o.c. 10). ‘The general perspective
Isherwood and Don Bachardy, supposedly distorting space in
[of these composite images] is built up from hundreds of
order to make it more expressive of actual lived experience.
micro-perspectives’ (o.c. 20). But by mid-May 1981 Hockney
The space around the house and the rooms within it appear
had abandoned the Polaroids and moved on to traditional
to have been folded open and welded together, along with
photographs, which came with the added advantage that
the constantly shifting view of the surrounding landscape,
they did not have a white frame around the image. Hockney
to create a dynamic impression of what it is actually like to
now started to assemble immensely complex photo-collages
move up to and about in the house. Interestingly, the Dutch
that were meant to convey the actual experience of looking
experimental filmmaker Frans Zwartjes had earlier created
at space. This meant that the images would have to translate
similar visual effects in his short films, notably the film Living
how we experience space as our eyes move through it, from
(1971) in which he takes us on a guided tour of his new home
one point of focus to the next, assembling a sense of the
by holding his camera at arm’s length from his own face
overall space in the mind. ‘Everything we look at is in focus
and having it tilt and turn in all directions, an almost literal
as we look at it,’ Hockney explains. ‘Now, the actual size of
expression of Ralph Waldo Emerson’s view of the self as a
the zone the eye can hold in focus at any given moment is
transparent eyeball, inviting us to turn our eyes upside down
relatively small in relation to the wider visual field, but the
to view the world in a fresh way (Sitney 2008: 7-8).
eye is always moving through that field and the focal point of
Hockney next took this new way of looking at space into
view, though moving, is always clear’ (o.c. 31). By using indi-
photography, which is the medium most closely connected to
vidual photographs to capture one such focal point of view,
(and structurally determined by) one-point perspective. His
Hockney could assemble large numbers of such photographs
first photographic experiments were made with a Polaroid
into overall impressions of a space. He soon found that this
camera. Hockney would photograph several aspects and de-
also allowed him to introduce an element of time in the im-
tails of his subject and afterwards assemble the Polaroid pic-
ages. Since the photographs were taken one at a time and
tures in a grid that offered a general overview of the subject,
since the eye of the viewer can only look at one photograph,
almost as if the complete picture had been made from one
or a limited cluster of photographs, at a time, the eye is con-
perspective. Only on closer inspection does it become clear
stantly moving over the composite image, travelling through
that every separate image has its own perspective. Hockney
space and time. In this way the composite image actually
correctly (and in Cubist tradition) assumed that this way of
conveys the experience of being in a room with other people,
looking was truer to life than linear perspective. ‘I realised
where several things happen at the same time. The fact that
that this sort of picture came closer to how we actually see,
these many things are all captured in individual (clusters of)
which is to say, not all at once but rather in discrete, sepa-
photographs allows the viewer to see everything in detail
rate glimpses, which we then build up into our continuous
(and in focus), which he would not be able to do if he were
85
86
actually present at the event. It is as if, in such collages, we
for example, The Scrabble Game, Jan. 1, 1983 (1983). This shows
are allowed to endlessly walk around in one moment of time
a group of people, including Hockney’s mother, engaged in
that is made to stand still for us. But in its overall impression,
a game of Scrabble. Each participant’s face has been photo-
the image does feel like it is an entirely realistic representa-
graphed at several moments in time, but the resultant pic-
tion of how we actually experience a room and the people in
tures have been assembled to create a dynamic impression
it in the moment. This, Hockney says, allowed him to deal with
of their faces as they move through different expressions
people’s ‘liveliness’ (o.c. 27). Instead of having to sit still, his
and moods. Since the collage was assembled through time,
models could now simply go about their business as Hockney
the game of Scrabble can even be reconstructed, with several
snapped away with his camera.
pictures showing how the words aggregate on the board (We-
Initially, Hockney would include his own feet in such collages
schler 2008: 39). Similarly, Luncheon at the British Embassy, To-
to ‘plant’ both the image and the viewer in a specific point
kyo, Feb. 16, 1983 (1983) gives an impression (made from Hock-
of view. From this vantage point he would take in the scene
ney’s seat at the table) of a dinner party and its several guests
and translate it into a collage expressive of the actual experi-
as perceived from one point of view. The image strongly re-
ence of looking at the scene; that is to say, not one overall
calls Gustave Caillebotte’s painting Le Déjeuner (1876), an op-
image created through linear perspective, but an assembly of
pressively melancholy depiction of the elaborate dinner table
individual points of focus that, in themselves, are made with
at the home of the artist’s mother, painted from the vantage
linear perspective (that is to say, with a camera), but which
point of the artist himself. Like many of Caillebotte’s other
together do not add up to anything resembling such a tra-
paintings the image has a heavily anamorphosed perspective
ditional perspective. Impressive examples are both Sitting in
that is reminiscent of the way straight lines can become bent
the Zen Garden at the Ryoanji Temple, Kyoto, Feb. 1983 (1983) and
in a photograph. We see this ravine-like tilt of space also in
Walking in the Zen Garden at the Ryoanji Temple, Kyoto, Feb. 1983
his famous depiction of Rue de Paris; temps de pluie (1877) and
(1983). The former image shows an impression of the tem-
in his mighty Jeune homme à sa fenêtre (1875) (see Distel et al.
ple’s raked garden from one point of view, the latter gives an
1995: 194, 116, 148).
impression of the garden as Hockney is walking through it.
Hockney’s greatest masterpiece in this kind of collage is un-
‘When I first pieced them together,’ Hockney says, ‘I thought I
doubtedly Pearblossom Hwy., 11-18th April 1986 (Second Version)
had made a photograph without perspective’ (Hockney 1993:
(1986), ‘a panoramic assault on Renaissance one-point per-
100). Equally impressive are the highly subjective views of
spective’ (Hockney 1993: 112) that looks almost like a paint-
everyday places, such as his impression of a Telephone Pole,
ing of a stretch of highway in the desert, with some traffic
Los Angeles, Sep. 1982 (1982). As Hockney’s prowess in this new
signs, several trees, and some litter on the side of the road.
manner of photographic collage grew, the images became
Hockney explains that ‘it took me two days out there at that
more and more complex, and more and more lifelike. Take,
intersection in the desert to photograph all of those details;
87
88
I had to climb on a ladder, for example, to get the head-on
may be limited in scope, but we never see anything in a blur
shots of the stop sign, and for that matter to get the proper
(at least not under normal conditions and with healthy eyes):
down-gazing vantages of the foreground asphalt. Those beer
what the eyes see, they see in focus.
cans to the side, I had to get right up close to them and then
This brief overview of Hockney’s experiments in painting and
photograph them from an angle which subsequently would
photography can hope to convey but a small portion of the
meld with all the surrounding shots I was taking. And all of
artist’s insights in the art of representing the actual felt expe-
that is what accounts for the sense of immediacy, of close-
rience of space and sight. But it has convinced Hockney that
ness, of being right there’ (Weschler 2008: 176). Hockney’s
Cubism is probably the most important thing that happened
investigations into vision would eventually lead him to a
in the art of the twentieth century and that it is the aesthetic
revolutionary insight in the visual techniques of great paint-
question that contemporary art will have to return to sooner
ers of the past. This is his famous hypothesis, formulated in
or later because too many issues are still left unresolved. To
his book Secret Knowledge (2001), that artists of the past would
his mind, abstract and conceptual art, which would come to
sometimes use a camera obscura and other optical devices
dominate art in the latter half of the twentieth century, are
to help them achieve realistic effects in their paintings. Al-
temporary excursions and not the major line that art should
though controversial, Hockney’s argument is often extremely
be following. ‘The great misinterpretation of twentieth cen-
persuasive. It also overturned the traditional view of early
tury art is the claim advanced by many people, especially
masters as “primitives,” especially in the case of the Flemish
critics, that Cubism of necessity led to abstraction, that Cub-
primitives. With regard to Van Eyck’s famous altar piece with
ism’s only true heritage was this increasing tendency toward
the Adoration of the Lamb (ca. 1432), Hockney suggests that the
a more and more insular abstraction. But on the contrary,
Flemish master’s approach of the canvas might have been
Cubism was about the real world. [...] I mean, several paths
quite similar to the technique Hockney used on Pearblossom
led out from those initial discoveries of Picasso and Bracque,
Highway. ‘I’m convinced Van Eyck was doing something re-
and abstraction was no doubt one of them. [...] But still you
markably similar, pulling in close for each face in the crowd,
have to ask yourself, why didn’t Picasso and Bracque, who
for each clump of trees, for each flower, and then feathering
invented Cubism, ever follow that path? And I suspect that
all of those vanishing points one atop the next’ (ibid.). The
it’s because sitting there in Paris back in the early 1910s, play-
immense detail in Early Flemish Primitive painting is, ac-
ing out the various possibilities in their minds, they could
cording to Hockney, due to ‘hundreds of individual vantages,
already see that abstraction led into a cul-de-sac, eventually
one after the next, bringing every detail up close’ (o.c. 175).
even just an empty room, and they didn’t need to do it to find
The result is an image of great clarity and overall sharpness.
out. I mean, the urge to depict and the longing to see depic-
In fact, ‘the convention of the blur comes from photography’
tions is very strong and very deep within us. [...] And a long-
(o.c. 38): in real life everything we see is in focus. The focus
ing like that doesn’t just disappear in one generation. Art is
89
about making correspondences – making connections with
ing to say? And: What is the poet trying to make us feel?’ (FF
the world and to each other. It’s about love in that sense –
208-209). But this approach, which we find in Nussbaum, goes
that is the origin of the erotic quality of art. We love to study
against common sense because ‘every critic who is worth his
images of the world, and especially images of people, our
salt has enough literary intuition to know that the way of say-
fellow creatures. And the problem with abstraction, finally, is
ing things is somehow all-important’ (FF 208). After all, if the
that it goes too far inwards and the links become tenuous, or
object of literature is merely to communicate information or
dissolve, and it becomes too hard to make those connections.
to inspire adequate feelings and attitudes (“postures of the
You end up getting these claims by some of the formalist
heart and mind,” as Nussbaum calls them) in the reader, then
critics that art just isn’t for everybody – but that’s ridiculous’
why write literature in the first place? Why not simply state
(o.c. 50).
one’s case in plain language? Why create a work of literary art? Moreover, much poetry and quite a bit of narrative fiction
90
Virtual Life
is not easy to understand: does the poetic or narrative form
If we are to address the shortcomings we perceived in Nuss-
not hamper rather than facilitate the swift communication
baum’s pragmatic approach to literature we must now look
of ideas? Does it not endanger the presumed pragmatic func-
at how Langer sees expressive form at work in literary works
tions of language? If all one wants is to communicate, why do
of art. Langer puts poetry at the heart of her discussion of
it in such a roundabout and often absurdly embellished way?
literature but maintains that the basic principles at work in
The answer, obviously, is that literature does not aim at com-
poetry can easily be extended to the novel or any other work
munication at all. For this reason, Langer avoids speaking of
of literature. Right from the start Langer points to the lure
art’s “meaning” and prefers to speak of its import, because the
of the discursive: ‘The reason why literature is a standard
expressiveness of a work of art ‘is conveyed’ rather than com-
academic pursuit lies in the very fact that one can treat it
municated (PA 60 and 67). This distinction becomes especially
as something else than art. Since its normal material is lan-
crucial when dealing with literature, which uses language,
guage, and language is, after all, the medium of discourse, it
the very instrument of discursive thought, as its instrument.
is always possible to look at a literary work as an assertion of
But a poet or novelist ‘uses discourse to create an illusion, a
facts and opinions, that is, as a piece of discursive symbol-
pure appearance, which is a non-discursive symbolic form.
ism in the usual communicative way. [...] It is a truism for
The feeling expressed by this form is neither his, nor his he-
modern pragmatists that there are only two essential func-
ro’s, nor ours. [...] He has made an illusion, as complete and
tions of language (however much they talk about its many,
immediate as the illusion of space created by a few strokes
many uses), namely to convey information, and to stimulate
on paper [...]. He has made an illusion by means of words
feelings and attitudes in the hearer. The leading questions
[...]. But what he creates is not an arrangement of words, for
of poetry criticism, therefore, must be: What is the poet try-
words are only his materials, out of which he makes his poetic
91
92
elements. [...] The poet’s business is to create the appearance
we can experience directly), we do not yet know how all our
of “experiences,” the semblance of events lived and felt, and
experiences connect. I cannot know that the man I met this
to organise them so they constitute a purely and completely
afternoon will turn out to be the love of my life. In fact, it is
experienced reality, a piece of virtual life’ (FF 211-212). This,
possible that I hardly noticed him or heartily disliked him on
then, is the artistic import and primary illusion of the liter-
our first meeting. It is only many years from now that this af-
ary arts: they express the experience of life entirely felt. To
ternoon will take on the form of “the afternoon I met my fu-
do this, the literary artist uses words just like the visual art-
ture husband”. It is only with hindsight that we see connec-
ist uses lines and colours. As we stressed earlier, the work of
tions, reasons, or larger biographical narratives. It is only near
art is a total reference and none of its elements has mean-
the end of a life, or after a considerable part of life has been
ing outside of the total reference. This applies equally to the
lived, that a person can look back upon that life and write a
words used in a work of literature. It is obviously true that all
coherent (auto)biographical narrative. ‘Past experience, as we
the words used also have meaning outside the literary work:
remember it, takes on form and character, shows us persons
this is the meaning (or the meanings) we can find in the dic-
instead of vague presences and their utterances, and modi-
tionary. But outside of the literary work the words have none
fies our impressions by knowledge of things that came after,
of the import they have within it: a dictionary can tell us what
things that change one’s spontaneous evaluation. Memory is
a word means in general discourse, but it can never explain
the great organiser of consciousness. [...] It is the real maker
how the word functions and which feelings it conveys in the
of history – not recorded history, but the sense of history it-
fabric of a specific work of literature. And in that sense the
self, the recognition of the past as a completely established
words do indeed lose their (work-specific) meaning or import
(though not completely known) fabric of events, continuous
outside the total reference of the work.
in space and time, and causally connected throughout’ (FF
But we must explain how literature goes about creating vir-
262-263). This also implies that the past tense enables us to
tual life. How does it create the felt experience of life entirely
reflect upon history, because we can only evaluate events if
lived? Several aspects come into play and with regard to nar-
we have an overview of the entire fabric in which they are
rative prose, and especially the novel, the element of tense
integrated. The past tense also helps create a sense of dis-
is paramount. Novels are usually written in the past tense
tance which is crucial to the aesthetic experience: it conjures
because this is the tense of memory. If a novel is to tell a life
up the past, and in the case of the novel the virtual life that
or to tell a series of events, it must construct a history. In
is being offered for our perception, as a whole: ‘the mode in
this, the novel resembles memory: it endeavours to create
which events appear is the mode of completed experience,
‘a perception of the whole history as a fabric of contributive
i.e. of the past. This explains why the normal tense of literary
events. Actual experience has no such closed form’ (FF 262).
narration is the past tense’ (FF 264).
When we experience the present (and the present is really all
In a work of literature, as in any other work of art, life is
93
94
presented in an enclosed form that is not coextensive with
to switch the reader’s or hearer’s attitude from conversational
the real world in which we live. The novel is fiction and the
interest to literary interest, i.e. from actuality to fiction’ (FF
narrative presentation is a framing device that makes clear
213) so that ‘the reader is confronted at once with a virtual
that what is presented is not a real event but a virtual event.
order of experiences’ (FF 214). It is common knowledge that
‘Literary events are made, not reported, just as portraits are
lovers of literature will often read the first line of a novel
painted, not born and raised’ (FF 257). This element of fram-
before purchasing it. This makes perfect sense: if the first
ing should be well understood. It refers exclusively to the fact
line does not draw one into the fabric of the virtual world
that the world represented in a work of art is not an exten-
presented in the novel, one is not likely to persevere for the
sion of the real world. So the frame that cuts a work of art off
many following pages. A particularly fine example of a first
from the real world is the very fact of its being a work of art. This
line that immediately establishes an entire fictional world
applies equally to all the arts. The room depicted in a paint-
can be found in Virginia Woolf’s great modernist novel Mrs
ing is not an extension of the room in the museum where
Dalloway (1925): ‘Mrs Dalloway said she would buy the flowers
the picture is hung. The painting is framed not because there
herself.’ This sentence does many things at once. By using a
happens to be a wooden frame around it but because it cre-
passive construction in the past tense, the events are imme-
ates a virtual space in itself and all of its own. Similarly, the
diately framed at a distance. The elegance of the short sen-
virtual space created by dancers on a stage is not coextensive
tence gives the illusion of something entirely self-contained:
with the space of the spectators in the theatre. As Langer
it is a marvel of concise expression. It also gives one a feeling
points out (and as we shall discuss at greater length in Chap-
of who this Mrs Dalloway is, for there is a sense of decisive-
ter Three), the dance creates a relation of forces in which the
ness in the utterance. Even in the passive she seems to speak
dancers seem to magnetise and attract each other: a virtual
with conviction. She is mistress of the house, something
space with no ties to the surrounding world (FF 175-176). So
which is also made clear by referring to her formally as “Mrs
framing has nothing whatsoever to do with the presence or
Dalloway,” although we will presently get to know her more
absence of an actual frame around the work of art. Simply
intimately as Clarissa. The sentence is at once distanced
by being presented as a work of art, namely something ficti-
and engaged with its subject. And it immediately propels us
tious, a virtual reality, the work of art is framed, cut off from
into the narrative for the use of the definite article to refer to
the everyday. So we may say that the frame is the fictional
“the” flowers implies that everyone in the virtual world of the
character of the work. Michael Polanyi, speaking of framing
novel knows which flowers are referred to, that there is a very
in literature, says that ‘the frame and the story embody each
specific reason for buying the flowers, and that this reason
other’ (Polanyi and Prosch 1975: 87): the work is framed by
is known to all relevant parties in the virtual world. So we
virtue of its being a virtual presentation.
are alerted to the fact that we are about to find out what the
Framing starts with the very first line of the work, ‘which has
flowers are for, why they are needed, and why Mrs Dalloway
95
96
announces so decidedly that she will get them herself. Final-
is successful we enter into it and imaginatively supplement
ly, and most brilliantly, the sentence encompasses the entire
other features. But even in our mind there is never an entire-
scope of the novel, for much of the subsequent life in the
ly detailed picture of the virtual world: we are happy to have
novel will consist in a stream of consciousness presentation
an overall sense or feel of the place. Once we have entered
of Clarissa Dalloway’s impressions, feelings, and thoughts as
into the novel, the fabric of its virtual world seems to weave
she journeys through London to get the flowers in question.
itself. That is why it was so apt of Clive Barker to situate the
Interestingly, once the virtual world of a novel is created, the
fantastical parallel world of his novel Weaveworld (1987) in
author need not go into detail about its individual proper-
the images depicted in the fabric of a carpet: the world he
ties. The reader will supply much of the material that is not
creates is embedded in an actual tapestry that can be read as
explicitly mentioned. Many novels do not bother to give us a
a metaphor for the creative act itself.
detailed outline of the scenery through which the characters
The fabric of the virtual world must be successfully created
move and a novel does not lose its vividness if we as read-
or the novel fails to capture our imagination. And once it
ers are not familiar with the detailed geography of the city in
is created it is not easy to isolate elements from the fabric
which it is set. Similarly, novels rarely elaborate on the furni-
without losing their artistic or emotive import. That is why,
ture, curtains, wallpaper, or other decorative aspects of each
when we look up a favourite passage in a novel, it sometimes
and every room the characters enter. Such details are only
seems colourless and unconvincing when read in isolation.
supplied when they are necessary for the fabric of the virtual
What seemed imaginative, lively, and highly original on the
world. Once the sense of life has been created, the reader’s
first reading, may even seem pedestrian on rereading. The
imagination will fill in the gaps. This means that no two read-
reason for this is that our first reading was embedded in our
ers will read exactly the same novel. But that is no matter, for
experience of the entire virtual world. The bare words were
all the details that do matter are mentioned. We may ad lib
doubly enhanced on that occasion: they were enhanced by
the rest at will. This is especially important in relation to the
their inclusion in the work of art made with words and by
more fantastical genres in literature such as fantasy or sci-
our engagement with the virtual world thus created. When
ence fiction. Authors of such literature often take time to de-
we reread such a passage or sentence in isolation, we are
scribe the scenery of, for example, an exotic planet on which
often confronted simply with the words. We often have simi-
the action is situated, but they too are not able to go into ex-
lar experiences with photographs. We take photographs to
haustive detail about the properties of the virtual world they
memorise a special occasion, special people, or the flavour of
create. But the illusion works as long as the author offers the
a place. Photographs are meant to capture the moment. But
salient features that make the scene, and therefore the sense
looking at them some time later we are often left with simply
of life, come alive. The elements they offer suggest a vital
the buildings, the surroundings, and the people in them. The
pattern of what the virtual world is like and if the suggestion
moment is lost to us and the photograph becomes merely
97
98
anecdotal. In fact, a good poem, a piece of music, or another
The life expressed in art is virtual, which means that a work
work of art is more likely to trigger in us the sentiment ex-
of art will always be a work of fiction. This is intrinsically
perienced on that specific occasion than a photograph that
linked to its framed nature, which cuts it off from the realm
leaves us feeling less than what it shows. Works of art that
of actual everyday life. So art is a fictional symbolic repre-
are unrelated to the memorialised event can bring back the
sentation of the felt experience of life that is (an apparition)
feel of the moment because they are works of the imagina-
presented to our perception. Turning at last to Nussbaum,
tion that offer us symbols of feeling. They succeed because
with whom we still have something of a philosophical quar-
they, unlike the photograph, create a virtual experience that
rel to resolve, we find that Nussbaum has very little time
is discontinuous with the realm of everyday life and evokes
for Langer’s theory of art. In Upheavals of Thought (2001) she
the feeling apart from the anecdotal event. That, incidentally,
dismisses it because she feels it rests on what she consid-
is probably also the reason why art can soothe and calm us:
ers to be a simplistic theory of the emotions that fails to see
not because art has some cathartic effect (as the aristotelians
emotions as intentional. According to Nussbaum, Langer
and pragmatists would claim) but because it envelops us in
sees emotions as immediate and unreflected reactions to
another reality, a virtual world in which our actual life is mo-
outward impulses whereas Nussbaum has convincingly ar-
mentarily suspended. Art does not resolve our emotions, its
gued that there is an evaluative moment in all emotions and
illusions give us temporary relief from our emotions by invit-
that emotions are therefore never entirely “expressive” in an
ing us to direct our complete attention and sense of felt life
unmediated way. But even if we were to accept this criticism
towards the logical expression of feeling in the forms of the
that does not mean that we should reject Langer’s theory of
work. Harold Bloom reports that during the week following
art. In fact, we might want to try and adjust it and introduce
the September 11, 2001, terrorist attack on the World Trade
an intentional theory of the emotions, such as Nussbaum’s,
Center in New York he ‘taught scheduled classes on Wallace
into it. It then becomes clear that such an operation would
Stevens and Elizabeth Bishop, on Shakespeare’s early come-
not invalidate or even change Langer’s theory of art. Whether
dies, and on the Odyssey. I cannot know whether I helped my
emotions are conceived of as intentional or not does not
students at all, but I momentarily held off my own trauma’
necessarily affect their relationship with the forms we create
(Bloom 2002: 3). Reading literature did not cathartically re-
to express them since Langer holds that art is never directly
solve or heal trauma but kept it at bay.
expressive of emotions. Whether an emotion is understood as intentional or not has nothing to do with the legitimacy
Against Form
of the claim that feeling is expressed in expressive forms. So
Let us summarise the Langerian insights into art we have
we could (if we were to pursue the issue) accept Nussbaum’s
gained. According to Langer, art is expressive form, a logical
criticism of Langer’s theory of the emotions and still stand by
symbol of the felt experience of life. But that is not enough.
Langer’s theory of art.
99
100
But Nussbaum is also critical of Langer because she is one of
But this is of course the issue that concerns Nussbaum most:
a series of ‘writers on art who are lovers of music and wish
following a tradition that she traces back to Aristotle, Nuss-
to give music a special place among the arts’ (Nussbaum
baum claims that the issues of citizenship and ethics that
2001: 261). But surely, if it is legitimate to take literature as a
she addresses in literature are themselves aesthetic issues
paradigmatic case of the arts, as Nussbaum does, it should
and that an aestheticist approach that focuses on formal
be equally legitimate to favour music in such a way. Besides,
qualities is too reductive. She claims that ‘one of the great-
Langer several times points out that the fact that music is
est contributions of both Plato and Aristotle to aesthetics
often her prime exhibit should not be taken to mean that
was their subtle account of the ways in which literary forms
it is somehow the “highest” form of art or the most pure or
themselves convey a content, a view of what is worth taking
the most representative. All the arts are equally pure in their
seriously, and what the world is like. What could someone
greatest accomplishments and there is no hierarchy of the
mean by saying that these questions are not aesthetic? Such
arts. I feel Nussbaum is so quick to dismiss Langer because
a claim can be seriously supported only by defending a pic-
Langer’s theory of living form is broader in scope than Nuss-
ture of the aesthetic that has had a relatively narrow and
baum’s ideas on literature and because many of Nussbaum’s
recent history in the Western tradition, namely the Kantian
observations can be more adequately explained through
and Post-Kantian formalist tradition, according to which the
Langer’s theory. To look at Nussbaum through Langer is to see
proper aesthetic attitude is one that abstracts of all practical
the limitations of Nussbaum’s approach, for it is clear that
interests’ (Nussbaum 1997: 102). But Nussbaum misrepre-
Nussbaum’s theory of literature does not travel well to the
sent the issue. Langer would never deny that literary form
other arts and that what she says about literature requires
conveys a content that we should take seriously. All content
more grounding in an analysis of literary form. Langer shows
present in a work of art is artistic by being part of the work.
that the “modes of interaction” Nussbaum isolates move us
But Nussbaum would have us believe that the presence of a
not for their discursive content but because they are integrat-
content that deserves to be taken seriously is often in itself
ed parts of the fabric of an illusion of life entirely felt. What
the full measure of a work’s artistic import. And this is sim-
Nussbaum claims literature tells or teaches us could just as
ply claiming too much for seriousness and demanding too
easily be stated, and in fact in a discursively much less am-
little from art. All art is serious, but not all serious things are
biguous way, in a statistic. Nussbaum’s theory does not show
art. Besides, to state that ‘literary forms themselves convey a
why literature needs to be literature because it fails to identify
content’ is a simplistic truism: how could one use words and
anything in literature that makes it specifically literary as
not convey some content? Even nonsense poetry relies on the
opposed to a social pamphlet or an elucidating statistic. She
fact that words, even words randomly put on paper, always
mentions style and form but never explains how they func-
suggest meanings and associations. Nussbaum might just as
tion.
well argue that the aesthetic import of Richard Strauss’ opera
101
102
Salomé lies in the fact that it narrates how the titular vixen
prejudice against non-discursive thought in her work. That
managed to trade her dance for a baptist’s head. And surely
may be a reason (but surely not the only reason) why she has
the supreme import of Bach’s Matthäus-Passion cannot lie in
tried to establish the reason of emotions in her work, notably
the fact that it reports how a man came to die on a cross.
in Upheavals of Thought. If emotions can be shown to have
The problem is now clear. Kant’s theory of aesthetic judge-
reason, they can be made to work in a discursive way and are
ment, which started the formalist-aestheticist tradition in
thus rescued from the shapeless muddle that we usually call
modern art theory, was primarily devised from the point of
“the emotional”. But even if we grant that this view of the
view of the visual arts and music, whereas the tradition to
emotions is correct, and Nussbaum’s writing on the issue is
which Nussbaum belongs has always been concerned more
persuasive enough, this does not mean that we need to reject
with literature, and especially the example of Greek tragedy.
Langer’s theory. But Nussbaum does so nevertheless. This
Langer shows that it is possible to expand the formalist ap-
rejection is probably due to the fact that Langer accepts that
proach to include all the arts, including literature, while re-
certain facts, feelings, or emotions do not allow of discursive
taining a keen awareness of each art’s individual characteris-
symbolisation. Langer accepts the limits of language and the
tics. But Langer also suggests that any approach that looks at
limits of discursive reason and subsequently suggests that
art discursively runs the risk of agreeing with the early (and
this need not lead us into unreason: it simply opens a new
only the early) Wittgenstein that it is best to keep silent about
perspective on a symbolism that is not discursive but still
matters about which it is not possible to speak. To take dis-
logical. Nussbaum would seem to stick with early Wittgen-
cursive meaning as the standard for evaluating all the arts is
stein: if something is not communicable in discursive lan-
to overlook the fact that some of the arts might be very well
guage (or translatable into it), it is senseless.
suited to express feelings and subtleties that discursive lan-
Nussbaum’s view of art, as represented in her very nar-
guage is often unable to communicate. A discursive approach
row focus on literature (and, one might add, only one very
to art makes two assumptions, namely ‘that language is the
specific kind of literature, namely the realistic novel of the
only means of articulating thought’ and that ‘everything
nineteenth century), is still utilitarian instead of aesthetic.
which is not speakable thought, is feeling’ (PNK 87) about
Basically, Nussbaum still sees art as what Kenneth Burke
which it is best to keep silent. But it is wrong to assume that
once called ‘equipment for living’: aesthetic objects that help
‘all articulate symbolism is discursive’ (PNK 88). Whenever
us cope with the many perplexities of life (Burke 1973: 61).
language encounters feelings or facts that do not allow of
Nussbaum’s work is a latter-day example of the therapeutic
discursive expression another kind of symbolism may be
fallacy that the ultimate legitimacy of art lies in its thera-
sought to express them. Such a symbolism would be a non-
peutic or social benefits. In a sometimes vicious criticism
discursive symbolism as can be found in the arts. Nuss-
of Nussbaum’s work Geoffrey Galt Harpham claims that for
baum’s stress on literature suggests that there is a utilitarian
Nussbaum ‘the specificity of literature as a discourse, an
103
104
object of professional study, is almost altogether erased and
which sets his work going, whether it comes suddenly like an
replaced by a conception that treats it bluntly as moral phi-
inspiration or only after much joyless and laboured fuddling,
losophy. [...] Her relation to literature, and to the world of the
is the envisagement of the “commanding form,” the funda-
mind in general, appears to have been based on the most
mental feeling to be explored and expressed’ (FF 389). This
“primitive” of all readerly responses, identification with fic-
‘power of conception’ is what Langer calls ‘genius’ (FF 408).
tional characters’ (Harpham 2002: 59). ‘Literature, she says, is
Genius is a much-maligned word and has become politically
useful because it cultivates emotions, and emotions are use-
incorrect since the triumph of the School of Resentment. It
ful because they foster a human community. The most useful
has also often been used in vague and pseudo-mystical ways.
literature is therefore realistic fiction’ (o.c. 68). Nussbaum’s
But the fact that many people have used a word badly should
social and moral goals may be laudable in themselves, but
not prevent us from using it correctly. There is nothing ob-
they cannot be imposed upon art without reducing art to
scure or arcane about genius: it is simply an artist’s ability
something which it is not. But this, in essence, is the error
to conceive of expressive form. Harold Bloom has called it
that lies at the heart of the therapeutic fallacy and that was
‘fierce originality’ (Bloom 2002: 11). In this, genius is differ-
also exposed by Langer when she pointed out that the ef-
ent from talent. ‘Although some degree of talent is necessary
fect of the pragmatic approach to art ‘is that aesthetic values
if genius is not to be still-born, great artists have not always
must be treated either as direct satisfactions, i.e. pleasure, or
had extraordinary technical ability; they have often struggled
as instrumental values, that is to say, means to fulfilment of
for expression, but the urgency of their ideas caused them to
biological needs. It is either a leisure interest, like sports and
develop every vestige of talent until it rose to their demands.
hobbies, or it is valuable for getting on with the world’s work
[...] But it is a mistake to think genius is complete from the
– strengthening morale, integrating social groups, or vent-
beginning. Talent is much more likely to be so, wherefore the
ing dangerous repressed feelings in a harmless emotional
infant prodigy is a well-known phenomenon. [...] Since ge-
catharsis. But in either case, artistic experience is not essen-
nius is not superlative talent, but the power to conceive invis-
tially different from ordinary physical, practical, and social
ible realities – sentience, vitality, emotion – in a new symbolic
experience’ (FF 35-36).
projection that reveals something of their nature for the first time, it does admit of degrees; and a small amount of genius
Genius Redeemed
is not a rare endowment. Whatever its scope, it is the mark of
A final question must be answered. We have said that art is
the true artist’ (FF 408-409).
expressive form. But what sets the creative dynamic in mo-
Harold Bloom explains that genius is derived from the Latin
tion? How does the artist engage upon a work of art? Cre-
and means ‘to be an attendant spirit for each person or place:
ation starts with an act of conception, namely when an artist
to be either a good or evil genius, and so to be someone who,
conceives of a commanding form. ‘The act of conception
for better or for worse, strongly influences someone else.’ It
105
106
is ‘our inclination or natural gift, our inborn intellectual or
the attitude of resentment. To enable communication with-
imaginative power’ (Bloom 2002: 7). Note that there is a dou-
out mental expansion Nussbaum approaches literature as a
ble aspect to genius: it is an inborn power, but at the same
mode of discourse while the New Historicists look at litera-
time it is a power that may influence someone else. This in-
ture as an effect of social forces: it could happen to anyone
fluence is what Harold Bloom calls authority. ‘Genius asserts
and you could discourse on it with everyone. This is equality
authority over me,’ Bloom claims, ‘when I recognise powers
as method.
greater than my own’ (o.c. 3). Quoting Emerson, Bloom writes
Does all this mean that art can have no social or moral ben-
that words of genius are words that ‘sound to you as old as
efits? Not entirely. But it does mean that we must understand
yourself’ (ibid.): we recognise genius when someone says
these benefits properly. Oscar Wilde prefaced his novel The
something about our deepest nature which we felt we always
Picture of Dorian Gray (1891) with a series of aphorisms and
knew but were never able to verbalise. This, too, is put most
one of the most famous states that ‘there is no such thing as
eloquently by Emerson when he writes that ‘in every work of
a moral or an immoral book. Books are well written, or badly
genius we recognise our own rejected thoughts: they come
written. That is all’ (Wilde 1991: 129). This is much more than
back to us with a certain alienated majesty’ (quoted in Bloom
a programme for aestheticism: it states the simple truth
2002: 246). By denying greatness and originality the School of
that no art can be successful if it is not successful as form.
Resentment limits human growth and rejects the possibility
It is the forms that allow us to conceive of import, not the
that a mind may be larger than our own and may help ours to
content. Harold Bloom has stated he has grave doubts about
expand through exposure to the expressive forms it creates.
literature’s value as educator since most of the great master-
Harold Bloom was very accurate to speak of resentment in
pieces are not the kinds of books one can read as benevolent
relation to many contemporary critics for there is something
social tracts in the way that Nussbaum reads Dickens. Most
narrow-minded and ungenerous in the inability or unwilling-
great literature is filled with villains and characters with
ness to see greatness anywhere. But as Langer points out, ‘a
grave moral flaws who display all kinds of behaviour that we
critic who cannot be awe-struck is not equal to his material’
might not judge very commendable for everyday use. There
(FF 246): his mind is incapable of imagination, of conceiv-
is dubious morality in much great literature and many great
ing feelings and ideas that he does not yet know. The cruel
literary characters would deserve our moral condemnation
irony of this, of course, is that the social reform that people
if they were real. As Harold Bloom sarcastically remarks, ‘the
like Nussbaum would like to generate through art depends
new commissars tell us that reading good books is bad for
entirely on our imaginative ability to put ourselves in the
the character, which I think is probably true. Reading the very
minds of unknown others. But this requires an expansion of
best writers [...] is not going to make us better citizens. Art is
the mind, of the possibilities of felt experience. There is no
perfectly useless, according to the sublime Oscar Wilde, who
attitude more pernicious to this generous state of mind than
was right about everything. He also told us that all bad poetry
107
108
is sincere’ (Bloom 1994: 16), a truth to bear in mind when
level [because] the arts we live with – our picture books and
confronting politically correct critics who feel that mere ex-
stories and the music we hear – actually form our emotive
pressiveness makes for good art. They are wrong: real artists
experience. [...] This influence of art on life gives us an indica-
don’t cry, they conceive of expressive forms.
tion why a period of efflorescence in the arts is apt to lead
What, then, is literature, or art in general, for? As Harold
a cultural advance: it formulates a new way of feeling, and
Bloom points out, ‘the true use of Shakespeare or of Cer-
that is the beginning of a cultural age. It suggests another
vantes, of Homer or of Dante, of Chaucer or of Rabelais, is
matter for reflection, too: that a wide neglect of artistic edu-
to augment one’s own growing inner self. [...] All that the
cation is a neglect in the education of feeling. Most people
Western Canon can bring one is the proper use of one’s own
are so imbued with the idea that feeling is a formless total
solitude, that solitude whose final form is one’s confronta-
organic excitement in human beings as in animals, that the
tion with one’s own mortality’ (o.c. 30). ‘What Johnson and
idea of educating feeling, developing its scope and quality,
Woolf after him called the Common Reader [...] does not read
seems odd to them, if not absurd. It is really, I think, at the
for easy pleasure or to expiate social guilt, but to enlarge a
very heart of personal education’ (PA 71-72). In her Philosophi-
solitary existence’ (o.c. 518). The confrontation with great art
cal Sketches Langer adds that art is ‘the spearhead of human
cannot make us better people and it cannot cure social ills,
development, social and individual. The vulgarisation of art is
but it can expand our consciousness, deepen our insight, and
the surest symptom of ethnic decline’ (PS 83-84).
help us reach some kind of wisdom. ‘The question we need to put to any writer must be: does she or he augment our con-
Inventing the Human
sciousness, and how is it done? I find this a rough but effec-
As an example of the way art can help us shape our emotion-
tual test: however I have been entertained, has my awareness
al lives Langer points to Irwin Edman’s suggestion that ‘our
been intensified, my consciousness widened and clarified? If
emotions are largely Shakespeare’s poetry’ (PA 72). This idea
not, then I have encountered talent, not genius. What is best
has recently been elaborated by Harold Bloom in a massive
and oldest in myself has not been activated’ (Bloom 2002: 12).
study of Shakespeare’s work. But the notion that Shakspeare
Langer points to something similar when she writes that art
provided the model for the personality and emotional make-
can help us form and expand our emotional lives. ‘As soon as
up of modern man can be traced at least to Early German Ro-
the natural forms of subjective experience are abstracted to
manticism and the work of Friedrich Schlegel (1772-1829) and
the point of symbolic presentation, we can use those forms
Ludwig Tieck (1773-1853), a context which Bloom does not
to imagine feeling and understand its nature. Self-knowledge,
mention but which is worth a detour here because it will take
insight into all phases of life and mind, springs from artistic
us right back to the problems we have been tackling in this
imagination. That is the cognitive value of the arts. But their
chapter. Friedrich Schlegel was probably the quintessential
influence on human life goes deeper than the intellectual
Early Romantic philosopher. His work includes a philosophy
109
110
of Romantic irony and fragmentation that often reads like a
Schlegel calls the tendency towards the Absolute within the
manifesto of postmodern sensibilities. Like the other Roman-
finite. This is a rather abstract way of saying that allegories
tics, Schlegel believed that the ultimate foundation of every-
are an attempt to somehow show or capture the Absolute in
thing, which was usually called the Absolute, was unattain-
a finite form. In an allegory we use an image to refer to some-
able. Therefore it became the object of a never-ending search.
thing else. It is an attempt to capture something elusive or
This search was the essence of philosophy, which Schlegel
abstract in an image. So an allegory uses an image of some-
defines as ‘Sehnsucht nach dem Unendlichen’ (Frank 1997: 521)
thing finite to focus on something beyond the finite: ‘Because
or a longing for the infinite. The destination of our longing is
it is ineffable, the highest can only be expressed allegori-
forever beyond reach, it remains a mystery. Because of his in-
cally’ (Frank 1989: 136; Frank 1997: 932). It should therefore
ability to gain access to his essential nature, man is split. Man
come as no surprise when Schlegel writes, in fragment 48 of
is a broken being that feels at once finite and infinite. This
his Ideen (1800), that ‘where philosophy ends, poetry must
double aspect is due to the unattainability of the Absolute:
begin’ (Frank 1997: 944). Poetry or allegory takes over from
we have an essence, a unity, a foundation, but we cannot
philosophy because philosophical reflection falls short of
attain it. Our most fundamental self remains forever alien to
its intended goal, which is to gain insight into the Absolute.
us. We cannot find out what we really are and can therefore
Reading fragment 48 one feels as if one were standing on
never be truly whole. Nevertheless, we feel ourselves whole.
the cross-roads between Langer and Wittgenstein: discursive
We feel or sense the Absolute. But every time we try to grasp
language and rational philosophical reflection fail to express
it, it eludes us. So we are on an infinite quest for insight into
the ineffable, but where Wittgenstein takes his silent leave
the Absolute. During this quest we feel at the same time fi-
and retreats into profound silence, Schlegel and Langer point
nite, namely a corporeal being that is limited and cut off from
towards a different symbolic order, a mode of expression that
the Absolute, and infinite, namely somehow linked to that
allows us to give form to what eludes rational discourse. But
elusive Absolute, attracted to it but never able to take hold of
allegory, which may surely be read here as shorthand for the
it. As a consequence, the subject experiences itself as a mere
arts, is not the only way Schlegel feels we can glimpse some-
fragment. It experiences a feeling of limitation that expresses
thing of the Absolute; there is also the joke, which is the op-
a most distressing truth: ‘dass wir nur ein Stück von uns selbst
posite of allegory. In the joke we actually find a short flash of
sind’ (o.c. 876). The other, missing part is the Absolute.
insight into the Absolute. Where allegory is directed upwards,
This longing for the Absolute which cannot be fulfilled, and
away from the finite and with the gaze fixed upon the beyond
cannot be fulfilled on principle, is expressed in a dialectic or to
of the Absolute, the joke tries to capture the Absolute firmly
and fro between the principles of allegory and the joke. The
within a piece of the finite. The joke is like a flash of insight
dialectical movement between these two principles is what
into the Absolute, like lightning striking into stone (lightning
Schlegel calls irony. Let us first look at allegory, which is what
or ‘Blitz’ was a preferred image of Schlegel’s to characterise
111
112
the joke). Jokes are funny because they are contradictory, they
to anything. So we can and will say anything and then sim-
go against logic and common sense. They turn the usual or-
ply deny it. What separates Romantic irony from postmod-
der upside down. In doing so, they illuminate our inner split.
ern irony is a sense of the tragic, of loss, of being bound to
Irony is the attitude man has when he confronts the Abso-
something we cannot attain. For postmodernists it no longer
lute. Fully aware of his lacking self, man mocks both the finite
seems to be tragic that we lack essence. It has simply become
and the infinite. This mockery is irony. Man mocks the finite
a joke. A shallow and hollow joke and a rather petite sort of
because it is always in conflict with itself, a constant chaos of
lightning. Postmodernity is simply irony made easy.
fragments and ever-changing individual positions that never
But now for Shakespeare. Romantic irony is not the everyday
come together in a coherent whole and always remain lack-
irony we use to distance ourselves from people or ideals.
ing in relation to the Absolute. But man also mocks the Abso-
Neither is it the famous Socratic irony that feigns ignorance
lute itself because it is unattainable. To be grasped by human
only to entrap an antagonist in debate. Romantic irony is a
reflection (or philosophy) the Absolute must limit itself (in
higher form of irony that is not even necessarily funny. To
allegory, in the lightning flash of the joke). But in doing so,
Tieck, it is a spirit that penetrates a complete work of litera-
the Absolute is simply not showing itself. Since the Absolute is
ture and both destroys and holds together everything in it.
infinite (and unattainable) no finite form can ever capture it.
Tieck himself has called this spirit an ‘Äthergeist, der [...] über
In showing itself, the Absolute retreats. So all fragments are
dem Ganzen schwebt’ (Frank 1989: 371). This means that irony
in the end revealed to be but failed images of the Absolute.
is not an element in the plot of a novel or play. It is not even
Irony is the tragic consciousness of one’s fragmentary condi-
an attitude of the characters. It might be those things, but it
tion. It is clear that what we have here is an early, and prob-
is essentially more. It is a spirit that pervades the entire work
ably the earliest, systematic description in the modern era of
and that must therefore be ingrained in its very fabric. And
what we have come to call “postmodern irony”. But there is a
that means that irony must be found in language itself. Both
difference, and an important one. Postmodern irony can be a
Schlegel and Novalis have spoken of a ‘Transzendentalpoesie’
very irritating attitude that easily lends itself to smugness. It
in this context, analogous to Kant’s concept of a ‘Transzen-
is often an excuse to not take any position at all. Postmodern
dentalphilosophie’. This is a philosophy that does not seek
irony can never be taken to account for anything because it
to describe what we know but how we know. This was also
never really stands up for anything. This smug irony repre-
the project of Kant’s first critique: to analyse how we gain
sents a shift away from Romantic irony. The Early Romantics
knowledge of the world and describe that epistemological
and Schlegel never denied the existence of the Absolute. They
mechanism. Similarly, transcendental poetry would be a po-
simply believed that it could never be attained. Postmodern
etry that reflects on itself as poetry while it is being written.
irony will usually do away with this belief in the Absolute.
It is a text that announces itself as text. ‘Transzendentalpoesie,’
Since nothing universally applies, we need not truly commit
Schlegel writes, ‘[stellt] in jeder ihrer Darstellungen sich selbst mit
113
114
dar’ and is ‘überall zugleich Poesie und Poesie der Poesie’ (o.c. 364).
losopher as Richard Rorty defined an ironist as a person who
It is at once poetry and poetry of poetry. This self-reflexivity
always maintains a distance towards his supposed essence
means that poetry loses its unequivocality and becomes all-
because such essences are never final).
encompassing in its meanings. No single word has one single
Tieck has described this concept of irony in his early essay
meaning anymore.
on Shakespeares Behandlung des Wunderbaren (1793), in which
So Romantic irony for Tieck is a stylistic irony. Robert Minder
he asks how Shakespeare gets us to suspend disbelief in the
has called it ‘la grâce tieckienne’ (o.c. 371). It is to be found in
face of the many wondrous and surreal things that happen
the way Tieck treats his language and can be gleaned only
in his plays. According to Tieck, Shakespeare succeeds by
indirectly, in the lightness of phrasing, in the inconsistent
making sure that the attention of the spectator can never
way characters are developed, and in the loose way in which
stay completely focused on one element. He constantly
drama is motivated. Negatively put, this means that Tieck’s
shifts from humour to terror, from horror to drama and back
irony can be seen in the fact that there is something light
to comedy, piling up stylistic and dramatic contrasts in such
and ephemeral in his phrasing, that his characters act in
a way that the mind is overwhelmed by the onslaught of
inconsistent and implausible ways, and that there is no firm
shifting moods and perspectives. There is such a clash of op-
causal relation between dramatic events, so that these events
posites, and it is sustained at such a level and for such a long
might at some times seem somewhat absurd or bizarre. The
time, that the mind simply starts to feel exhausted and is no
Romantics believed that this lack of consistency, this free-
longer able to find any reason or rationality in the proceed-
dom from solid character, was in fact the true freedom of
ings. This leaves the mind with only one option: to sit back
human nature. Why, after all, should man have substance?
and surrender wholly to the illusion of the play. To put it un-
What if the real freedom of man lies in the fact that he does
kindly, and profoundly unjustly, Shakespeare might be said
not have substance? This insight, which reads thoroughly
to beat his audience into submission by the sheer power of
postmodern to our eyes, was neatly expressed by Schelling
his mercurial imagination shooting all over the place. Inter-
in a 1820/21 lecture where he describes human subjectivity
estingly, Tieck believes that Shakespeare can do this because
as a ‘durch alles gehen und nichts sein, nämlich nicht so sein, dass
the human mind itself is very susceptible to this method.
es nicht auch anders sein könnte’ (o.c. 372). To be human is es-
The mind of man is nimble. It has no essence and is there-
sentially never to exist in such a way that existence could not
fore plastic. What we have here, is the un-essentialist Ro-
be different. In man, nothing is determined and all is possible
mantic view of the subject that we found in Schelling’s state-
because, as Novalis once wrote, ‘jeder Mensch ist ohne Maass
ment. For man, all is possible. So man is also receptive to a
veränderlich’ (Frank 1985: 23): there is no limit to our mutabil-
poetry (which stands pars pro toto for all the arts) in which
ity. Since the Early Romantics this lack of essence has been
everything is possible, even the wondrous and supernatural.
linked to the concept of irony (and as we saw, as recent a phi-
Romantic irony, in the sense of Tieck, but also in the sense
115
116
of Schlegel, expresses human nature through its agile to and
a ‘naturalistic unreality’ (o.c. 12). As Bloom points out, ‘the
fro between extremes of emotion and experience without
reading of character appears infinite in Shakespeare’ (Bloom
ever attaining an essence or an end. Of Tieck’s own literary
1994: 53) and ‘no other writer, before or since Shakespeare,
characters Manfred Frank has written that they are driven
has accomplished so well the virtual miracle of creating ut-
by an ‘inner Void’ (Frank 1989: 386). This void is the essence
terly different yet self-consistent voices for his more than
of Romantic subjectivity. If one writes for the stage, this sub-
one hundred major characters and many hundreds of highly
jectivity is expressed through sheer inconsistency. This was
distinctive minor personages’ (Bloom 1998: xix). Shakespeare
also the view held by Novalis, who demanded ‘Mannigfaltig-
achieved this through what Bloom calls ‘a psychology of
keit in der Darstellung von Menschen,’ and especially ‘nur keine
mutability’ that ‘originates the depiction of self-change on
Puppen, keine sogenannten Charaktere – lebendige, bizarre, inkon-
the basis of self-overhearing [...]. We all of us go around now
sequente, bunte Welt. Je bunteres Leben, je besser’ (ibid.).
talking to ourselves endlessly, overhearing what we say, then
This mercurial man, leaping from either extreme of the emo-
pondering and acting upon what we have learned’ (Bloom
tional gamut to the other and responsive to sudden violent
1994: 48).
swings in mood and perception, was invented by William
Through this self-discovery through speech Shakespeare’s
Shakespeare. Modern man, ironic and sceptical, forever
characters develop to a point beyond our grasp. They create
torn by the question whether to act or not to act, is Hamlet,
themselves through the art of speech and become larger
Prince of Denmark. ‘Even at its darkest,’ Bloom writes, ‘Ham-
than ordinary life. ‘Hamlet baffles us by altering with nearly
let’s grief has something tentative in it. “Hesitant mourning”
every phrase he utters’ (Bloom 1998: 410). In a similar way,
is almost an oxymoron; still, Hamlet’s quintessence is never
all of Shakespeare’s characters ‘become free artists of them-
to be wholly committed to any stance or attitude, any mis-
selves, which means that they are free to write themselves,
sion, or indeed to anything at all. His language reveals this
to will changes in the self. Overhearing their own speeches
throughout, no other character in all of literature changes
and pondering those expressions, they change and go on to
his verbal decorum so rapidly. He has no center: [...] Hamlet
contemplate an otherness in the self, or the possibility of
is too intelligent to be at one with any role’ (Bloom 1998:
such otherness’ (Bloom 1994: 70). This is the expansiveness
406). Hamlet’s character is ‘a dance of contraries’ (o.c. 407).
of Shakespearean character that makes the Bard, in Bloom’s
To him, ‘the self is an abyss, the chaos of virtual nothing-
view, the author of modern man. ‘Shakespeare so opens
ness’ (o.c. 5). Bloom argues that Shakespeare, in inventing
his characters to multiple perspectives that they become
Hamlet, ‘invented the human as we continue to know it’ (o.c.
analytical instruments for judging you. If you are a moral-
xx). But the argument should not be limited to the gloomy
ist, Falstaff outrages you; if you are rancid, Rosalind exposes
prince of Elsinore. All of Shakespeare’s great characters are
you; if you are dogmatic, Hamlet evades you forever. And if
constructed from ‘seeming contradictions’ that give them
you are an explainer, the great Shakespearean villains will
117
118
cause you to despair. Iago, Edmund, and MacBeth are not
opaque philosophy of human reflection in his Fichte-Studien
motiveless; they overflow with motives, most of which they
(1795/96). Novalis (1772-1801) asks how knowledge of the elu-
invent or imagine for themselves. [...] The most bewildering
sive Absolute, and of our truest self, is possible. As starting
of Shakespearean achievements is to have suggested more
point he takes the notion of “reflection” and takes it literally
contexts for explaining us than we are capable of supplying
to mean a mirror image. If we look in a mirror, we see every-
for explaining his characters’ (o.c. 64). Shakespeare robs us
thing reversed: left becomes right and everything is turned.
of the possibility to think ourselves original in our concept
But we also think of our self-consciousness as reflection,
of our self. Shakespeare, as Camille Paglia has pointed out,
namely as self-reflection, a reflection upon our own thoughts
‘is the first to reflect upon the fluid nature of modern gender
and actions. So Novalis asks if a similar reversal of images
and identity’ (Paglia 1991: 197) and many of his comedies
also applies there. And it does. If we try to fathom the Ab-
evolve around mistaken identities with characters dressing
solute (or ourselves) through reflection, and this obviously
up as persons of the opposite sex. This fluidity, blurring the
means through the activity of philosophy, we constantly feel
lines of fixed personality, infects Shakespeare’s language,
that we are missing the Absolute. It eludes us and cannot
teeming with mercurial metaphors that ‘spill from line to
be attained. We have a feeling (‘Gefühl’) of what the Absolute
line, abundant, florid, illogical. [...] Shakespeare’s metaphors,
might be, but when we try to capture this feeling in (discur-
like his sexual personae, flicker through a rolling stream of
sive) thought, ‘der Geist des Gefühls ist da heraus’ (Frank 1997:
development and process. Nothing in Shakespeare stays the
817). As Nietzsche would later write in Die fröhliche Wissen-
same for long. [...] Shakespeare is an alchemist. In his treat-
schaft (1882), thoughts are mere shadows of our perceptions,
ment of sex and personality, Shakespeare is a shape-shifter
darker, emptier and simpler (‘Gedanken sind die Schatten un-
and master of transformations’ (o.c. 197-198).
serer Empfindungen, – immer dunkler, leerer, einfacher, als diese’;
The constant change in self, Hamlet’s ‘metamorphic nature’
Nietzsche 1999b: 502). But if rational reflection results in a re-
(Bloom 1998: 430), makes it ‘very difficult to generalize about
flection, namely a reversal of the true image, then reflection
Hamlet, because every observation will have to admit its
must also have the ability to reflect this reflection, to turn
opposite’ (o.c. 409). This has something of the to and fro that
it again and put it right. This would be a double reflection
marks the infinite Romantic consciousness that Schelling
that might be called self-reflection, namely a reflection upon
described as anti-essentialist openness. This becomes espe-
and of the reflection that happens in reflection. The inverted
cially clear in light of Bloom’s remark that ‘Hamlet’s players
image in a mirror is reverted again when reflected in another
hold the mirror up to nature, but Shakespeare’s is a mirror
mirror. If we seem to lose track of the Absolute in reflection,
within a mirror, and both are mirrors with many voices’
because we only get an inverted and therefore unreal image
(o.c. 15). The imagery of mirrors, which Bloom borrows from
of it, then the reflection of reflection might put the authentic
Shakespeare, can serve as a direct link to Novalis’ rather
image of the Absolute right again. If reflection is a movement
119
away from the Absolute towards a false image, then double
Chapter Two
reflection can be experienced as a movement of the Absolute towards us, opening and presenting itself in its true form. But this play of reflections is too easy an answer to our predicament. It would border on sophistry to make things look so easy. Novalis is aware of this and therefore denies that double reflection can give us insight into the Absolute. What the double reflection does do, however, is make us acutely aware of the falseness of the image captured in reflection (in thought, in philosophy). Our perceived knowledge at-
ARTWORLD INC.
tained through reflection is unmasked as false knowledge. So double reflection does not lead to insight in the Absolute, but to a knowing-of-not-knowing, a docta ignorantia! This is the spirit of Romanticism: there is something within us that 120
is beyond our comprehension and that can only be traced,
121
as Schlegel would say, through fragments. The Absolute is
One of the most important relationships in an artist’s life
larger than we could ever be. It is the same expansiveness
is that between himself and the artworld: the international
of the human soul that makes Shakespeare’s characters so
network of artists, curators, critics, and collectors who shape
much larger than us, but at the same time so close to us. It
the public face of the cultural realm. It is the curators, critics,
is in Shakespeare that we first find this infinity within that
and collectors who decide who’s hot and who’s not, which
the Romantics described as the source of our infinite Sehn-
works will be shown, and what will be sold. On a deeper level
sucht. It has been with us ever since and has shaped the way
the artworld probably also decides to a certain degree what
we think about ourselves. In fact, the postmodern condition
kind of art can be made at a given time. Obviously, this does
was invented by Shakespeare and is modelled on Hamlet. So
not mean the artworld decides which works of art will or
Shakespeare’s is a strong case indeed to show how art can
will not be made; it means that the artworld to a large extent
shape our emotional and spiritual lives.
decides what kind of art will be taken seriously at a given moment. Needless to say, the artworld is not a monolithic thing: there are many subcultures in the artworld. And the artworld is also often wrong in retrospect. The fact that the work of the Impressionists was jeered at and went unrecognised at first shows how wrong the artworld can be. It also shows
that a group of artists can form a subcultural artworld that
35) Danto is careful to speak of an interesting perceptual dif-
turns out to be more important than the dominant artworld.
ference because as he knows there were differences between
At least two lessons can be learned from this. First, an artist
Warhol’s Brillo Boxes and the real items one could buy in the
must always make the kind of art he believes in. No amount
supermarket. Not only were Warhol’s boxes handmade, they
of contemporary success or lack of it can say anything about
were also slightly smaller in size than the real Brillo boxes.
the value or importance of your work in the long run. Second,
So there are perceptual differences between art and real-
whether he likes it or not, every artist will have some kind
ity, but for Danto these differences are not “interesting” in a
of relationship with the artworld, even if it is simple flat-out
perceptual way, although they are of huge importance on a
rejection. So it is to the artworld and its dynamics that we
conceptual level. In fact, we will see that Danto so overvalues
now turn.
their conceptual importance that he becomes blind to such perceptual and material differences as are readily at hand in
122
Art Criticism After the End of Art
a given work of art.
In 1984 Arthur C. Danto made a bizarre claim about what he
Danto takes great pains to explain why Warhol’s Brillo Boxes
called the end of art. The end of art as Danto saw it has often
are a historical watershed. ‘Until the twentieth century it was
been misunderstood. Danto did not mean that no more art
tacitly believed that works of art were always identifiable as
would be made in the future. Nor was his claim about the
such. The philosophical problem now is to explain why they
end of art meant as a critical judgement on the art of the pe-
are works of art. With Warhol it becomes clear that there is
riod. Danto did not claim that contemporary art was so abys-
no special way a work of art must be’ (ibid.). For centuries
mally bad that he was witnessing something like the end of
this had been different. Danto believes that the ending nar-
art in the sense of the end of good art. Danto’s claim pointed
rative about art was begun around 1400, with the dawn of the
at an evolution within the narratives about art. Something
Renaissance. For centuries afterwards the narrative about
about the way we think and talk about art had so profoundly
art had to do with mimesis: art was judged on its ability to
changed that Danto believed it signalled the end of an era.
represent reality. Representational fidelity of some kind was
Danto was very specific about the date and place the era
the norm and art was felt to progress in its increasing abil-
ended: it was in Andy Warhol’s exhibition of his Brillo Boxes
ity to represent the world in ever more accurate ways. This
at the Stable Gallery in 1964. Warhol’s exhibition made it
is ‘the progressive model of art history’ (PDA 86) that starts,
clear that henceforth it was no longer possible to distinguish
for Danto, with Vasari. In the nineteenth century another
works of art from other objects. Warhol’s exhibition raised a
narrative developed out of this: the story of artistic Modern-
fundamental question: ‘what makes the difference between
ism. For Danto, the invention of the cinema, with its ability
a work of art and something not a work of art when there is
to represent movement with the highest representational
no interesting perceptual difference between them?’ (AEA
fidelity, was crucial in making artists abandon representa-
123
124
tion and raise ‘the question of what could be left for them to
itself is gained, it becomes pointless to pursue any further
do, now that the torch had, as it were, been taken up by other
the search for insight into art’s essence.
technologies’ (PDA 100). Most art histories put this shift at a
For Danto, the end of art ‘lies in the Age of Manifestos being
much earlier date, with the invention of photography, but the
over because the underlying premiss of manifesto-driven art
outcome was the same either way: the practice of painting
is philosophically indefensible. A manifesto singles out the
changed fundamentally. Now that photography and cinema
art it justifies as the true and only art, as if the movement it
had taken over the representational function, painting had
expresses had made the philosophical discovery of what art
to look for something else to do because it simply could not
essentially is. But the true philosophical discovery, I think, is
compete with the new media’s representational fidelity. With
that there really is no art more true than any other, and that
Modernism art became self-referential: ‘the whole main point
there is no one way art has to be: all art is equally and indif-
of art in our century was to pursue the question of its own
ferently art’ (AEA 34). With the end of art we have entered a
identity while rejecting all available answers as insufficiently
new era which Danto calls the Post-Historical era. From 1400
general’ (PDA 110). Modernism was what Danto calls the Age
until Modernism we lived in the historical era, at least in
of the Manifesto: innumerable manifestos were written about
artistic terms, because there was a belief in progress. In the
the one true art. Every artistic movement within Modernism
Renaissance and afterwards artists believed they were getting
believed it held the key to what art really was. And no move-
better and better at representing reality. In Modernism, with
ment agreed with any other about the nature of art’s essence.
its many manifestos, every avant-garde believed it was some-
By consequence, ‘the history of art simply seemed to be the
how progressing towards aesthetic truth, the ultimate pure
history of discontinuities’ (PDA 108), an endless parade of
and true essence of art. Such progress is no longer possible in
conflicting models without any progressive narrative thread.
the Post-Historical era. Therefore we have reached the end of
What Warhol showed, was that all these discontinuous ap-
history, which ‘means that there can be no historical direc-
proaches to art had somehow missed the point: what art was
tion art can take from this point on’ (AEA 36). If the historical
actually about was the attainment of consciousness of itself as
era was about drawing lines between what is and what is
art. This is an approach to art and history that Danto borrows
not (true or pure) art, no such lines can be drawn in the Post-
from Hegel’s Phänomenologie des Geistes (1807), which sees
Historical era. ‘To say that history is over is to say that there
history as the gradual development of Spirit (which is every-
is no longer a pale of history for works of art to fall outside of.
thing) towards total self-knowledge. In his highly tendentious
Everything is possible. Anything can be art. And, because the
view of the history of art, which is made to fit the Hegelian
present situation is essentially unstructured, one can no lon-
model, Danto sees this process at work, culminating in War-
ger fit a master narrative to it’ (AEA 114). Since the 1960s we
hol, whose art is about nothing more than itself (at least in
have learned to accept everything as art.
Danto’s eyes). Once the insight that art is really just about
For the art critic the Post-Historical condition is somewhat
125
126
perplexing for he is confronted with a relativism in art that
of abstract art this presentation of his ideas is reductive and
seems to make any kind of standards-based criticism diffi-
highly tendentious. To understand this we must consider the
cult. Danto speaks of an ‘unforgiving sort of relativism’ with
role of feeling in Kant’s aesthetics. For Kant, all our informa-
which ‘the concept of quality became odious and chauvinist.
tion about the world comes from our senses. Sensory input
[...] In candour, [...] it would be altogether wonderful if one
is next processed in the mind, where it is ordered according
could turn to aesthetics as a discipline for guidance out of
to a set of twelve categories that shape the stream of sensory
the chaos’ (AEA 94). However, a theory of art criticism has be-
information into coherent wholes. Through this process,
come very difficult to obtain since the end of history means
which is an interplay between sensory experience and the
that ‘a philosophical definition of art must be compatible
analytical workings of the mind, an image of the world or
with every kind and order of art – with the pure art of Rein-
representation (Vorstellung) comes about. This representation
hardt, but also with illustrative and decorative, figurative and
is not in itself beautiful or ugly, it is simply the way the world
abstract, ancient and modern, Eastern and Western, primi-
is presented to our senses (at this point, the reader might
tive and nonprimitive art, much as these may differ from one
want to recall Langer’s similar concept of intuition).
another. A philosophical definition has to capture everything
To determine whether a representation is beautiful or not we
and so can exclude nothing’ (AEA 36). According to Danto, the
must submit it to our sense of pleasure or displeasure: ‘Hier
Kantian paradigm is no longer a suitable candidate for such
wird die Vorstellung gänzlich auf das Subjekt, und zwar auf das
criticism. ‘The mistake of Kantian art criticism is that it seg-
Lebensgefühl desselben, unter dem Namen des Gefühls der Lust
regates form from content’ (AEA 98). But this is a wrong read-
oder Unlust, bezogen’ (KdU §1). In other words, the aesthetic
ing of Kant based on a common misunderstanding of the Kri-
judgement is not cognitive, it is about how we feel and expe-
tik der Urteilskraft (1790). Danto takes issue with Kant’s notion
rience a representation. The aesthetic judgement expresses
of disinterestedness, the idea that we should judge beauty ‘ohne
how the subject feels itself while perceiving a representation:
alles Interesse’ (KdU §2). He takes Kant to mean that disinter-
it is an experience ‘in der das Subjekt [...] sich selbst fühlt’ (ibid.).
estedness implies that we must void ourselves of feeling and
This means that the representation or Vorstellung is submit-
become neutered perceivers who simply register forms. Read
ted to the felt experience or ‘Lebensgefühl’ of the subject. If the
in this way, and the reading is quite common among Kant’s
representation kindles a pleasurable felt experience, it may
critics, Kant’s aesthetics becomes reductively formalist and is
be called beautiful, if not, it may be called ugly. But Kant goes
merely about registering relations between shapes and forms.
on to say that for such a judgement to be pure it must be dis-
In this way, Kant’s work is read as essentially a philosophy of
interested. This means that the aesthetic judgement must be
abstract art: the sheer play of forms in space or on a plane.
wholly aesthetic: it must consider only the way the representa-
Something that you can apply to Mondriaan, but to not much
tion we perceive engages our felt experience. We must not be
else. But while Kant’s philosophy does allow of a philosophy
motivated in our judgement by any kind of extra-aesthetic
127
128
considerations, be they practical, moral, financial, or of any
or some abstract graph). It is simply erroneous to think that
other kind. The aesthetic judgement must be exclusively
Kant reduces all our perceptions to a set of geometric shapes
concerned with the aesthetic, namely perception and how this
with colours painted in. The things we perceive are not sche-
perception makes us feel. Disinterestedness implies that no
matic forms but landscapes, birds and birdsong, paintings,
non-aesthetic issues may come into play. This does indeed
boys and girls, a sunset, and so on. A Kantian perceiver does
sound like a formalist aesthetic: it is concerned only with
not reduce these objects to abstract geometric schemata, he
the way perceived shapes and forms address our sense of
judges them as they are. All these things are in themselves
felt self. But two observations should be made to qualify this
shapes and forms. The whole of their perceptual properties
statement. First, Kant does not limit perceived shapes and
is what constitutes their form. When looking at a red rose
forms to geometrical shapes and forms (as common use of the
a Kantian does not see an irregular globe-like mass with
words shapes and forms might lead us to suppose); perceived
curved lines and frilly borders, all of it dyed in reddish hue; a
shapes and forms really encompass all the sensory data we en-
Kantian simply sees a rose. The rose is itself the form. Simi-
counter. Hence, a sound or a smell is also a perceived shape
larly, a Kantian perceiver does not see identical schemata of
or form. Second, Kant’s approach may sound distanced and
people walk around in the street as if they were a bunch of
formalist, but it is by no means void of feeling. On the con-
clones; he sees actual individual people. But to judge whether
trary, disinterestedness means that there should only be feel-
these people are beautiful he must make abstraction of his
ing, but feeling about the forms and shapes perceived. Beauty
own extra-aesthetic feelings about these people and merely
is about what pleases us in perception.
judge their perceptual properties as a unitary form. That is
But Danto’s claim was not about the segregation of form and
to say, for example, that a Kantian will have to make abstrac-
feeling in Kantian aesthetics but about the segregation of
tion of his personal dislike for his neighbour if he wants to
form and content. Danto might well grant the central role of
judge whether his neighbour is beautiful. The content of the
feeling in Kant’s aesthetics and still hold that any amount of
neighbour (“who he is” as an individual) is not segregated
feeling in judgement does not bestow content upon form. So
from his form, it is simply the perceiver’s personal interest
our argument does not really answer Danto’s objection at all,
that is segregated from his aesthetic judgement. Kant himself
although it does point us in the right direction. The problem
states the point very clearly: ‘If someone asks me whether
is that Danto presupposes that form itself cannot be content.
I find the palace that I see before me beautiful, I may well
And this is really the crucial issue, for a Kantian may very
say that I don’t like that sort of thing, which is made merely
well hold that it is. Kant’s third critique is not a philosophy
to be gaped at, or, [...] I might even vilify the vanity of the
of art but an extension of Kant’s theory of perception. What
great who waste the sweat of the people on such superfluous
we perceive is never some abstract shape (except, of course,
things [...]. All of this might be conceded to me and approved;
if the object under consideration is itself an abstract painting
but that is not what is at issue here. One only wants to know
129
130
whether the mere representation of the object is accompa-
sensory experience with the innate categories of the mind.
nied with satisfaction in me’ (KdU §2; Guyer 2005: 557).
The trouble with this view, however, is the question of how
Obviously, Kant’s theory of beauty has many complexities
you bring the two together: where do senses and mind meet?
and raises many further difficulties that cannot be addressed
The third critique tried to bridge the gap in “reflecting judge-
here. What is important for us, however, is to make clear that
ment,” which comes about when the forms of perception and
a Kantian aesthetic does not preclude feeling or content,
the categories of the mind are allowed free play among each
which renders calling it “formalist” rather tricky and mislead-
other in the construction of perception. The power of judge-
ing. Kantian philosophy suggests that the feeling experienced
ment is the point where mind and body meet. To be sure, this
in aesthetic judgement is profoundly linked to the formal
is a highly simplified presentation of Kant’s argument. And it
properties of the object under consideration. These formal
remains open to question whether Kant’s bridging of the gap
properties are not some kind of abstraction but a particular
is at all successful and could pass the test of philosophical
content. But all particular content has a form or shape and
scrutiny. But that need not concern us here: what matters for
it is this form that must be judged. To see Kantian aesthet-
us is the mere fact that Kant had the intent to bridge the gap
ics as a disembodied formalist theory is therefore to miss its
between body and mind in the third critique, which puts the
point entirely, as art historian Amelia Jones does (but many
lie to any discussion of Kantian aesthetics that tries to sell it
others with her) when she claims that Kantian aesthetics and
off as an abstract and somehow “disembodied” enterprise.
the art criticism that derives from it ‘are predicated upon the suppression of the particular, embodied, desiring subject; the
Skirting Langer
artist and the critic must remain transcendent rather than
If anything, it is the Hegelian approach to art as we find it in
immanent (embodied)’ (Jones 2000: 20). It is true that Kant
Danto that appears to be guilty of a lack of embodiment. To
would consider a desiring subject a subject with interest, for
see this we should return to Danto’s discussion of Warhol’s
to desire something is the very definition of interest (KdU
Brillo Boxes, which he sees as very pure examples of what he
§2). But it is manifestly untrue that a Kantian perceiver must
calls “indiscernibles”: real objects and art objects that are so
be disembodied and transcendent. For Kant, there is beauty
similar that they cannot be told apart on the basis of visual
only in the particular because beauty is always grounded in
perception alone. But as we saw, Warhol’s Brillo Boxes are very
a judgement on subjective perception. The Kantian perceiver
easily told apart from the real thing: they are painted on
must be wholly embodied for it would be quite impossible
wood, handcrafted, and slightly smaller in size than the ac-
for him to judge anything if he had to go about without his
tual boxes. Nobody has ever approached a Warhol Brillo Box as
physical senses. In actual fact, Kant’s aesthetics were part
if it were an actual Brillo box. Danto seems to ignore this fact
of his attempt to bridge the gap between mind and body. As
and claims that with Warhol’s work ‘it becomes clear that
we saw, we construct our image of the world by combining
there is no special way a work of art must be – it can look like
131
132
a Brillo box, or it can look like a soup can’ (AEA 35). But this
the difference between the real and the counterfeit Napoleon.
is not really an issue about what art can be, it is about what
Danto seems to claim that the fact that an object is an indi-
can become a topic or motif in art. Warhol has never made a
vidually crafted and fictional work of art is not sufficient to
work of art that looks like a soup can. Warhol has painted im-
explain that it is different from the real thing it represents.
ages of soup cans, which is rather a different matter. Nobody
Danto’s inability to deal with the material facts of art is pain-
as yet has tried to open a Warhol painting of a Campbell’s
fully clear in The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (1981),
soup can to try and eat its contents for the very simple rea-
which relies almost entirely upon fictional examples of pos-
son that Warhol’s work is a painting and not a faux soup can
sible or hypothetical works of art. At one point Danto even
with misleading three-dimensional properties. A painting of
discusses a work that Picasso could have made (but obviously
a soup can is not a work of art that resembles a soup can: it
didn’t) at elaborate length. There is in fact very little actual
is an image that represents a soup can. That Danto overlooks
art under discussion in Danto’s book, which is devoted al-
the difference between an actual object and its representa-
most entirely to showing that art is now about philosophy.
tion in a two-dimensional image is rather alarming in a phi-
Danto’s main claim is that everyday or commonplace objects
losopher and critic. It clearly shows that his own theory of art
are turned into art (transfigured, so to speak) because of the
is so focused on the conceptual level, namely the idea that
meanings the artist or the critic attaches to them. But the
art has now become totally self-reflexive and hence a kind
transfigured object remains outwardly indiscernible from its
of philosophy about art, that he is totally blind to the material
non-artistic counterpart. As such, Danto’s book is an apol-
properties of the art under discussion. ‘It is true,’ he admits of
ogy for conceptual art. At one point in the discussion Danto
the Brillo Boxes, ‘that Warhol’s boxes were made of plywood,
brings up Nelson Goodman’s reasonable suggestion that total
stencilled by hand by Warhol and his assistants, and the
indiscernability between similar objects is highly unlikely
commercial cartons were made of printed cardboard on huge
and that close scrutiny of pairs of similar objects is almost
industrial presses. But that, surely, could not explain the dif-
logically determined to show up some difference between
ference between art and reality’ (Danto 2005: xi). But if that
them, especially if we are dealing with sets of objects one of
cannot explain the difference, I should like to know what can.
which is a work of art and one of which is not. Danto has a
To claim that the difference between the real thing and an
hard time refuting Goodman and reverts to the claim that ‘it
imitation cannot explain the difference between art and real-
is striking as a matter of concealed bias on Goodman’s part
ity is special pleading with a vengeance. In fact, I would say it
that he should spontaneously have assumed that all aesthetic
is simply stupid for by the same token one might claim that
differences are perceptual differences’ (CT 43). I fail to see the
the fact that the historical Napoleon Bonaparte was a physi-
bias in this: it is plain common sense. The only way to make
cal human being and David’s painting of Napoleon Bonaparte
Danto’s claim that aesthetic differences could be non-per-
is an image of the man in paint does not sufficiently explain
ceptual legitimate would be to assume that ideas or concepts
133
134
attached to objects are part of their aesthetic properties. As
The truth of the matter is that, contrary to Danto’s claims,
we will see, this is exactly what Danto assumes, but it ren-
most contemporary art is very clearly discernible as art.
ders the whole issue rather sterile. Since ideas and concepts
Most contemporary artists do not even try to make their
are not visible in themselves it is straining the meaning of
work look indistinguishably like an object in the real world.
“aesthetic” to categorise them in that rubric: to be percep-
It is certainly true that any object or any image can now be
tible (aesthetic in the etymological sense of “present to the
appropriated into art and that artists can now freely move
senses”) ideas and concepts must be expressed in material
between media and kinds of art, making a painting today, a
containers, not simply attached to them as some invisible
sculpture tomorrow, and maybe write a book or direct a film
Platonic Idea. But Danto is systematic in his madness for
next year. It is true that most of what we now happily con-
in the same paragraph he claims that ‘future investigation
cede is art could only become art in our Post-Historical age
may reveal differences between two objects which are not
of pluralism. But that does not mean that all those works are
perceptual differences’ (ibid.) but, we may now assume, dif-
not distinguishable from ordinary objects. Or, to paraphrase
ferences in meaning. The problem with this (apart from the
the title of Danto’s own book, the commonplace has not
fact that an appeal to hypothetical results of possible future
simply or even primarily been transformed in a conceptual
research is a council of despair even in the most speculative
way: when artists work with commonplace objects they usu-
of metaphysics) is of course that the presence of some idea
ally change a lot about their material conditions and hence
or concept in or around an object can be neither proved nor
their form, their presentation, their context, their stylistic
disproved, which makes the entire argument facile or void or,
features. Most art that deals with the commonplace does not
at least, uninteresting. Hence, Danto’s entire claim is (in Witt-
transform the commonplace rather than depict it or use it as a
genstein’s sense) senseless.
material. A Wolfgang Tillmans photograph of the Concorde is
But let us return to the indiscernibles. Danto’s claim that it
not the Concorde itself, just as David’s portrait of Napoleon
is now impossible to tell art objects apart from “real” objects
Bonaparte is not the actual chieftain of the French. And a
because anything can be art has only ever been true of a very
Sarah Lucas sculpture made of cigarettes is itself hardly an
limited class of conceptual art objects. It certainly does not
object for smoking (I was going to add that so far nobody has
hold of Duchamp’s urinal, which is often the prime exhibit of
tried to shove Paul McCarthy’s giant butt-plugs up his be-
Hegelian conceptual theories, but of which Elizabeth Frank
hind as if they were real all-kinds-of-anal-pleasure-inducing
has rightly pointed out that it ‘was turned upside down
butt-plugs, but I refrain). What these artists do, and what in
when first shown in New York in 1917; it had a signature,
fact artists have done through most of art history, is to take
“R. Mutt” and, however much it scandalised people, nobody
objects or people that are present in the real world and use
peed in it, at least not to my knowledge; had it been placed
them as a motif, a topic, a model, a tool, an ingredient, a
in a real men’s room, nobody would have’ (Frank 1996: 279).
material. They represent or alter the commonplace object.
135
136
Hence, the object is no longer a commonplace object, just
seems problematic to me, especially since her work offers so
like the paint applied to a canvas by a painter is no longer
many valid answers to the questions Danto poses. Further-
the commonplace object it was while it was still inside the
more, in a criticism of Langer in Art After the End of Art (1997),
tube. The artist does not transform the commonplace paint
Danto claims that feeling and form (the title of Langer’s great
itself into art but uses it as a material for art. Danto does not
work) ‘have tended overall to rule one another out’ (AEA
get this. For example, he refers to 1960s ‘avant-garde dance,
112). But to say that feeling and form rule each other out one
where dance movements, outwardly indistinguishable from
must hold a naive traditional view of feelings as irrational
simple bodily movements, began to be performed. What was
and shapeless and therefore opposed to the rational clarity
the difference between walking and performing a dance
of forms. But as Langer points out, feelings and emotions
movement that consisted in walking?’ (Danto 2005: xi-xii)
only seem irrational ‘because language does not help to make
The difference is very simply that in the dance the walking
them conceivable, and most people cannot conceive any-
movement has become a motif that is used within the pri-
thing without the logical scaffolding of words’ (PS 88). To be
mary illusion of the dance.
more precise, it is discursive language that fails to adequately
This takes us right into the work of Susanne K. Langer, who
express emotions because it ‘does not reflect the material
claims that anything, even the most commonplace object or
form of feeling’ (PS 89). This is why man develops art, ritual,
movement, can become a motif in art if it is integrated in an
religion, and metaphor: their symbolism offers logical forms
expressive form. For Langer the formal properties of a work
that do express the forms of feeling. Danto’s claim that feel-
of art are related to the feeling or content they are meant to
ing and form are at odds becomes even more bizarre in light
convey. In this sense her work is a fine example of how one
of passages in his own work that have a decidedly Langerian
can develop an aesthetic theory that is Kantian in inspiration
ring. For instance, Danto uses (late) Wittgenstein’s notion
(but developed via Ernst Cassirer and John Dewey, amongst
of “forms of life” to illustrate that every style of painting is
others) without segregating form and content or form and
embedded in a form of life and cannot simply be transposed
feeling. Langer manages to evade the segregation through her
to another period. Such a period ‘is not simply an interval of
keen insight into symbolism and language. But Danto rarely
time, but rather such an interval in which the forms of life
mentions Langer. This is odd, for when he does mention
lived by men and women have a complex philosophical iden-
her, he refers to her as ‘my teacher, and my friend’ (AB 2; cfr.
tity, as something lived and known about in the way we know
AEA 112). I do not know the details of Danto’s relationship to
about things by living them’ (AEA 201). When Danto claims
Langer, whether he studied under her or simply sat in on her
that the way art is made, including its style, is closely related
lectures. But I do assume that you may be taken to be conver-
to a form of life as it is experienced by the people living it, he
sant with a philosopher’s ideas if you label that philosopher
is really suggesting that there is link between subjective feel-
your teacher and friend. So Langer’s absence in Danto’s work
ing (of which daily experience is a part) and the forms that
137
138
may be used to express it.
any object, any gesture, any motif, no matter how common-
There are probably several reasons why Danto skirts Langer.
place. Judging by the brief Foreword Danto fabricated for the
It is not uncommon for thinkers to develop a blind spot for
abridged edition of Langer’s three-volume Mind, published in
other thinkers by whom they have been profoundly influ-
1988, it certainly seems as if Langer’s hovering intellectual
enced or whose ideas they perceive as a philosophical threat
presence was in need of exorcism for Danto calls Mind ‘a
to their own theories because they get too close for comfort.
work inadequate in its original execution’ and ‘an unwieldy
So Langer beat Danto to the idea of the Post-Historical era
book’ in which ‘the supporting material obscures the philo-
by at least a decade (Danto first formulated his views in a
sophical architecture’ (Danto 1988: vi). Coming from the au-
paper published in 1964). But there may be a strategic reason
thor of The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, which is one of
behind Danto’s tiptoeing around Langer. Danto has the clear
recent philosophy’s most plodding books, comments about
intention of promoting himself as a key historical figure. In
obscured philosophical architecture are somewhat ironic.
the Introduction to Unnatural Wonders (2005) Danto writes
More importantly, Danto completely disregards the custom
about his own experience after publishing his essay about
that a Foreword, especially the Foreword to a book by a friend
the end of art in 1984. ‘Though it took awhile for the fact to
who had died only a brief few years before and was therefore
dawn on me, I was in a sense the first posthistorical critic of
no longer around to defend herself, is supposed to be lauda-
art. There were of course plenty of art critics in the period we
tory. That Danto uses such a Foreword to disparage Langer’s
had now entered. What was special about me was that I was
work is in very poor taste to say the least. But whatever Dan-
the only one whose writing was inflected by the belief that
to’s (obviously conflicted) relation to Langer may be, I believe
we were not just in a new era of art, but in a new kind of era’
that Langer’s theory of art is exactly what Danto needs to
(Danto 2005b: 3). Danto’s inflated sense of his own impor-
get out of the chaos the art critic in the Post-Historical era
tance is illustrated when he next claims that he only has one
finds himself in. Langer’s view of art as expressive form is
real forerunner: Hegel. Danto does put himself in rather lofty
sufficiently general to take in all the arts. She discusses all
company, although a more sober-minded critic might argue
the major forms of art that were about when she was writ-
that what made Danto special was the way he developed a
ing. She obviously does not address performance or video art
sense of his own towering historical importance from getting
or other more recent kinds of art that have developed in the
his Kant all backwards.
pluralist era. But as we will see in the next chapter, her ideas
The one thing that could deflate Danto’s self-promotion is
can very easily be expanded to include newer forms of art in
to find another thinker who had already proposed similar
a meaningful way. But at the same time Langer’s ideas are
claims in the recent past. To be sure, Langer never suggests
sufficiently specific to make criticism possible. This is in fact
we have entered a new era, but she did suggest already in
the great strength of her concept of “primary illusion,” which
Feeling and Form that anything could be integrated in art:
defines in a clear but general way what is the basic structure
139
of every kind of art. Langer tells us what art is, what it does,
forever seeking out anything that is new and has a radical
and how it does that in its several forms. The implications of
ring to it, so we may be sure that they have done the Danto
her theory therefore make it ideally suited to deal with art in
thing). Or maybe Danto was right when he said that art had
the Post-Historical era.
ended in 1964 but his theory no longer applies to more recent art because history has moved on after all. That would mean
140
A Short History of the Avant-Garde
that art after art has not necessarily been made in the mode
Let us return to Danto’s claim that the Post-Historical era
of the end of history. Possibly, something entirely different
means the end of the Age of Manifestos. This claim is clearly
may be going on. But whatever it is, we shall make it the
related to the claim that we have witnessed, in recent times,
business of the present section to try and see more clearly
the end of the avant-garde. The avant-garde, after all, was a
into the matter of what has happened to the avant-garde in
Modernist idea that expressed many artists’ sense that they
the current pluralistic age.
were in the vanguard of history. But if there are no more
The first thing to consider is that several noted authors of-
master narratives there can be no more avant-gardes. In
fer readings of the history of the avant-garde that seem to
reality, however, the rhetoric of avant-garde has never left
discredit several aspects of Danto’s presentation. In his clas-
the artworld. In fact, with the advent of postmodern Theory
sic theory of the avant-garde Peter Bürger distinguishes the
imported from France since the late 1960s, great progress into
historical avant-garde from the neo-avant-garde (Bürger 1974:
ever new areas of profound new theoretical insight has been
44-45). The historical avant-garde emerged at the end of the
announced with numbing regularity. It sometimes sounds
nineteenth century and is exemplified by Dadaism and Surre-
as if every new book by every famous critic were rewriting
alism. Its core project was to dissolve art into life. The histori-
the whole of history from the point of view of new theoreti-
cal avant-garde was a reaction to bourgeois culture. Bourgeois
cal insights that are invariably shaking the foundations of
culture saw a gradual division of society into several autono-
Western culture. Despite the widespread belief in historical
mous areas, similar to the division of labour in the industrial
relativism and the end of the master narratives talk of prog-
area. This means that art also gradually developed into an
ress towards new insights has continually poured forth from
autonomous practice, with the artist emerging as a “special-
people, mostly theorists, who seem to firmly believe they are
ist” in the same way that any other craftsman or labourer
at the vanguard of the very history presumed dead. This is
could be a specialist in some specific activity (o.c. 42). This
odd, to say the least, and several explanations come to mind.
emancipation of art culminated in Aestheticism, which is the
Maybe Danto was simply wrong in talking of the end of art
final consolidation of art as a separate institution within soci-
and the dawn of the Post-Historical era. Maybe he was right
ety. As art grew more independent from other areas of society
but the trendies of Theory are simply still having to catch up
it also lost its influence in society and ceased to play a defin-
with the fact (but this seems unlikely since the trendies are
ing social role. In earlier times, especially in the Middle Ages
141
142
and the Renaissance, art had been closely linked to the needs
avant-garde art had been more or less limited in its expres-
and demands of the church or the aristocratic classes. In the
sive possibilities by an epochal style that determined more
Renaissance the evolution towards emancipation started
or less what ways of making art were available to artists. In
with the emergence of highly idiosyncratic personal styles.
contrast, the avant-garde never developed a canonical style.
In the Middle Ages most artistic production had been anony-
Not only were there many strands within the avant-garde,
mous, in the Renaissance the individual genius took centre
but even within every strand there was no canon for creation.
stage. With the triumph of bourgeois culture over aristocratic
No two Dadaist works look alike and neither do two Surreal-
culture art’s function within society changed dramatically:
ist works. With the avant-garde everything becomes possible:
the artist now became a merchant trying to sell his goods on
every style and every means of expression suddenly comes at
the art market. Individual style and excellence became all-
the artist’s disposal (o.c. 23-24). This means that Bürger situ-
important whereas traditional social or moral messages de-
ates the switch to what Danto would call the Post-Historical
creased in importance because the average collector was now
era, where everything is possible, in the era of the historical
a bourgeois individual who did not seek political statements
avant-garde. Its prime exhibit is, obviously, Duchamp’s urinal.
but art that would enhance his own conception of himself as
In this work Duchamp questions several core tenets of art in
a citizen and bourgeois. In the bourgeois period the classical
the bourgeois period, first and foremost the institution of art
tension in art between form and message was eliminated in
itself. By placing a urinal in a museum Duchamp questions
a decisive shift towards the dominance of form (or a signa-
the position of the artist as the unique creator of the work.
ture style). It is this shift that would help make Modernism
He also questions the institutions that were linked to the
possible, the series of artistic movements that question the
bourgeois conception of art: the museum and the exhibition.
nature of artistic representation itself.
The prime tactic of the historical avant-garde was provoca-
Aestheticism is the end point of the evolution of bourgeois
tion, a kind of shock tactics that was aimed at taunting the
art. It clearly shows the dual nature of art in bourgeois soci-
public and making it reflect on art and life. A favoured prin-
ety. On the one hand Aestheticism shows the full autonomy
ciple in this project was estrangement (‘Verfremdung’; o.c. 24).
of art: it is only about itself, it is sheer form. But by implica-
However, the avant-garde never really exploded the au-
tion it also shows the full emancipation of art from society in
tonomy of art. It simply subverted its categories. The reason
the sense that such an Aestheticist art has lost all influence
for this is quite simply that any art that merges entirely with
in society. It is socially impotent and at worst (from the point
life would cease to be art at all. The success of Duchamp’s
of view of social influence) merely decorative. For Bürger the
provocation is entirely dependent upon the existence of the
historical avant-garde was a reaction against the impotent
category of the artist as the autonomous maker of the work
autonomy of art. It rejected bourgeois art in a radical way and
of art. Without such a framing theory the urinal becomes
sought to re-integrate art into life. Until the emergence of the
simply a urinal and loses all its subversive power. This is
143
what makes the neo-avant-garde an impossibility. For Bürger
if it wants to have any kind of critical or subversive effect in
the neo-avant-garde comprises the conceptual, minimalist,
society, i.e. if art wants to be some kind of protest, it needs to
and performance movements emerging since the late 1950s.
be autonomous, which means that art must be separate from
The problem with art such as Duchamp’s urinal lies in its
the practice of everyday life (o.c. 73). This certainly raises
nature as a unique event. One cannot repeat it. ‘Duchamp’s
many questions about community art or any kind of activity
ready-mades are not works of art,’ Bürger writes, ‘but mani-
aimed at the strengthening of the social fabric that is pre-
festations’ (o.c. 71). Contrary to Danto, Bürger claims that
sented as art. Despite the many claims of conceptual art and
the power of the urinal has nothing to do with the classical
other kinds of “critical” art since the 1960s, Bürger’s analysis
tension between form and content (or meaning), but with
suggests that all this recent art is not really critical at all be-
the tension between a factory-made serial object on the one
cause it simply repeats gestures that were critical only when
hand and the fact that the artist has signed it and thus in-
they first emerged in the historical avant-garde.
scribes it into the bourgeois narrative of the artist as the au-
144
tonomous maker of art. Once the idea that the individual is
Kondylian Combinations
necessarily the creator of the work has been dispensed with
Bürger’s history of the avant-garde is corroborated in an
within the artworld such gestures lose all force. Art after Duch-
interesting way in Panajotis Kondylis’ history of the decay
amp has been very willing to accept ready-mades (or indis-
of the bourgeois way of life and the emergence of mass de-
cernibles) as “real” works of art. This means that the idea of
mocracy. Kondylis argues that every culture looks at reality
the artist as individual creator has been abandoned and that
from a specific perspective or worldview. Such a worldview
the category of “the work of art,” which the historical avant-
is created to cope with the world: it is a means of survival in
garde sought to dismantle, has been restored (o.c. 78). So all
a hostile environment. By imposing a certain view upon the
such provocation after Duchamp simply falls flat because the
world, a culture establishes an identity that allows it to con-
avant-garde has been institutionalised: in the 1960s nobody
trol the world. Through this control a culture and its inhabit-
was shocked when commonplace objects were presented
ants are able to keep themselves alive (Kondylis 1984: 14).
as art. We had seen it before and the thrill was gone. This,
This means that every worldview is designed in relation to
according to Bürger, was the problem facing the neo-avant-
whatever may threaten a culture’s survival. These threats are
garde of the 1950s and 1960s. The ideas of the historical
the culture’s enemies. In primitive cultures the enemy may
avant-garde have become common currency in the artworld
be wild animals or poisonous plants, but in our more devel-
of the late twentieth century, ‘so the gestures of protest of the
oped societies the worldview is usually designed to identify
neo-avant-garde become prey to inauthenticity. Their claim
and do battle with ideological enemies, namely groups of
to protest can no longer be sustained because it cannot be
people or cultures that live by another and usually conflicting
made good on’ (ibid.). This leads Bürger to conclude that art,
worldview. This means that for Kondylis ‘es gibt keinen anderen
145
methodischen Zugang zur Erfassung des Charakters einer Epoche oder einer Gesellschaftsformation als ihre Abgrenzung gegen eine frühere oder eine andere’ (Kondylis 1991: 287). To understand a culture or epoch one must understand against what or whom it was constructed. For instance, the worldview of the Enlightenment was developed as a strategic answer to the christian worldview of the Middle Ages. The christian worldview saw everything from the perspective of religion and salvation, with the main focus of attention lying in the afterworld. It was a world of disembodiment and spirituality. The Enlightenment was a strategic answer to the challenge of gaining victory over this worldview by trying to rethink the relationship between mind and body (Kondylis 2002: 19). A specific way in which this strategic answer took form can be seen in modern aesthetics, notably in the works of Schil-
146
ler and Kant. As we saw before, Kant’s aesthetic theory was an attempt to bridge the gap between body and mind. This means that he was trying to undo the bifurcation of body and mind that was at the heart of Christianity, where the body had to be mortified and only the immortal soul would be saved. A similar tactic is at work in Schiller’s work, where the arts, and notably the theatre, are engaged in a didactic process: the theatre can be used as a stage for attractively packaged moral messages. However, Schiller argued for the autonomy of art: whatever moral message a work of art may present, it could only be successfully conveyed if the work of art was not subservient to morality. There had to be harmony of form and content and neither of the two should dominate the other. Kondylis has called the mechanism at work in modern aesthetics ‘the rehabilitation of the sensual’ (‘die Panajotis Kondylis
Rehabilitation der Sinnlichkeit’; ibid.): both Kant’s and Schiller’s
147
148
works (but the works of many others too, and not merely in
according to Kondylis, is therefore time: there is a trend to-
aesthetics) can be seen as attempts to re-enfranchise the
wards harmony that develops through time. Modernity is the
physical realm in view of the traditional hostility towards it.
culture of perfectibility. History is a process of progress. In
One way of doing this was to stress the moral potential of art:
the arts bourgeois culture is expressed in Classicism, where
aesthetic enjoyment (which is sinful in a christian perspec-
there is a symmetrical relation between the whole and its
tive) could serve higher moral ends. But both Kant and Schil-
parts and a perfect union of form and content, as in Schiller’s
ler stress the autonomy of art in this process, which chimes
proposals for the theatre. In the modern view, art is included
with Bürger’s claim that bourgeois culture evolved towards
in the history of organic progress for it is usually seen as the
an emancipation of the aesthetic into an autonomous realm.
highest triumph of nature: it is in art that mankind achieves
In Kant this trend towards autonomy of the aesthetic is most
the highest expression of himself. It is no coincidence that
clear in the element of disinterestedness which we have al-
this idea was also at the heart of Schiller’s aesthetics, where
ready discussed.
it is art that allows man to bind together his sensual and his
Kondylis has sketched bourgeois culture as ‘synthetic-
moral self (Kant’s body and mind) in a greater harmony that
harmonising’ (‘synthetisch-harmonisierend’; Kondylis 1991:
is his highest human calling.
15): it is a worldview that is well-ordered and scientific and
Bourgeois culture in its pure form only existed for a very
aims at a harmonic synthesis of opposites. It tries to bring
brief period of time. It soon started to erode from within.
everything together in what can be called le juste milieu. This
This process becomes especially visible in the second half of
term is borrowed from the arts, but we find it equally at work
the nineteenth century, when the emancipation of the sev-
in the other aspects of culture. For example, deism seeks to
eral spheres of action becomes clearly visible. The decline of
harmonise the existence of a superior being with the find-
bourgeois culture is in many ways a parallel process to the
ings of modern science, thus saving both traditional moral-
division of labour, as Bürger also claimed. The nineteenth
ity and modern science from mutual embarrassment (and
century saw the gradual emancipation of the labourer in the
philosophical writers from possible prosecution by church or
emergence of social movements. This started a process of at-
state). In the case of Kant, the harmonising middle ground
omisation of society: as the twentieth century progresses, the
lies in his attempt to bridge the gap between body and mind,
individual comes more and more to the fore and egalitarian
whereas Schiller epitomised the rehabilitation of the sensual
ideals gain ground. This is an effect of the process of emanci-
in his moral mission for the theatre. But apart from harmo-
pation of bourgeois culture. Artistically, this process came to
nising, the modern bourgeois worldview is also organic in
an end with Aestheticism, art for art’s sake. This means that
structure. This is expressed in the idea of Bildung: man has
the autonomy of art, which we saw emerge in Kant’s idea of
an essential nature which must be nurtured to bring it to
disinterestedness, had finally run its course. On this point,
fruition. The prime metaphor to understand modern culture,
Kondylis’ analysis merges with Bürger’s: the avant-garde
149
150
(or what Bürger calls the historical avant-garde) demands
space in which all individuals, lifestyles, values, or objects are
the end of art in the sense that art and life must merge. On
simply at hand. There is no hierarchy. There is no individual
a more general level, the synthetic-harmonising culture of
more valuable than any other, no lifestyle more favourable
bourgeois modernity makes way for a new culture that will
than any other. Everything is equal. Which means that things
evolve into the postmodern. The postmodern is no longer
are simply at hand in space as in a huge window display or
aimed at synthesis or harmony and is described by Kondylis
on a counter. This is the analytical aspect: everything is bro-
as ‘analytical-combinatory’ (‘analytisch-kombinatorisch’; ibid.).
ken down into its most basic constituents. The combinatory
Society is no longer harmonised but analysed into its con-
aspect next says that all these elements can be combined in
stituent parts. This means that the process of emancipation
whatever combinations we please. This means that personal-
started in bourgeois culture is taken to its logical extreme:
ity is no longer seen as a temporal thing, as in the ideal of Bil-
every individual becomes important in its unique individual-
dung. People construct their personality: they make choices,
ity. This is the emergence of the atomised society that we call
identify themselves as belonging to specific subcultures, they
mass democracy. In a 1961 lecture Langer has referred to this
choose their gender roles, their jobs, their dress, everything.
as a process of individuation; a process that she felt had ‘all
And no choice is ever final: there are no essences and every
but reached its limit. Society is breaking up into its ultimate
choice can always be traded for another styling of the self
units – single individuals, persons’ (PS 140). Langer looked at
and its mercurial identities. We no longer accumulate our
this process with some concern because ‘the fact is that in
personality through time but assemble it as a work of art. For
our Western culture [...] each individual really stands alone’
the arts this means that artists can use whatever they want
(ibid.) and many people ‘feel, but cannot understand, their
in whatever combination they want. The prime example of
loss of the sense of involvement, which makes the world
postmodern or analytical-combinatory art is the collage, or
seem like a meaningless rat race in which they are reduced
the collection of perspectives in a Cubist painting. In fact,
to nothingness, alone in life and in death’ (PS 141). A parallel
Bürger maintains that montage should be considered ‘the
process can be seen in the arts of what we now call Mod-
basic principle of avant-garde art’ (Bürger 1974: 97), partly
ernism: artists seek the primary elements of art, be it pure
because its explicitly constructed nature is the exact oppo-
colours or shapes, basic forms, or the basic elements of per-
site of the organic concept of art found in bourgeois culture
ception (Kondylis points out that modernism in history and
(Robert Rauschenberg tellingly referred to some of his works
Modernism in the arts do not coincide: artistic Modernism is
as “combines”). This again means that what Danto has called
in fact the kind of art developed in the postmodern era). This
the Post-Historical condition in art, namely the fact that
is what Danto calls the Age of Manifestos.
anything can become art or be integrated in art, is in fact a
The guiding metaphor of postmodernity is not time but
feature of artistic Modernism. Both Bürger and Kondylis show
space. Mass democracy can be represented as a huge plane or
that Danto is at least fifty years behind when he defines 1964
151
152
as the point in time where the Post-Historical era emerges.
gardless of its intent, was an actual urinal, whereas Warhol’s
If we hold that Danto errs when he sees 1964 as a watershed
Brillo Boxes, for all their resemblance to the real thing, were
in the history of art we must ask why he preferred Warhol’s
fictional representations of the actual boxes. In fact, since
Brillo Boxes over Duchamp’s upturned urinal as the crucial
Warhol’s boxes were handmade and smaller than the real
turning point in art. This choice was motivated in part by
thing they had far less formal similarities to reality than Du-
his concept of Pop Art, which, according to Danto, ‘set itself
champ’s urinal, which was (we must repeat) an actual urinal.
against art as a whole in favour of real life’. In fact, Pop Art
Because he never looks at the materiality of art, Danto simply
answered to a ‘universal sense that people wanted to en-
gets his Duchamp and his Warhol mixed up. Warhol’s faux
joy their lives now, as they were, and not on some different
boxes are much more in the tradition of the imitation of real-
plane or in some different world or in some later stage of
ity than Duchamp’s ready-mades because they are fictional
history for which the present was a preparation’ (AEA 131).
representations of the real world. If Warhol feels free to take
There is certainly truth in this: Pop Art did celebrate the or-
ordinary boxes as a motif in his art, Duchamp had already
dinary world and often had a decidedly upbeat feel. On the
gone one step further and simply used real objects as art in
other hand, much of Warhol’s and Rauschenberg’s work is
themselves. So from Danto’s point of view Duchamp’s act is
concerned with death, disaster, or neurosis, and much Pop
much more telling than Warhol’s.
is highly ironic or critical towards the reality it depicts. Nev-
But in order to see this, one must take the materiality of the
ertheless, Danto feels that what happened in Pop was pro-
works into consideration, which Danto simply does not do. So
foundly different from what happened in Duchamp. ‘What-
the fact that Danto is about fifty years behind in situating the
ever he achieved, Duchamp was not celebrating the ordinary.
turn towards the Post-Historical in 1964 is much more than
He was, perhaps, diminishing the aesthetic and testing the
an error in chronology: it points towards a deficient grasp of
boundaries of art.’ But the resemblances between Duchamp’s
what happens in art. Danto has simply magnified his own
ready-mades and Pop Art ‘are far less striking than those be-
misguided response to Warhol’s boxes to historic propor-
tween Brillo Box and ordinary Brillo cartons. What makes the
tions. Danto should have realised by now that it was his own
difference between Duchamp and Warhol is similarly far less
lack of knowledge about the recent history of art that made
difficult to state than what is the difference between art and
Warhol’s Brillo Boxes such an overwhelming experience. His
reality’ (AEA 132). Again, there is some truth in this. We can
instincts about a shift in what art was about was correct, but
agree that Duchamp’s gestures were primarily an attempt to
he should have realised that the shift had already occurred
test the boundaries of art. But then we again meet Danto’s
much earlier. Danto has simply taken the moment when he
claim that Warhol’s Brillo Boxes are much more profoundly
became aware of the shift, namely 1964, as the moment that
indiscernible from reality than a Duchamp urinal. And this, I
the actual shift took place. But that is of course a fatal error.
believe, is not the case. For one thing, Duchamp’s urinal, re-
In Danto’s case the error leads to an interpretation that is
153
154
further discredited by his highly tendentious reading, or lack
Commonplace (1981) is the best place to start. Danto here ar-
of reading, of works of art as material objects. For instance,
gues his claim that ‘the philosophical question of its status
commenting on Warhol’s early paintings of comic strips and
has almost become the very essence of art itself, so that the
advertisements, Danto writes that ‘in 1961 no one would have
philosophy of art, instead of standing outside the subject and
seriously considered either the comic strip images or the
addressing it from an alien and external perspective, became
pictures used in the advertisements as art, but the Pop move-
instead the articulation of the internal energies of the sub-
ment assigned artistic value to the images of everyday life’
ject. It would today require a special kind of effort at times to
(Danto 2005b: xi). But we should not accept too readily that
distinguish art from its own philosophy. It has seemed almost
Pop Art did that. Pop artists certainly felt justified in using
the case that the entirety of the artwork has been condensed
such images as motifs in art, but that is something quite dif-
to that portion of the artwork which has always been of phil-
ferent from attributing artistic value to the everyday images
osophical interest, so that little if anything is left for the plea-
themselves. The fact that I paint a Campbell’s soup can or a
sure of artlovers. Art [...] has turned into self-consciousness,
hot-dog does not necessarily imply that I believe the soup
the consciousness of art being art in a reflexive way that bears
can or hot-dog itself to be a work of art. Here we once again
comparison with philosophy, which itself is consciousness
see Danto’s inability or unwillingness to discriminate be-
of philosophy; and the question now remains as to what in
tween an object and its artistic representation. That a paint-
fact distinguishes art from its own philosophy.’ According to
ing of a comic strip is art does not imply that the comic strip
Danto, ‘artworks have been transfigured into exercises in the
itself is art (although it might well be argued that it is if it can
philosophy of art’ and ‘the definition of art has become part
be shown to have artistic import). This is exactly what makes
of the nature of art in a very explicit way’ (TC 56). This shift
Danto an exasperating critic to argue with, for how do you
means that the Kantian-formalist approach to art has lost its
argue with a critic who claims that the fact that a painting is
relevance because the element of aesthetic pleasure is now
a painted representation is not relevant to distinguish it from its
outmoded. Art is about meanings. Danto compares art to the
model in real life?
philosophy of science, ‘which holds that there is no observation without interpretation’ and claims ‘that something of
Art and Philosophy
the same order is true in art. To seek a neutral description is
Let us return to the suggestion that the end of a master nar-
to see the work as a thing and hence not as an artwork: it is
rative about art also signals (or should logically signal) the
analytical to the concept of an artwork that there has to be
end of the avant-garde. To understand how the artworld
an interpretation’ (TC 124). This is fair enough, and Langer
has reacted to the end of the avant-garde we must first get
would certainly not dispute this since her definition of art as
a clearer understanding of what Danto sees as the special
expressive form immediately entails that there is meaning in
nature of art after the end of art. The Transfiguration of the
art, which in turn always entails the possibility of and pos-
155
156
sible need for interpretation of some kind.
meaning of “aesthetic” presupposes the first, which means
But then Danto does something interesting. He claims that
that our perception of objects cannot change in the sense
‘seeing an object, and seeing an object that interpretation
of “pertaining to beauty” either. A possible third meaning of
transforms into a work, are clearly distinct things, even when
“aesthetic” is “pertaining to whether something is or is not
in fact the interpretation gives the object back to itself, as
a work of art”. This means that to judge aesthetically is to
it were, by saying the work is the object’ (TC 125). This sug-
make an ontological differentiation between objects that are
gests that an ordinary object is somehow transformed or
and objects that are not works of art. But this third meaning
transfigured in our perception (‘seeing’) by our interpretation
of “aesthetic” renders Danto’s claim about our changed per-
of it as art. ‘As a transformative procedure, interpretation is
ception circular because he holds that there are two orders
something like baptism, not in the sense of giving a name
of aesthetic response depending on whether something is
but a new identity, participation in the community of the
a work of art or not. This means that the first two mean-
elect’ (TC 126). Taken together, these two claims suggest that
ings of “aesthetic” can only become operative after an object
the same object will be perceived differently before and after
has been evaluated under the third. But how we perceive an
“baptism” because of the interpretation attached to it. I look
object (and whether it is beautiful in perception) is hardly
at a urinal and I see a urinal. Then along comes Duchamp,
a function of its being a work of art or not. In fact, only the
who declares the urinal a work of art, and suddenly, the uri-
question of whether we will attach an interpretation to it is
nal is changed in my perception. This leads Danto to claim that
a function of its being art or not. Artworks may be declared
‘there are two orders of aesthetic response, depending upon
different kinds of objects thanks to some inaugural transfigu-
whether the response is to an artwork or to a mere real thing
rative magic, but that does not make them differently percep-
that cannot be told apart from it’ (TC 94). But this is nonsense
tible kinds of objects in comparison to ordinary things, a fact
for several reasons. First, the meaning of the word “aesthetic”
Danto will again dispute in The Philosophical Disenfranchisement
in Danto’s claim is not at all clear. Since he is discussing the
of Art, where he claims that ‘the fact that something is an
act of “seeing” indiscernible works, aesthetic could mean, as
artwork makes an aesthetic difference, even if the artwork it
it etymologically means, “pertaining to perception”. But since
is is not to be told apart from a mere thing’ (PDA 26).
interpretations are in themselves invisible, the claim that
It is an indisputable and rather unsurprising fact that works
their presence changes our perception of objects is untenable
of art become works of art because they are presented as
in this sense of “aesthetic”. But “aesthetic” could also mean,
works of art. But we must be clear about what we mean by
and is most commonly used to mean, “pertaining to beauty”.
this. I am not defending an Institutional Theory of Art by
An “aesthetic” object is then simply a “beautiful” object. But
which an object is a work of art because you or I or the art-
since an object’s beauty is a function of its sensory qualities (I
world in general say so, although I do not want to deny that
must see, touch, or hear it before I can judge it beautiful) this
the Institutional Theory has a point either: an object must
157
158
be recognised as art by someone (but that could be anyone)
The symbolic nature of art offers an important clue to an-
before it becomes a candidate for the considerations usu-
other deficiency in Danto’s meaning-centred theory of art. To
ally bestowed upon art. This is not a great postmodern or
say that a work of art is a symbol with total reference (as we
Post-Historical insight but a truth of cultural relativism that
claimed earlier) is to say that a work of art is more than the
sociologists, anthropologists, and historians have been aware
sum of its parts: the elements must come together in a uni-
of for quite some time now. Several philosophers have known
fied symbol. To say that a commonplace object and a set of
it at least since Nietzsche, and a few others might even have
meanings or theoretical musings about the nature of art can
gleaned this relativist insight in Plato’s Republic. It is, in fact,
be combined to transfigure an everyday object into a work of
common sense, and has been since the modern era opened
art is to say that the sum of the parts does make up the work
up the world to New Worlds with different cultural practices.
of art. The word “transfiguration” is simply used to hide this
The problem with the claims of the Institutional Theory, or
fact, for when object and meanings meet there is never any
with Danto’s claim that it is an interpretation that turns an
fusion of the two into a greater organic whole. In fact, with a
object into art, is therefore not that it is wrong, but that it is
gullible public (or an audience greedy for a sense of trendy
banal; it teaches us nothing new, and, most damning, it tells
insiderness) you can attach just about any meaning to any
us nothing at all about what art actually is. And if we do want
everyday object. Take a chair, any chair, and theorise about
to learn something about the nature of art, I feel we should
how it expresses anguish, and sooner or later people will see
once again turn to Langer, who has shown that what turns an
anguish in it because they project anguish onto it. But they
object into art is something in the work itself, namely what we
need to be instructed to project anguish, for very few chairs
have called its framed or fictional or symbolic nature, which
exude anguish of their own accord. This is made clear when
presents it as not coextensive with the real world and an-
we consider that another critic or artist might just as easily
nounces its utter practical uselessness. The fictional nature of
make us see the chair as expressive of joy. Really good art
a work means that it is offered merely for our contemplation.
may have many meanings for many different people, but it is
The fictional, framed, or symbolic character of the work is in-
rarely that extensive or contradictory in its possible meanings
herent in the work itself: a painting, a novel, or a play are not
because good art does not simply have meanings attached
fictional symbols because you or I say so but because they
to it, the meanings inhere in it and emerge form the symbol;
were created that way. Works of art are created to be fictional
not by some kind of semantic magic, but because the artist
symbolic representations with no practical use: that is their
has inscribed the meanings into the form (in fact, it is Dan-
purpose (a purpose without practical purpose!). To be sure, I
to’s idea of transfiguration as a kind of creative baptism that
could make practical use of a book to kindle a fire, but every-
smacks of magic). Take for example Munch’s The Scream. This
one would immediately see that this is not the appropriate
painting is not simply an expression of anguish because you
use of a book, which is made for reading.
or I say so but because the anguish is there, in the material
159
160
conditions of the work, in its form, in the colours, in the han-
sort of way) that the mere fact that one shovel is isolated,
dling of the brushwork. Similarly, a performance of Waiting for
given a title, and presented as a work of art “baptises” it as a
Godot is not about nothingness because we so decree it but if
work of art (whether it is also good or even interesting art is
and only if the performance gives us a persuasive impression
a different matter entirely). But, Danto continues, if naming
of life in the mode of nothingness. And no amount of mean-
an object can transform it into art, ‘then, surely, appreciation
ing-pandering will ever convince me or you that The Scream
of these works must in part consist in feeling the philosophi-
is all about life-enhancing joy and that Beckett’s play is about
cal tensions they must give rise to, rather than, as it were,
the responsiveness of the natural world to our deeper emo-
mooning over their Significant Forms or whatever’ (PDA 31-
tional yearnings. In fact, even Duchamp’s urinal and Warhol’s
32). The cheap slur against Clive Bell aside (whose notion of
Brillo Boxes will not suffer just any meaning attached to them.
“significant form” Langer developed into “expressive form”)
Meanings and interpretations do not determine whether
this is true: the whole point of such works would seem to be
something is art; let alone that they would transfigure an
philosophical. But the case again remains that we can attach
object into a different kind of object.
any manner of title or meaning to any manner of common-
These issues are so complicated, and so confusingly handled
place object and philosophise about it all we like and none
in The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, that Danto felt com-
of this will make any kind of aesthetic difference, unless you
pelled to return to them in The Philosophical Disenfranchisement
take “aesthetic” to mean “pertaining to whether something
of Art (1986) to try and state his case more clearly, which he
is or is not art”. This meaning, of which Danto seems to be
did in some measure (and with greater wit), but to no avail
rather fond, certainly lies behind Danto’s statement that ‘my
since his case remains unpersuasive. To illustrate his argu-
view, philosophically, is that interpretations constitute works
ment Danto now introduces another set of indiscernibles,
of art’ (PDA 23), thereby shifting the question of what deter-
which in this case happen to be Duchamp’s snow shovel and
mines whether something is art to the inaugural moment
an indiscernible counterpart. One of the shovels is given a
when some applier of interpretation bestows artness upon it;
title and turned into a work of art, the other is not. Danto
which, despite Danto’s protestations to the contrary, sounds
claims of the shovel that is “also” a work of art that ‘its pro-
suspiciously like something akin to the Institutional Theory
motion to the status of art lifts it above, or at any rate outside
of Art. And regardless of the fact that Danto now speaks of
the domain of the mere utensil, and so there is a tension af-
a “tension” between works of art and commonplace objects,
ter all between work of art and tool’ (PDA 31). I have no more
this “tension” soon evolves back into ‘an aesthetic difference,
quarrel with this, for a “tension” is surely something different
even if the artwork it is is not to be told apart from a mere
from a perceptual difference. But we now see that there is
thing like a snow shovel’ (PDA 26); so our quarrel appears to
really nothing especially remarkable about Danto’s claims,
remain after all and Danto’s text is still a muddle of confused
for it is obviously true (in a banal, Institutional Theory of Art
meanings.
161
A final point. If Danto argues that ‘interpretation is in effect
quality was to be found in the interpretations attached to
the lever with which an object is lifted out of the real world
them, I might well wonder why I should bother to visit it at
and into the artworld’ (PDA 39) this claim really only holds in
all. Surely someone could tell me all about those meanings
a relevant way for a very specific set of works which we com-
without my having to make the excursion to a room full of
monly call conceptual works of art. Put differently, Danto’s
objects adorned with nothing but bare meanings.
theory would only hold for works of art that are well and
162
truly indiscernibles. But as we saw, such indiscernibles are
Beauty and Ugliness
very rare indeed. Even some of Danto’s prime exhibits like
Both Danto’s inability to really look at art and his dire need
Duchamp’s urinal and Warhol’s Brillo Boxes can be convinc-
for some Langerian insight are put in perspective if we look
ingly shown not to be indiscernibles after all; which leaves
at some cases of practical criticism in his work. In his book
Danto building a theory on a gallery of fictional or hypotheti-
The Abuse of Beauty (2003) Danto is puzzled by the fact that
cal works of art fashioned by such luminaries as the fictional
some people describe ugly art as beautiful. He addresses this
artists J and M, who are featured throughout The Transfigura-
problem in relation to Roger Fry’s important exhibitions of
tion of the Commonplace. Danto’s theory will not withstand
“Post-Impressionist” art at the Grafton Gallery in London in
scrutiny as a general principle, for as was shown above, it is
1910 and 1912. Fry argued that such works were experienced
the fictional character, the framing of the work, that makes
by many as ugly but that people would learn to appreciate
an object a work of art; if only because the recognition of its
their beauty once they had grown accustomed to their visual
artistic nature so often precedes interpretation. I would hardly
language: ‘every work of creative design is ugly until it be-
be induced to reflect upon a snow shovel’s metaphysical or
comes beautiful,’ Fry claims (Danto 2003: 34). But Danto dis-
other meanings had I not been told beforehand that this is
agrees with Fry and claims that the works in the shows were
not a mere snow shovel but a work of art and hence must
not beautiful and that one could never learn to perceive them
have some kind of surplus meaning beyond its practical func-
as beautiful. This does not diminish the works’ importance
tion in the Zeugzusammenhang of the everyday world. Danto
or their artistic import and value. It just means that not all
might now reasonably claim that interpreting and naming an
good art is beautiful (and that not all beautiful art is good art).
object and thus lifting it into the artworld is the very act of
Danto claims that ‘Matisse’s Blue Nude [1907] is a good, even
framing it and making it fictional. If this is his meaning, we
a great painting – but someone who claims it is beautiful is
can heartily agree and we probably have no quarrel after all.
talking through his or her hat’ (o.c. 36-37). In fact, ‘when one
But even though this may be a legitimate way of turning a
says that Blue Nude is beautiful, one is merely expressing ad-
commonplace object into art, it is surely the least interesting
miration for its strength and power’ (o.c. 88). For Danto, this
(and it is certainly not a “transfiguration”). In fact, if I were
is one of the central problems with Modernism: henceforth
invited to visit an exhibition of objects whose sole artistic
there was no longer a necessary link between beauty and ar-
163
164
tistic import. Great art could be, and would be, unmistakably
objects that are manifestly ugly. It is, on the contrary, to wield
ugly. ‘But Fry made it sound as if they were going to look aes-
a concept of beauty that is more well-defined and precise,
thetically beautiful once they were understood. But [...] works
and certainly more helpful, than the traditional “aesthetic”
might still be perceived as ugly even when we have come to
one. But there is a deeper problem still, because Matisse’s
see their “artistic excellence.” The recognition of excellence
Blue Nude is not at all ‘unmistakably ugly,’ as Danto would
need not entail a transformation in aesthetic perception.
have it. The work is supremely sensual and wonderfully ex-
They don’t change before one’s eyes, like frogs into princes.
pressive. Just look at the way the breasts of the woman are
[...] The ugly does not become beautiful just because the ugly
voluptuously rendered. Look at the curves of her left leg, the
art is good. My sense is that artistic excellence is connected
slight dent in her buttocks. Although it lacks representational
with what the art is supposed to do, what effect it is intended
fidelity, this image has the look and the feel of real human
to have’ (o.c. 107).
flesh. It seems that Danto’s judgement of Matisse’s painting
One problem with this argument (besides the fact that he still
is prejudiced by Danto’s own preconceptions about what art
believes artistic import cannot lie in a work’s formal prop-
should be and how it functions. If he cannot see the stunning
erties) once again lies in the fact that Danto never defines
beauty of Matisse’s Blue Nude, Danto has no business being an
“beauty” or “aesthetic”. He here seems to use the terms in a
art critic. He is blind.
common way, referring to things that are pleasing to the eye.
But maybe we should use Danto’s arguments against him.
He uses beauty in the sense of something being beautiful to
We can do this by referring to his discussion of another
look at, in the way one might say of a person that he or she
body of work in which he does address the tension between
is beautiful. Danto does claim at one point that ‘the meaning
feeling and form and comes closer to the kind of reading
of a work of art is an intellectual product, which is grasped
that he should have applied to Matisse and Modernism. I
through interpretation by someone other than the artist, and
am referring to his discussion of Robert Mapplethorpe in
the beauty of the work, if indeed it is beautiful, is seen as en-
Playing with the Edge (1996), where Danto explains how Map-
tailed by that meaning’ (o.c. 13). But this complicates matters
plethorpe could make beautiful art out of a source material
even further because it seems to suggest that even beauty
(extreme sexual behaviour) that many would call ugly or
in the aesthetic/perceptual sense is a product of first having
disgusting. For a long time, Mapplethorpe was mostly known
seen a meaning attached to the art object. However, Danto’s
for his rather tepid classicising nudes and formulaic flower
problem, and especially his problem with Matisse’s Blue Nude,
photographs. But as several critics, Danto among them, have
disappears once we adopt a Langerian view of beauty. If
pointed out, Mapplethorpe’s greatest artistic achievement
beauty is expressiveness, then it is indeed the ‘strength and
were his infamous sex pictures, the so-called X Portfolio and
power’ of the work that we call beautiful. This is not simply a
related images that caused the uproar over the Perfect Mo-
matter of semantics, expanding the term “beauty” to include
ment exhibition. Danto argues that Mapplethorpe’s sex photos
165
166
display an unflinchingly honesty, both in the sense that they
twentieth century. For instance, when discussing the triptych
do not hypocritically seek to soften their subject matter and
Jim and Tom, Sausalito (1977), which shows a man pissing in
in the sense that Mapplethorpe himself never tried to hide
another man’s mouth, Danto claims that ‘nothing in my ex-
his deep personal involvement with this subject. The sado-
perience or fantasy had prepared me for an image of that sort
masochists that appear in these images were friends of the
of act’ (o.c. 8). I wonder how any educated, worldly-wise in-
artist. Moreover, Mapplethorpe shared their sexuality and
tellectual of the 1990s could not have been aware of the fact
their fetishes and probably engaged in sexual rituals with
that some people like to engage in that kind of sexual play?
them on more than one occasion. So Mapplethorpe has cre-
For someone who has built his career on the work of Andy
ated these pictures as a kind of intimate record of a subcul-
Warhol, whose films and artwork very often address issues
ture to which he belonged. The fact that his photographs are
of sexual edge-play, not to mention pissing, Danto seems to
often very stylishly composed can cloud the fact that these
be striking a very coy pose here. But regardless of the undeni-
are intensely personal images. But Danto argues, persua-
able brutality of some of the images, such as those of a blood-
sively, that it is their stylisation that allows them to succeed
scattered penis trapped in what looks like a kind of mouse-
as art. For Danto, Mapplethorpe’s personal engagement with
trap, it was not Mapplethorpe’s primary intent to shock.
his subject sets him apart from other photographers, such as
Rather, as he himself liked to point out, he was “playing with
Diane Arbus. ‘With Arbus, one feels, over and over again, that
the edge”. For Danto, this means that Mapplethorpe’s work
she found ways of betraying the trust that permitted her to
was a balancing act between art and porn, an attempt ‘to
get the pictures we see. There is something vaguely exploit-
achieve “smut that is also art”’ (o.c. 76). To argue this point,
ative about her work’ (Danto 1996: 43). Mapplethorpe, on the
Danto uses Hegel’s concept of Aufhebung, which is a process
contrary, ‘was remorselessly sincere’ as an artist. ‘In a video
in which two radical opposites are brought together and
made for Spanish television, Sam Wagstaff [Mapplethorpe’s
lifted up on a higher plane, where they coexist in a new unity
benefactor, collector, and lover] said that Mapplethorpe was
that somehow neutralises their opposition. For Mappletho-
the most honest person he had ever known. This is borne out
rpe’s work, Aufhebung means two things. First, the subject
in the interviews. Mapplethorpe is unflinching. One cannot
matter of the photographs should be frankly acknowledged:
read very many of them without being struck by his absolute
it is a sometimes brutally explicit rendering of extreme sex-
candour. He never dodges a question. It is this honesty that
ual acts. But second, the images are composed in a way that
characterises the self-portraits as well. Even when he got
often makes them strangely beautiful. This is how Aufhebung
himself up as a devil or a girl, or a punk, it was in the interest
comes about in Mapplethorpe’s pictures. ‘There is the energy
of discovery and personal truth’ (o.c. 55).
of the displayed sex, and there is its containment, its absorp-
The sex pictures are sometimes disturbing, depending on
tion, into the work of art. It is preserved and negated at the
one’s naiveté about the sexual realities of life in the late
same moment’ (Danto 1996: 82).
167
But we need not make a detour trough Hegel to make this
(such as offal) in their art. But it does show that people who
point for the dynamic of Mapplethorpe’s sex pictures is a
claim that seemingly ugly works of art are beautiful are not
fine example of the coming together of feeling and form in
talking trough their hats.
Langer’s sense. Perusing Mapplethorpe’s sex pictures, one is
168
struck by the tension between form and content. This tension
Killing Art
is especially noticeable in the fact that the subjects of the pic-
When art strives towards the condition of philosophy it be-
tures always retain their humanity. Mapplethorpe makes the
comes conceptual art. According to Danto the path towards
trust between the men, and between them and him as a pho-
this transfiguration starts in the eighteenth century, with the
tographer, almost palpably present. The stylised features of
invention of the discipline of aesthetics as a way of keep-
these photographs do not seek to embellish what would oth-
ing art separate from what really matters in the shaping of
erwise be brutally shocking or “merely” pornographic; they
human life and society: politics. This is Danto’s objection
express the calm dedication and trust with which these men
to Kantian disinterestedness: just like Plato kept art at bay
explore the limits of their bodies and their sexuality. And it
because it was too distant from the real reality (of the realm
is in this sense, and not in the more superficial “aesthetic”
of Ideas) the element of disinterestedness assured that art
sense, that form fits feeling in these works. Obviously, Map-
would not get involved with the things that ‘normally move
plethorpe’s photographs exhibit a classical composition that
men and women – money, power, sex, love’ (PDA 9). So Danto
makes them eligible for “beauty” in the traditional “aesthetic”
reads disinterestedness in a political way, and an interesting
sense. But what makes them great art is not this composi-
political way in view of our earlier historical survey, which
tional feature, but the way feeling and form are welded to-
showed that bourgeois culture developed towards the au-
gether in their features. I would argue that this same welding
tonomy of art (its disinterestedness) with a concomitant in-
of feeling and form occurs in Matisse’s Blue Nude and in many
efficiency of art. Aesthetics thus becomes part, for Danto, of
other works of art that Danto would judge “unmistakably
something politically oppressive. That is probably why Danto
ugly (although great art)”. What we gain from this approach
somewhat sarcastically (and not quite correctly) describes
is not only a relevant increase of beautiful objects (things
Kantian disinterestedness as ‘a tepid gratification since un-
that are called ugly turn out not to be ugly at all) but also
connected with the satisfaction of real needs or the achieve-
increased insight in our own reasons for finding such objects
ment of real goals. So it is a kind of narcoleptic pleasure, the
beautiful (we now know that their welding of feeling and
pleasure which consists in the absence of pain’ (PDA 11).
form appeals to a sense of beauty that is more complex than
Danto next claims that this modern aesthetics has left ‘seri-
the traditional aesthetic one). This does not deny the fact that
ous artists to suppose it their task to make beauty’ (PDA 12),
there is indeed a lot of art that is (meant to be) manifestly
which seems to me wholly unpersuasive in view of both the
ugly, as when artists consciously use disgusting materials
political charge of Romanticism and Realism and the formal
169
170
investigations of the many kinds of Modernism, not to men-
have become indiscernibles: everyday objects with no signifi-
tion the provocations of the historical avant-garde; none of
cant aesthetic properties to mark their difference from other
which were concerned with anything so “parochial” as mak-
everyday objects. What turns them into art is the theory at-
ing beauty. Even Oscar Wilde’s aestheticism was considered
tached to them. And to top it all off, Danto obviously sees a
such a subversive affront to polite society that the man was
historical necessity in this late condition of art. ‘If something
brutally destroyed by genteel backwardness.
like this view has the remotest chance of being plausible, it
But we might save our dispute over Danto’s historical survey
is possible to suppose that art had come to an end. Of course,
for another occasion and look at what was the philosophical
there will go on to be art-making. But art-makers, living in
present for Danto when he was writing down these ideas in
what I like to call the post-historical period of art, will bring
The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art (1986). At that point
into existence works which lack the historical importance or
(which for Danto had begun in 1964) the central question had
meaning we have for a very long time come to expect. The
become ‘what should art be if it throws off the bondage to
historical stage of art is done with when it is known what art
prettiness?’ (PDA 13) We started our discussion with Danto’s
is and means. The artists have made the way open for phi-
claim about the end of art in the sense that art had become
losophy, and the moment has arrived at which the task must
essentially self-reflexive, and self-reflection now unsurpris-
be transferred finally into the hands of philosophers’ (ibid.).
ingly turns out to be exactly the sort of thing that art without
All of this may well make one wonder if art should really
prettiness should be: ‘if we look at the art of our recent past
continue to be made at all. If art is really about philosophy
in these terms, grandiose as they are, what we see is some-
and not about crafting expressive forms then why not simply
thing which depends more and more upon theory for its
do away with art schools and academies and recognise that
existence as art, so that theory is not something external to
philosophers, or people with an MA in philosophy, are the
a world it seeks to understand, so that in understanding its
real artists now? What could conceivably be taught at an art
object it has to understand itself. But there is another feature
school that is not already and better taught at the philosophy
exhibited by these late productions which is that the objects
departments of universities? By the same token we might
approach zero as their theory approaches infinity, so that
now suggest that all philosophers are really simply artists
virtually all there is at the end is theory, art having finally
and that they have failed to understand their own identity in
become vaporised in a dazzle of pure thought about itself,
thinking themselves to be only philosophers (as distinct from
and remaining, as it were, solely as the object of its own theo-
artists). In any case, the suggestion that art is now philoso-
retical consciousness’ (PDA 111). Behold, then, o reader, the
phy is both elucidating and problematic for several reasons.
birth of conceptual art from the mind of the Hegelian theorist
First, it offers us a clue to the lamentable state of art itself in
as the Great Transfigurator of the Commonplace Object. Ap-
the wake of the big turn towards the conceptual. In the 1970s
proaching zero in the arts simply means that works of art
art schools all but acted upon the suggestion to do away
171
172
with themselves in the sense that many academies simply
ience of matter. But most of all, it will give him something to
stopped training their students in elementary draughtsman-
revolt against. The idea of artists who cannot and were never
ship and painting because such skills had become outmoded
taught to draw rejecting or revolting against the idea of draw-
and had been superseded by the conceptual and the mini-
ing is preposterous: it is mere posturing because there is no
malist modes. In lieu of academic technique students got
true knowledge of what one is rebelling against. The attitude
Theory. In Unnatural Wonders (2005) Danto has described this
is simply facile, if only because it insults other artists who did
evolution: ‘The institutions of the art world began to change
submit to the discipline of the hand and emerged with mean-
radically in response to the radical pluralism that overtook
ingful art. It also overlooks the fact that many of the artists
it in what I spoke of in the “posthistorical” period we had
who lead the way towards the Post-Historical era, including
entered. In art schools, for example, skills were no longer
Warhol, were accomplished craftsmen in their chosen art
taught. The student was treated from the beginning as an
who could draw and paint well and whose swerve away from
artist, and the faculty existed to help the students realise
the classical approaches to the visual arts was motivated by
their ideas. The attitude was that the student would learn
a sincere search for new ways of expression. But the dam-
whatever he or she needed in order to make what he or she
age was done and few seemed to care. In fact, young artists
wanted. Everyone used everything and anything – audio, vid-
(or rather: young people who for many reasons believed they
eo, photography, performance, installation. Students could be
were, could, or should be artists) were now being tutored in
painters or sculptors if they liked, but the main thing was to
the resentment of skill by artists who no longer mastered or
find the means to embody the meanings they were interested
cared about those skills. Today, many instructors are very bad
in conveying’ (Danto 2005b: xiv-xv).
craftsmen themselves. They are ill-placed to teach younger
You see the folly of this approach: an artist, let alone a young
artists their craft. The damage done in one generation will
student, cannot suddenly decide to sojourn for a while in a
take several generations to undo as artists who are interested
new branch of the arts for which he or she neither has train-
in skill will have to find out on their own what had previously
ing nor talent or inclination. There is a difference between a
been transmitted from master to student for centuries. The
pluralist and a lacklustre approach to art, and what we were
scandal of art education in the so-called pluralist era shows
getting here was definitely not any kind of focused art-mak-
how easy it is to destroy a tradition. The results of this hor-
ing. To check in on what’s happening and help students em-
ribly misguided evolution are everywhere on display in the
body their ideas du jour hardly amounts to what I would call
dismal art that has poured forth since the 1970s: mediocre (or
an education. To begin with, it is at odds with the very psy-
worse) painting where the artist’s inability to master form is
chology of education: even if one disapproves of a classical
sold as a conscious rejection, a revolt, a highly moral gesture,
training in the arts, at least it will hone a budding artist’s skill
or what you will. Ineptitude was now being paraded around
and perseverance, it will teach him patience and the resil-
as expressiveness. But in order to deconstruct a technique
173
174
you have to know it from the inside. Artists like Picasso had
make good films if one has (developed) the cinematic sensi-
earned the moral right to subvert form because they had
bility that this requires. Some of the great masters of modern
submitted to its discipline and knew exactly what they were
cinema, such as Pasolini or Derek Jarman, came to the film
doing when they distorted shapes in their work. In fact, their
without one iota of technical know-how, for which they relied
distortions often testify to superior craftsmanship where
on trained technicians. But they had vision and were able to
most of the latter-day work is not even convincing as distor-
translate that vision to the screen. Obviously, an artist should
tion to begin with.
carefully consider in which medium he or she wants to work.
Obviously, I applaud the artist’s freedom to tackle any me-
Nobody is forced to draw or paint, but if you insist on doing
dium in the pluralist era and nobody would want to condemn
so, you had better learn something about the skills you are
the contemporary artist to so pedestrian a practice as to draw
addressing. It is all very well to speak of expressiveness to
accurately from life (God forbid!). But it would be nice if an
cover up your inability, and no doubt you will find some critic
artist could consider, before venturing into any new medium,
willing to rave about your expressiveness, but the discerning
whether he or she has any inclination or gift for that particu-
eye of the true art-lover can often tell at a glance whether a
lar branch of the Muse. I do not think I am asking for much.
painting is a deliberate distortion by a gifted hand or a mere
In fact, I am asking for very little for I do not even believe
symptom of ineptitude. Again, to distort form you must first
one needs to have any particular technical knowledge of cer-
master it. For the same reason, being a dyslectic will not help
tain media to create superior work in them. Surely, to draw
you write the next Finnegans Wake. It takes intimate knowl-
or paint one needs to master some technique. But consider
edge of how language works in order to subvert it in a mean-
experimental film-making. In the 1960s first 16mm and then
ingful way. It takes much deliberation and a firm purpose of
8mm equipment became affordable for the average person,
gesture to do anything well in the arts. In the final reckoning,
allowing literally anyone to become a filmmaker. And for a
it even takes a lot of very good thought to produce a convinc-
brief time it seemed that everyone actually did. But the great
ing work of conceptual art, although we should consider very
masters who finally emerged as the leaders of the move-
carefully whether a thought and nothing but a thought (ad-
ment, such as Warhol, Brakhage, and Markopoulos, were not
mittedly with a commonplace object attached to it) is a work
necessarily the greatest technicians. In fact, filming equip-
of art at all or mere pedantry.
ment became so user-friendly that sometimes all you had to
All of this leaves us with the obvious question of what con-
do was literally aim the camera and press a button to record,
ceptual art is, whether it is art at all and when, if it is, it
as Warhol did. These days, with digital video technology, we
should be considered good art. In view of our severe criticism
are witnessing a similar revival. But despite the enormous
of the conceptual mode of artistic interpretation, I feel an
simplicity of the technology, very few filmmakers achieved
answer to these questions is certainly not too much to ask.
great works for the very simple reason that one can only
And my answer is brief. I suggest we agree that conceptual
175
176
art is not art at all. Since interpretations do not add anything
Avant-Garde After the End of Avant-Garde
aesthetic to a commonplace object, or at least nothing in an
A second problem with art as philosophy has to do with
interesting sense of aesthetic (which would be the first two of
the philosophy itself and leads us straight into the complex
the possible three listed before), and since all this talk about
problem of the avant-garde after the end of the avant-garde.
transfiguration through interpretation is very much rhetori-
If conceptual art, and Post-Historical art in general, ap-
cal because no transformative fusion of object and interpre-
proaches zero it also becomes more and more cerebral. This
tation ever takes place (in opposition, for example, to the way
trend found a parallel movement in the world of philosophy,
forms, colours, and canvas are fused to create a painting that,
where postmodern Theory became all the rage in the 1960s.
as a prime symbol, is more than the sum of those constituent
Gradually, several kinds of structuralist and post-structuralist
parts), conceptual art really offers us two things: a piece of
French philosophy became the leading school of thought.
philosophy or theory on the one hand, and on the other hand
This kind of postmodern philosophy is so idiosyncratic that
an object that is supposed to convince us of the artistic and
it is often simply called “theory” instead of philosophy and
creative nature of the person ushering it in. I do not dispute
I shall continue to refer to it as “Theory,” capitalised to refer
that conceptual art has often raised very interesting issues,
to its status as a kind of movement. To understand the sud-
even issues of the greatest importance. But an issue is not a
den rise of this very cerebral branch of philosophy we must
work of art and a commonplace object is not turned into art
understand the dire straits the humanities found themselves
because it comes, reportedly, with an issue attached to it. If
in in the late 1960s. It was a crisis that is still not over today
the issues raised by conceptual art are interesting and rel-
and that revolved around the justification of the humanities.
evant, they are interesting philosophy. But philosophy is not
In a world obsessed with economy, growth, progress, and
art, unless it happens to be expressed in a book or an essay
productivity it is very difficult to argue for the legitimacy of
that displays remarkable literary qualities (for the essay, we
the humanities, which seem to be going nowhere and usu-
should remember, is a literary genre and hence belongs in the
ally produce nothing remotely marketable. They tend to be as
realm of art). All the conceptual object serves is the supposed
useless as the arts they study. The advent of Theory suddenly
artist’s ego. Conceptual art now offers even the person void of
allowed professors and critics in the humanities to pretend
any talent except a talent for sophistry to present herself as
they were involved in something scientific and progressive.
an artist. “Conceptual artist” is the chosen profession for any
The jargon involved in Theory created and arcane aura of
art-hack who would like to have his cookie and eat it: to have
cutting edge concepts that were constantly yielding new in-
an opinion about art is now a work of art in itself. What bet-
sights into power, social structures, sexuality, or what not. It
ter way to boost your ego and create an inflated sense of your
suddenly appeared that the humanities might yield knowl-
own importance?
edge as verifiable and quantifiable as the knowledge generated by physics and biology. And the jargon involved certainly
177
178
sounded as if this new Theory was just as state of the art and
umbrella of male authority and one-man rule: the French big-
just as fine-tuned as the theories that were used in physics.
wigs offered to their disciples a soothing esoteric code and a
For such reasons the appeal of postmodern Theory was very
sense of belonging to an elite, an intellectually superior unit,
strong. Suddenly people in the humanities started practising
at a time when the market told academics they were useless
all manner of “deconstruction” if they happened to be follow-
and dispensable’ (Paglia 1992: 220). In an Open Letter to the
ers of Derrida while those in thrall with Foucault decided en
students of Harvard, published in the February 17, 1994 issue
masse that they should apply themselves to sex, or sexuality,
of the Harvard Crimson, Paglia added that ‘the bottom fell out
and set about hunting for phalluses and androcentrism in
of the Harvard literature departments in the Seventies. They
works of art previously innocent of any kind of political in-
had failed to find new blood to continue Harvard’s reputa-
correctness.
tion into the next generation [...]. The English department
The results of all this activity were often disastrous because
nearly went into receivership. [...]. Desperate, the Harvard
the people who ventured into these new areas were not very
administration went on a fast shopping expedition and filled
well-prepared to deal with the issues at hand. To begin with,
the faculty with the current hot property, theorists, many of
their knowledge of philosophy was usually too limited to see
them women, as an affirmative action sop. Now you’re stuck
the philosophical tradition that had shaped the postmodern
with them. [...] Harvard, which sacrificed scholarly standards
mode. For example, there is little point in discussing decen-
for expedience, has condemned itself to at least two genera-
tredness without having a clue that decentredness was not a
tions of mediocrity in the humanities, since these people are
new invention by Lacan but something that had already been
certain to hire only those who will prop up their decaying
analysed very well by the Romantics, especially Friedrich
reputations’ (Paglia 1995: 119-120).
Schlegel, Novalis, Hölderlin, and the much-neglected Lud-
But even among the critics who did manage to get things
wig Tieck (see Chapter One). Furthermore, much of Lacan’s
right there arose a problem. This problem is linked to the pro-
theories of language had already been formulated in the
fessionalisation of the arts. We have recently witnessed the
dialectics and hermeneutics of Friedrich Schleiermacher. But
introduction of PhD programmes in the arts. This innovation
academics were simply blinded by the wordplay of the French
was sold as an initiative beneficial to artists when it was in
philosophes and the mileage their careers could get from quot-
fact only beneficial to a specific group of artists: those whose
ing them. Referring specifically to the situation at American
work had close links with the kind of Theory that emerged
universities, Camille Paglia writes that ‘the collapse of the job
in the Post-Historical era. If art is about philosophy, and phi-
market, due to recession and university retrenchment after
losophy is about Theory, it is not difficult to guess what kind
the baby-boom era, caused economic hysteria. As faculties
of art would now become the very image of PhD-worthy art.
were cut, commercial self-packaging became a priority. Aca-
It is clear that the PhD in the arts entails the very grave risk
demics, never renowned for courage, fled beneath the safe
of splitting the already rivalry-ridden art community even
179
180
further into the haves and the have-nots. If sufficient artists
uses the PhD as a tool to hold the profession in what William
attain a PhD to make this a substantial group within the art
James has compared, in an indictment of the PhD system
community a difference is bound to arise sooner or later be-
written in 1903, with the stranglehold of an octopus (James
tween those who did get it and those who didn’t, with those
1987: 1111-1118). I think that the PhD in the arts serves at
who did enjoying greater stature because they are obviously
least three highly interconnected purposes in the artworld,
the more clever ones and therefore the more profound or bet-
where it is used as a strategic device in the struggle for power
ter artists. Obviously, art is never that easy. But markets usu-
(in the kondylian sense). By giving art the aura of scientific
ally are. And the sad thing about art is that really good art has
legitimacy the PhD in the arts shows administrators and
really nothing in common with a real art market: their aims
politicians that art is not simply about subjective expression
and methods are completely at odds. Advocates of the PhD
but about something analysable, something positive, tangible,
in the arts usually speak of art as a form of research, which
and somehow measurable; or at least measurable in the
sounds innocent enough because art obviously does entail a
sense that a committee of “experts� is able to discriminate
kind of research, as we saw in our discussion of David Hock-
between art that is worthy of a PhD-label and art that regret-
ney. Unfortunately, artistic research has little in common
tably is not. But in the careerist world of academe and the
with the kind of research involved in science, even in the
greedy world of the art market one scores no points for try-
humanities, and is first and foremost an inner exploration,
ing, so not winning the PhD race means something like losing
a process of thought and reflection, and finally an attempt
the art race: you become something like what Katlijne Van
to shape matter (paint, wood, words, clay, sound) into an
der Stighelen, one of my teachers at Louvain University, liked
expressive form. This is research all right, but only in a very
to call the zweite Garnitur: the secondary artists whose names
specific and non-objective sense. After all, we saw that a work
are known only to specialists and not to the general public.
of art is one indivisible symbol that cannot be analysed into
These artists are the filler of history because their work,
its constituent parts. This should make us suspicious of any
while often popular in their own time, is second-rate. In this
kind of programme that looks at art from what is basically a
sense, the PhD in the arts signals the icing on the cake of the
discursive point of view: art as PhD-oriented research means
yuppification of the arts that started with the surge of the art
that the process of creation can be tracked and analysed,
market in the 1980s: sooner or later it will become a career-
resulting in a manual or PhD thesis to accompany whatever
making or -breaking certificate that determines whether your
work is presented as a PhD project.
art will sink or swim, or, more importantly, sell or not. The
I would suggest that the introduction of the PhD in the arts is
second purpose served by the PhD in the arts is a direct con-
mainly a very clever marketing tool in artworld politics that
sequence of the first. Since the PhD-programme is a direct
has been created for the benefit of a group or school of critics
consequence of the Post-Historical condition of art in its nar-
and artists with high stakes in the marketplace. This group
row sense of conceptual art (art striving to the condition of
181
182
philosophy), it creates a false sense of progressiveness in the
artists-as-researchers mutually sustain each other’s reputa-
arts and in the humanities. Researchers, artists-as-research-
tions. Obviously, such mechanisms have always been at work
ers, and critics are now explorers of new frontiers of thought
in the artworld. The finest and probably most tragic example
where no man hath thought before, making ever new prog-
is without doubt the huge influence of Clement Greenberg in
ress into the vast and as yet unclaimed fields of theoretical
the 1950s and his slow withdrawal into total silence as the
insight. The history of art-as-research is then portrayed as
1960s progressed and the Bright Young Things of the Concep-
an epic history of artistic exploration, phrased in Theory. It is
tual Era took over. What is different from the past, however, is
very easy to see how this can lead to a renewed sense of the
that the very people who maintain a power elite in the art-
avant-garde: there is now a small elite of insiders, Those Who
world are also the people who are constantly babbling about
Know And Speak Theory, who are at the vanguard of art and
multiculturalism, diversity, and open discourse, which are
philosophy, urging history on even after its much-publicised
reportedly central concerns in their high-minded theoreti-
and even more elaborately theorised demise. Those of us who
cal endeavours. But these are false claims to diversity. What
do not think or write Theory are the poor sods who missed
these careerist theorists have really done is create theoretical
the gravy-train of history, the silly naifs who still cling to an
enclaves that effectively bar many dissident voices from be-
outdated belief in form, matter, or aesthetics. We are the dull
ing heard or included in the debate. In many circles a critic,
duds, whereas the international magnates of Theory are the
artist, or hanger-on is only allowed to join the party if he or
shining sophisticates.
she either speaks theoretical newspeak or is willing to wor-
The third purpose of the PhD in the arts is again a function of
ship at the feet of those who do. Gullibility and sycophantism
the previous two, for the dynamics of false progressiveness
seem to be the prime characteristics of The Person Sure To
and neo-avant-garde sensibilities allows collectors, curators,
Rise Fast In The Cultural Realm. The system of Theory in-
and critics (what Danto calls the three C’s of the artworld) to
cludes a network of academics, curators, journal editors, and
determine just where the really hot stuff is happening. Here
critics who have created a power zone that determines who’s
another layer of insidious insiderness is added to the game,
in and who’s not.
for many of the curators and critics involved are themselves
Finally, it is worth pointing out that the problems with the
the product of an academic education drenched in Theory.
PhD in the arts are similar to the problems we found in
So they have a lot at stake: their intellectual credibility de-
Danto’s idea of embodied meanings. We said earlier that the
pends on the continuing reign of Theory as the One True
meanings attached to a commonplace object do not become
Form of Criticism. Writing about cerebral art allows these
embodied in it by fiat; which is to say that if you claim that
critics to flex their theoretical muscles, display their astute-
certain meanings are embodied in an object, they should be
ness in selecting the Art That Matters, and hence forward
there for our perception and we should be able to see those
their upwardly mobile careers. This way, critics, theorists, and
meanings inscribed into the object itself. Similarly, if a PhD in
183
184
the arts results in an object (or a performance or whatever)
called street art. Obviously, street art is not entirely new. Its
with an accompanying explanatory thesis, I feel we should
inclusion in the world of high art started with the inflated
say that it has failed as art. If the art object (or performance
reputations of Jean-Michel Basquiat and Keith Haring in the
or whatever) requires a text on the side to explain its mean-
1980s. But since the turn of the millennium the artworld has
ings, then the art work in itself lacks expressive force. It
been especially receptive to street art, street photography and
needs crutches to tell us what it is about. So what you get, is
similar forms of artistic expression that have emerged from
bad art with a theoretical statement attached to it. Neither
youth cultures. The exhibition and catalogue Beautiful Losers
the work nor the text are successful art or philosophy on
(2004) were something of a watershed in this development,
their own. What has been achieved is not a PhD in the arts
but arguably the critical success of Larry Clark’s film Kids
but, at best, a PhD in philosophy of the arts, in theory, in so-
(1995) was equally a tell-tale sign that there was a growing
ciology, or whatever, but with an object attached. The PhD in
awareness within the broader artworld of what was happen-
the arts is only justified if the research is expressed and com-
ing in the street. If we look, ever so briefly, at the precedents
municated in the work itself. Recalling David Hockney’s re-
for this development, it could be argued that the tradition of
search into our perception of space, it is clear that his works
street photography harks back to the 1960s and 1970s, when
do not need texts to explain them (although good criticism
photographers like Lee Friedlander, Danny Lyons, and espe-
can often be illuminating, good art should not depend on
cially Dian Arbus took to the streets to photograph the grim
it). The research and its findings are there in the works if you
realities of everyday life. This eased the way for Larry Clark,
only know how to look. Similarly, Matisse once said that if you
whose seminal book Tulsa (1971) collected photographs of his
want to be a painter, ‘then begin by cutting off your tongue.
friends on the fringes of society. Clark in turn proved a huge
Henceforth, your expression will be left to your brushes’
influence on a generation of photographers who emerged at
(Parry 2004: 4). This brings us full circle back to Langer, whose
the end of the 1970s. Nan Goldin is the most remarkable pho-
concept of living form is of course the very definition of em-
tographer of this generation. Her work, which we shall dis-
bodiment of meaning in a work of art. In Hockney’s work, as
cuss in more detail in Chapter Five, is decidedly narrative in
in all good art, the meanings he expresses are truly embodied
tone, often autobiographical, draws on human sexuality and
because his meanings, and his research, are there for us to
emotions, and casts a critical eye upon society through its fo-
see. They shape the very works that express them.
cus on the lives of society’s rejects and minorities (transvestites, drug addicts, people with aids). Goldin’s signature work
Radical Chic for Chic Radicals
was The Ballad of Sexual Dependency (1982), a feature-length
But the new sense of avant-gardism is not only apparent in
narrative slide presentation of her photographs which was
the use of Theory. I believe it is equally at work in the way
influenced by the work of the underground filmmaker Jack
the artworld has dealt with a relatively recent phenomenon
Smith who, through lack of funding, had largely abandoned
185
186
film-making at the beginning of the 1970s and turned to cre-
the screenplay for Clark’s film Kids before turning to directing
ating outrageous slide presentations with exotic imagery that
himself.
often featured, beside himself and several underground per-
Several trends within the artworld helped to smoothen the
sonalities, a toy penguin.
way for street art into the gallery. To see this we must again
The critical success of Goldin and Clark paved the way for
return to the 1980s and the emergence of issue-based and
another generation of street photographers. Ari Marcopoulos,
identity art. This was a highly politicised form of art in which
for instance, originally heralded from the Netherlands and
victimhood and identity often took precedence over aesthetic
worked for a while as an assistant to Warhol before produc-
issues. Certain artists such as David Wojnarowicz, whose
ing his own body of work for which he often gets inside spe-
writing is especially persuasive, managed to transcend the
cific subcultures such as the world of skaters or snowboard-
merely political and personal claims of this movement, but
ers. In Transitions and Exits (2000), his book on snowboard
much of the work created within its framework was of dis-
culture, Marcopoulos explains that he sees his work as a form
mal quality. The work of such luminaries as Judy Chicago,
of artistic anthropology, ‘investigating who these people were,
Karen Finley, and Barbara Kruger has dated badly and seems
how they were connected to each other, what their rituals
to have lost much of its relevance with the passing of the
were, how they constituted themselves’. Probably the most
time-bound political issues it addressed. This is indeed a sign
gifted photographer of this new generation is Ed Templeton, a
of bad art, because there is no intrinsic reason why politi-
former skateboard champion whose reputation as an athlete
cal art could not also be good or great art (let us not forget,
has secured his privileged access to this particular subcul-
for example, that Michelangelo’s David was also a work of
ture. But Templeton also documents his personal life and
propaganda art, a warning against the Medici tyrants who
often presents very intimate imagery of his wife and himself.
had been expelled from Florence; Hibbard 1992: 58). Whether
Templeton has also produced a considerable body of work as
political and issue-based art will prove enduring depends on
a painter, but this is considerably less accomplished than his
whether it will be art first or political first. A second influence
work in photography. The Beautiful Losers exhibition of 2004
within the artworld was the explosion of the art-market in
brought together the work of Templeton with that of many
the wake of Reaganomics. In the 1980s prices for often me-
of his contemporaries, including Mark Gonzalez, Harmony
diocre contemporary art soared beyond belief, leading to the
Korine, Cheryl Dunn, Spike Jonze, Margaret Kilgallen, Ryan
inevitable burst of the bubble by the end of the decade. Since
McGinley, Mike Mills, Terry Richardson, and many others.
then the situation has hardly changed, as Saatchi’s pushing
Several of these artists, notably Jonze and Richardson, have
of the YBA’s (Young British Artists) clearly showed: if an art-
since acquired considerable fame and artistic reputations. It
ist’s reputation can be made or unmade by the buy-and-sell
is interesting to note that Larry Clark has actively sought to
policies of an influential collector (who might not even be an
engage this new generation. In fact, Harmony Korine wrote
actual connoisseur of art, but simply an entrepreneur) then
187
188
there is nothing left to distinguish the artworld from the free
always been rejected by the dominant culture, including the
market at large.
artistic establishment. But they erroneously infer from this
In fact, capitalist logic now controls the art-market. Markets
that what is misunderstood by the mainstream cultural press
are in constant need of input of fresh faces, fresh work, fresh
must necessarily be the next great avant-garde. But some-
reputations, and the next hot thing. Every new season and
times art is overlooked or dismissed because it just isn’t good
every new opening is supposed to bring us new revelations
enough. It is true that much and perhaps even most great
and revolutions. In this sense, the artworld has come to re-
modern art was initially rejected, sometimes even for years
semble the porn industry, where careers are brief and new
and decades on end, but that obviously does not imply that
faces appear with deadening regularity. The artworld is now
to be neglected is to be great by definition.
constantly on the lookout for the next big thing, living from
Much of the art that is reproduced in the Beautiful Losers
hype to hype. This explains the hugely inflated reputations
catalogue is not very sophisticated. And I do not mean so-
of such middling talents as Haring, Basquiat, or Jeff Koons.
phisticated on a theoretical or conceptual level, but simply
Interestingly, Koons once claimed that his then-wife, Ilona
on a stylistic or even painterly level. It often looks bland and
Staller, better known as the Italian porn star La Cicciolina, ‘is
sometimes even amateurish. One gets the impression that
one of the greatest artists in the world. She is a great com-
the basic artistic and iconographical language that underlies
municator, a great liberator. Other artists use a paintbrush.
such street art has not notably developed since the time of
Ilona uses her genitalia’ (Muthesius 1992: 142). Koons did not
Haring and Basquiat. There is a reason for this. Street art
half know how right he was, for La Cicciolina’s work in erotic
works within specific codes and has a very distinctive aes-
cinema is probably much more interesting than anything
thetic. It ranges from skateboard and surf design through
Koons ever did. In any case, since the 1980s high-profile art-
graffiti art and tagging. I think this suggests that we are deal-
ists have often presented themselves as entrepreneurs and
ing here with a form of folk art, a subcultural phenomenon
careerists, working for the market rather than working from
that is comparable to biker culture, surf culture, and maybe
necessity or compulsion. Today there are artists who do not
even sports culture and the iconography that it inspires. Per-
work if they do not get paid. But the fear of missing the next
haps an exhibition of such work, which is very valuable in
big thing also informs the Beautiful Losers catalogue, and this
itself, would be more honestly at home in an institution such
is especially revealing of the way the artworld operates today.
as the Smithsonian than in a museum for contemporary art.
In an instructive piece of artworld marketing strategy, the
There is still a difference between design, folk art, and what
authors of the catalogue compare the neglect that street art
we might call, for better or for worse, high art or fine art. In
had previously suffered to the neglect the artworld initially
this sense it is very telling that Ed Templeton has kept his ac-
lavished upon such important movements as the Beat poets
tivities as a designer of skateboards strictly separate from his
and Pop Art. The authors point out that the avant-garde has
work as a visual artist. The design shop is a job, the photogra-
189
190
phy and the painting are his art. Similarly, graffiti has proved
ence life on the fringe is possibly a reason why explicit sexual
to be a highly intelligent and subversive means of expression,
photography such as that of Larry Clark has become so popu-
especially in the hands of gifted artists such as Banksy. But
lar: it feeds a voyeuristic need to boldly go and see where no
we must ask ourselves if we are really doing these artists a
proper artworld person has ever gone or seen before. Similar-
favour by bringing them into museums for contemporary
ly, the wave of porn chic we have seen in the artworld is clad
art. Does this not undermine the purpose of their work? This
in the same hypocritical garb. The curators who set up porn
kind of work has been described as non-commissioned pub-
in their galleries or who commission artists to produce tepid
lic art (a great euphemism to describe the fact that graffiti
pieces for portmanteau film projects such as Destricted would
is often simply illegal from the point of view of the powers
probably not be caught dead in an actual sex shop or perus-
that be), and this shows that much of it is intimately linked
ing the adult section of their local video store. Yes, we want
to contemporary forms of activism, such as the Reclaim The
images of whores and call-boys in our gallery, but would you
Streets manifestations that seek to oppose oppressive domi-
sit down with them for dinner? Would you go out into the
nant culture. But to treat such subversive work as high art is
streets at night and spend an hour with them on a bench,
often to aestheticise and hence defuse it.
discussing the hardships of life on the street? I don’t think
However, the political charge of much street art is possibly
so. All of this is not a criticism of the art involved. As with all
the reason why the artworld is so eager to bring it into its
art, there is a lot of very bad street art, a considerable amount
museums. This has everything to do with radical chic. Since
of good street art, and some of it will no doubt turn out to be
the avant-garde is officially dead, it has become difficult for
great. What I am critical of is the way the artworld deals with
artists and art institutions to prove their edge merely on the
this kind of art. There is a lingering feeling that the easy ac-
basis of aesthetic or formal properties. So the edge must be
ceptance of street art in the artworld has less to do with the
sought elsewhere. To flaunt street art in one’s gallery or mu-
artistic merits of the work itself than with the desire of the
seum is to bask in the light of the streetwise. It is to dress
artworld to maintain a sense of the avant-garde after the end
oneself up in an air of hipness. It is to live the life of the
of avant-garde.
street vicariously. The new avant-garde is an avant-garde of radical chic and lifestyle. You prove how open-minded and radical you are by embracing the marginal, the transsexual, the criminal, the radical. If art itself has become obsolete, attitude is everything. No matter that the artist cannot paint, he is a drug fiend and this makes him cool. And we, showing his work, share in his coolness. It is the facade of daring, it is playing at being radical. This desire to vicariously experi-
191
Chapter Three
was purchased, which died within two days and again had to be replaced. In this bizarre anecdote of an artist braving ridiculously unnecessary dangers, not to mention sacrific-
GETTING
ing the life of several innocent goats, for the sake of painting
PHYSICALS
and even braved death for their art. Some actors, for ex-
a picture, we sense something of the dedication that artists often feel towards their work. Artists have starved, fought, ample, submit their bodies to terrific alterations for the sake of a part. For American Psycho (Mary Harron, 2000) Christian Bale honed his flesh to what a skilled observer of the male
192
While sojourning in the Holy Land in 1854 William Holman
physique has called an ‘exquisitely cut-glass body’ (Reuter
Hunt painted one of the nineteenth century’s most fasci-
2000: 140), only to starve its skeletal remains for the haunt-
nating paintings: The Scapegoat (1855). The picture shows a
ing The Machinist (Brad Anderson, 2004). But the artist who
vicious-looking goat on the desolate shores of the Dead Sea.
most clearly puts his body in jeopardy today is undoubtedly
It is based on an image found in Leviticus, where, as Hunt
the performance artist or body artist, who will often put his
wrote to his friend John Everett Millais, ‘you will read an ac-
physical well-being on the line for the sake of art.
count of the scapegoat sent into the wilderness, bearing all the sins of the children of Israel, which, of course, was insti-
A Body of Art
tuted as a type of Christ’ (Amor 1989: 125). Hunt had bought
Performance art is difficult to define. It seems to be so wide
a white goat to serve as his model for the painting. Led by
a concept, and so often draws on materials and techniques
a group of Arabs, Hunt set out into the wilderness, braving
that are usually considered kinds of art in themselves (such
desolation and the lurking presence of armed brigands (not
as video, painting, film, theatre, poetry, and many others)
to mention the artist at one point sinking into a pit of slime
that it cannot be defined. In fact, if we consult surveys of
and nearly perishing), until he found a suitable spot on the
performance art or of the related topic of body art, such
shores of the Dead Sea that proved a suitable scene for the
books rarely offer insight into what is the specific nature of
picture. Every morning, Hunt would venture out to the shores
performance art. In a classic survey, RoseLee Goldberg claims
of the ‘pestilential lake’ (o.c. 128), set up his easel and paint
that ‘by its very nature, performance art defies precise or easy
while the armed enemy looming in the hills stared at him in
definition beyond the simple declaration that it is live art by
baffled amazement. In the end, the Arab soldiers accompany-
artists’ (Goldberg 2001: 9). In the introduction to her book she
ing him wanted to return and Hunt had to finish the painting
suggests that ‘tribal ritual, medieval passion play, Renais-
in Jerusalem, by which time the goat had died and a new one
sance spectacle or the “soirées” arranged by artists in the
193
194
1920s in their Paris studios’ are all examples of performance
performance art; and he is certainly not the only critic to do
art (o.c. 8). But Goldberg’s description is too general and
so. But there is really a marked difference between the two.
wildly inaccurate, for I would claim that the medieval pas-
In the case of Oppenheim’s piece, for instance, one should
sion play is an example of the theatre and that a tribal ritual
wonder how two photographs could constitute a performance.
is not even art at all but, as is clear from the description, an
They document the results of an action on Oppenheim’s part
example of ritual. It would seem that with performance art
that may or may not have been a performance depending on
things are very much as they are with pornography: we all
whether the exposure to sunburn was in itself a public event
know what it is, especially when we see it, but don’t ask us
(a performance) or something Oppenheim engaged in in pri-
to define it. Such an approach, however, will not do. We can-
vate for the sole purpose of creating the photographs, which
not engage in any kind of profitable discussion of anything if
are then the actual works of art (getting sunburnt would then
we do not have clearly defined terms. So we will have to en-
be the preparation for the creation of the work, much like
deavour to find a more satisfying description of what makes
a painter buying tubes of paint, grinding pigment to make
performance art a specific form of art that is distinct from
paint, or preparing a canvas). In the latter case, Reading Posi-
the other arts. Since performance art was still in its infancy
tion would be a work of photographic art, not performance
when Langer wrote Feeling and Form that book does not offer
art, and should be judged as such. So Lucie-Smith’s descrip-
a discussion of the primary illusion created in performance.
tion is a muddle, but not an uncommon one in writing on
Our first task should therefore be to try and define this pri-
body and performance art.
mary illusion so that we may understand what happens in a
In her classic 1974 essay on body art Lea Vergine offers an
performance. Once we have insight in the primary illusion of
interesting clue towards the distinction between body art and
performance art we will also be able to argue why some kinds
performance art. She observes that in body art the body ‘is
of performance art are successful and others not.
being used as an art language’ (Vergine 2000: 7). Body art is
First, we shall have to distinguish between body art and
art in which the body is crucially and actually involved: the
performance art. The two are often discussed together, and
body itself becomes an art language. Body art happens to or
both categories do seem to flow naturally into each other.
with the body or intrinsically concerns the body. It has the
Consider Edward Lucie-Smith’s comment on Dennis Op-
body physical as its locus of expression: what is relevant in
penheim’s Reading Position (1970), a work that ‘consists of
such art is expressed through or impressed upon the body.
two photographs which record the effects of sunburn on the
As Tracey Warr has noted, in body art the body is ‘used not
artist’s own torso – part of it sheltered by an open book, and
simply as the “content” of the work, but also as canvas, brush,
part left exposed. This kind of expression is often classified as
frame and platform’ (Warr 2000: 11). In The Artist’s Body (2000)
body art or performance art’ (Lucie-Smith 2001: 159). Lucie-
Amelia Jones offers an overview of body art that considers
Smith clearly suggests an equivalence between body art and
‘the histrionically virile action painting body’ of Jackson Pol-
195
196
lock a crucial point of reference for body art (Jones 2000: 21,
achieve a performance in a way similar to the agency of the
23). After action painting the history of body art is taken to
body in achieving a painting: the body is, so to speak, the tool
include the ‘strategic banality’ (o.c. 26) of everyday gestures
required to create the actual work of art. For instance, when
used in the dance of Merce Cunningham or the Judson Dance
Dutch artist Wim T. Schippers emptied a bottle of lemonade
Theater; a 1962 Happening in which ‘Wolf Vostell instructed
into the ocean he was clearly performing a performance.
the audience to board a city bus, ride around Paris and take
But this performance was not body art: the artist’s body was
note of their aural and visual experiences’ (o.c. 28); Laurie
not intrinsically relevant to the proceedings, except as the
Anderson’s ‘large scale theatrical productions performed at
necessary agent for emptying the bottle of lemonade. The
large-capacity venues’ (o.c. 32); Yves Klein’s Anthropometries;
performance was not about the body physical but about an
the mechanical body extensions of Stelarc; the photographs
action undertaken by the artist as a person. The locus of sig-
of Cindy Sherman; Piero Manzoni’s canned Merda d’artista
nificance in this performance was not the body physical but
(1961); Duchamp’s masquerading as Rrose Sélavy; Niki de
the action itself. So a work can be performance art regardless
Saint-Phalle’s ‘bleeding’ Tir à Volonté-paintings; Warhol’s ‘piss’
of whether it is also body art. What seems to be crucial to
or Oxidation Paintings (1978); Marcel Duchamp’s small Paysage
performance art is the spectacle of action. Performance art
fautif (1946) which was in 1989 revealed to consist of semen
would then be a work of art in which taking action is itself
on black satin; the work of the Viennese Actionists; and even
presented as the work of art. In this sense it is related to Han-
‘the antics of the Spice Girls’ (o.c. 32). But if body art covers
nah Arendt’s notion of action. The creation of artefacts such
such a diverse range of artistic practices then body art as a
as works of art is what Arendt calls “work”. In “action,” on the
term becomes merely descriptive and has very little, if any,
other hand, no final product is created. The clearest example
critical power. Body art sounds like a kind of art (like paint-
of action is politics, where people act for the common good
ing or sculpture) but it is really just a genre within the arts.
but where every act (a law or “act” passed, a decision made,
Hence, we may assume that much performance art will also
a stand taken) can always be undone or overturned by future
be a kind of body art because it usually presupposes the use
acts. In this sense, action is open-ended: its results are never
of the body. But that is all the insight to be gleaned from such
certain and always temporary. If one sets out to act, one nev-
a general approach. After all, most art, even writing, presup-
er knows where one is going to end up.
poses the use of the body.
But performance art is not identical with action. There are
I would suggest that not all performance art is body art in
two reasons for this. First, performance art may leave behind
the sense described here. Not all performance art involves
a final object as end result, be it an artefact created in the
the body in its physicality. Sometimes the body is merely the
performance, some relic of the performance (as when Her-
agent that performs an action which is the actual focus of
mann Nitsch exhibits the paint-splattered and bloodstained
the performance. In this sense the body is sometimes used to
robes he wore during his performances), or a photographic
197
or other audio-visual record of the performance which may
perceived as politically charged acts of resistance, which
come to substitute for the actual performance in exhibitions.
makes them eligible as examples of actual political action. In
Second, insofar as it is art, performance art is not action as
Happenings the line between art and reality, between action
such, but the illusion of action. This becomes especially clear
and illusion, becomes blurred and our definitions flounder.
if we consider that performance art is usually limited in time.
198
It starts and it ends and in that sense it is not open-ended:
From Performance to Concept
when one starts a performance one has some idea of where
Trying to define performance art in terms of action seems
one is going and where one wants to end up. This means that
logical but has proved to be a conceptual dead end. So we
the performance is scripted, or at least outlined, and that it is
must try and find a better definition. But before we attempt a
not in its overall structure improvised or spontaneous (which
more satisfactory definition of performance art we might do
really simply means that there must be some kind of com-
well to dwell awhile on the reasons why the present defini-
manding form at work). All improvisation that does occur
tion of performance as action is insufficient. To do this we
must be framed within a pre-established pattern that should
might approach the problem from a different vantage point.
at least be known to all the participants involved in the per-
As we said, a performance must have some element of pre-
formance. Therefore a performance is never open-ended in
meditation to be art: there must be commanding form. But
the sense that (political) action is: it has a form and the act
from this an interesting issue emerges. Suppose that an art-
of performing is the presentation or elaboration of this form.
ist has planned a performance and sends out invitations to
But this description of performance art immediately raises
artworld people to be present at the performance. For the
several grave problems. For we might legitimately ask what it
benefit of the press and other attendants a brief statement
is about performance art that makes it an illusion of action?
has been prepared in which the artist outlines what he will
How can we distinguish between action per se (in the sense
do and what will be its meaning. An interesting way to deter-
of Arendt) and an illusion of action? If performance art is art,
mine the artistic value of the performance might be to ask if
it must have some formal quality that makes it so. Clearly,
the actual performance will add anything of an aesthetic nature
our definition of performance art as the illusion of action is
to the brief outline presented in prose. If the actual perfor-
not sufficiently specific and soon becomes a conceptual mud-
mance does indeed not add anything of an aesthetic nature
dle because it is too difficult to determine when an action
to the work (which means that it really does not matter very
should be perceived as actual or illusory. This issue becomes
much whether you are actually present at the performance
especially vexing in relation to a kind of performance art that
to grasp its meaning and intent), we might judge the per-
was particularly popular in the late 1960s, the Happening.
formance non-artistic, or at least failed or bad art. If the full
As Allan Kaprow pointed out, ‘a Happening cannot be repro-
import of the performance can be grasped in a set of instruc-
duced’ (Jones 2000: 28). In this way Happenings were often
tions or a detailed description to which the actual perfor-
199
200
mance as event has little or nothing to add, the work would
definition about ideas and not about form. It is very facile to
seem to be merely discursive: the performance-as-event has
place an object (which can then be called a “ready-made,” as
no aesthetic value in itself and simply serves as a vehicle for
if such renaming of everyday objects magically turns them
an idea or an argument that remains just as valid in an es-
into something other than what they are) in a museum and
say or any other discursive presentation. In fact, the value of
then elaborate on the many critical or political meanings that
the work seems to lie in the description and not at all in the
are attached to it.
action itself. When this redundancy of the performance-as-
But we must ask ourselves, after having read an essay about
event occurs, we might say that the performance is not art
the meanings of a certain conceptual artist’s work, if it is
but illustration.
really necessary to our understanding of the work to actu-
This approach to the problem of the artistic stature of per-
ally go to the museum and see with our own eyes the objects
formance art opens interesting perspectives on other fields
displayed as the carriers of such lofty meanings and radi-
of controversy in recent art, such as the doctorate in the arts.
cal sentiments. I dare suggest that a urinal, regardless of its
As we saw in the previous chapter, several academies and
geographical location, is still very much a urinal after such
universities now offer PhD programmes in art. Such pro-
meanings have been attached to it and that Duchamp’s ac-
grammes usually require the artist to create a work with an
tual urinal as installed in a museum has very little to add
accompanying treatise on the work’s meanings and the cre-
to the idea of Duchamp’s urinal as installed in a museum. So the
ative process involved. This sets the stage for much bad art,
urinal is probably not very great art, although we must grant
for any work of art worth its salt should be able to communi-
that Duchamp, being the first to create such ready-mades, did
cate with its audience in a relevant way without the require-
make a radical gesture and was too intelligent an artist not to
ment of the previous perusal of a theoretical manual. If art
be aware of the ironies and conceptual complexities involved
needs theory to make itself understood, the artist has simply
in it. It is mostly his followers who are flukes. This does not
failed to make a successful work of art. Much such work
mean that the ideas at work behind conceptual art cannot in
tries to redeem itself by being presented as a form of “artis-
themselves be legitimate and interesting. Much conceptual
tic research”. But this, we claimed, is bad faith. Not because
art raises very interesting questions. But the nature of the
artistic research does not exist, but because all good artists
questions or their tentative answers is not in any way en-
do their research in their work. The work is the research, not
hanced by calling them art. A question is not a work of art.
the commentary. David Hockney once mentioned ‘a wonder-
And a non-aesthetic object does not become art because a
ful quote of Picasso’s, which I keep referring to, where he
question is attached to it. It simply gives the whole operation
says he never made a painting as a work of art; it was always
some artistic cachet. In fact, it now becomes clear that much
research’ (Weschler 2008: 61). From this perspective we can
performance art and conceptual art, in setting forth critical
also take a fresh look at conceptual art, which is almost by
statements about the world and the objects in it, are much
201
202
nearer to what Arendt called action than to art. People who
seen, for a brief period of time, as a counter-force to the com-
do performances or who raise interesting questions through
mercialisation of the art market: here, at last, were works of
conceptual art do something more akin to politics, journal-
art that could not be bought or sold. But the artworld cynics
ism, and civil action than to art.
soon changed that: if you can’t sell the work, market the at-
The political component of performance art, its breaking of
titude. Hence the introduction of a new cultural currency: the
taboos and challenging of social norms, can also be seen as
avant-garde identity rather than the avant-garde work of art.
another way in which the artworld has tried to regain the al-
Finally, the link between performance art and political action
lure of avant-gardism after it had fashionably declared avant-
becomes especially salient if we keep in mind that the rise of
gardes dead: by subscribing to supposedly radical political,
performance art and conceptual art was closely linked to the
social, or sexual ideas they substitute an avant-garde of the
rise of issue-based and identity art in the 1970s and 1980s.
political and the sexual for an avant-garde of the formal or
In all these kinds of art content matters more than form
the aesthetic. The mechanism at work in the sudden popu-
and the content is often overtly political. In this respect, Lea
larity of street art is also at work in the radical posturing of
Vergine’s early theoretical statement is especially instructive
performance art and its politically charged discourse. Thus,
when it claims that performance and body artists ‘want an
street art and performance art both function along similar
intimate acquaintance with all of the possibilities of self-
lines: they provide the artworld with a new sense of hip
knowledge that can stem from the body and the investigation
avant-gardism, a trendy with-it attitude that recreates the
of the body. The body is stripped bare in an extreme attempt
exclusive sense of an inner circle that was once generated
to acquire the right to a rebirth back into the world. Most of
through formal aesthetic experiments within the actual work
the time, the experiences we are dealing with are authentic,
of art. The result is an artworld that is not really interested
and they are consequently cruel and painful. Those who are
in art anymore but in a politics of the personal. And it might
in pain will tell you that they have the right to be taken seriously.
certainly be true that the personal is the political (for every-
These artists do not “take a long look at life,” and their forms
thing political has repercussions for the way we live our per-
of expression are not genteel. They make no a priori exclu-
sonal lives), but art is not politics. Even politically engaged art
sions and in most of them suffering is not transformed into
is not politics (at worst it is propaganda). And politics, apart
mysticism. This is particularly true when they are involved in
from not being art, cares very little about art to begin with,
the investigation of our infirmities and the monstrous organi-
unless when art can serve political purposes (by becoming
sation of the real. It’s a question of facing up to death through
propaganda) or offers an opportunity to sound moral alarms
life, rummaging around in the under and seamy sides of life,
that will generate votes (as in the culture wars). What is es-
bringing to light the secret and the hidden’ (Vergine 2000: 8-9).
pecially ironic about this evolution within the artworld is the
This passage shows how the rhetoric of victimhood was in-
fact that performance art, along with land art, was actually
troduced into discussions of performance and issue-based art
203
almost from the start. The italics in the passage are Vergine’s
death, since the vomit would have no place to go. And should
and they stress the inalienable right of the victim to be taken
any one of us vomit, we might trigger him to do likewise”’
seriously, even when she is not creating any artistic form but
(Warr 2000: 104). From this description it is clear that to wit-
simply acting out her victimhood. It is surely no coincidence
ness McCarthy’s performance is a perplexing experience. To
that much issue-based art subsequently took the form of
act in such a provocative and disgusting way clearly affects
performances, as in the work of such feminist luminaries
the audience. Who would not become nauseous while watch-
as Karen Finley or the self-dramatisations of Bob Flanagan.
ing such a spectacle? But the question is of course why this
As Amelia Jones breathlessly points out, the ‘leaky bodies’
performance should be a work of art. Similar gross acts are
of Ron Athey, Gina Pane, and Orlan ‘violently recorporealise
perpetrated in such pseudo-reality television shows as Jack-
the subjects of culture who spew, shit, piss and vomit their
ass and Dirty Sanchez, and yet nobody has made claims for
woundedness (as female, gay, sick)’ (Jones 2000: 33). But is
the superior artistic quality of such shows. So there must be
there artistic achievement or aesthetic merit in displaying
something about McCarthy’s performance that sets it apart
one’s woundedness?
from mere provocation. As we saw earlier, the presence of all kinds of “subversive or critical meanings” hardly qualifies
204
Engaging the Audience
as such a difference, for we might well argue that any act of
We must now try again to find the primary illusion created
gross indecency, by virtue of its offensive nature, challenges
in performance art. Several classic instances of performance
established moral codes and should therefore be considered
art offer clues towards such a definition. Our first exhibit is
of artistic merit. And yet such acts, when perpetrated in pub-
a description of Paul McCarthy’s Hot Dog (1974), one of the
lic without prior consent of government officials, are usually
artist’s ‘earliest performances enacting masochistic culinary
condemned as indecent exposure and not celebrated as ma-
rituals. McCarthy stripped and shaved his body in front of a
jor feats of artistic achievement.
small group of friends in his basement studio. Artist Barbara
Let us look at two further examples. Gina Pane’s seminal
Smith, present at the event, reported: “He [then] stuffs his
performance Le Lait Chaud (1972) showed the artist cutting
penis into a hotdog bun and tapes it on, then smears his ass
herself with a razor blade. Pane herself describes what hap-
with mustard... He approaches the tables and sits nearby,
pened: ‘Suddenly I turned to face my public and approached
drinking ketchup and stuffing his mouth with hot dogs...
the razor blade to my face. The tension was explosive and
Binding his head with gauze and adding more hot dogs, he
broke when I cut my face on either cheek. They yelled “No,
finally tapes his bulging mouth closed so that the protruding
no, not the face, no!” So I touched an essential problem – the
mouth looks like a snout... He stands alone struggling with
aestheticism in every person. The face is taboo, it’s the core
himself, trying to prevent his own retching. It is apparent that
of human aesthetics’ (o.c. 121). A more extreme form of au-
he is about to vomit... Should he vomit he might choke to
tomutilation is performed in the “performance-surgery” of
205
206
French artist Orlan. Tracey Warr describes such an operation
art, where audience response and even audience participa-
as it was broadcast live to fifteen sites worldwide: ‘Specta-
tion are often made part of the work itself. To clarify this
tors around the world could ask the artist questions both
we might compare performance art with the theatrical arts,
before and during the operation, to which she responded as
where the presence of an audience is also highly desirable (if
the procedure permitted. Elaborately staging the events with
only to prevent the act of performing a play from being a pro-
colourful drapery, costumes created by famous designers,
foundly depressing experience for the actors involved). But
and extra personnel to translate into English and sign for the
in theatre, as in dance, the fictional space of the work is al-
deaf, Orlan transformed the operating theatre into her studio,
ways demarcated from the space of the audience. Langer has
while her operation provided the material for the production
written incisively about this feature, especially in relation to
of film, video, photographs and objects to be exhibited later.
dance. Langer suggests that ‘all dance motion is gesture [...].
The operation was performed by a feminist plastic surgeon,
Gesture is the basic abstraction whereby the dance illusion is
Dr Marjorie Cramer, who inserted implants above Orlan’s
made and organised’ (FF 174). But gesture is not gesticulation.
eyes and in her cheeks and chin. The artist was conscious but
‘Gesticulation, as part of our actual behaviour, is not art. It is
locally anaesthetised, and it is therefore the spectator who
simply vital movement’ (FF 175). Gesticulation, bodily move-
suffers as a result of the discomfort produced by images of
ments brought about by the hustle and bustle of daily exis-
the operation. The artist retains ultimate (conscious) control
tence, is not art. It is a symptom of our being actively alive in
of the process of her facial remoulding and thus the repre-
the world. ‘Virtual gestures,’ on the other hand, namely the
sentation of her (female) face and body in art’ (o.c. 185). The
gestures created in the illusion of dance, ‘are symbols of will.
case of Orlan is especially instructive. It is clearly a perfor-
The spontaneous gestic character of dance motions is illu-
mance in the sense that it is elaborately staged as an event
sory, and the vital force they express is illusory; the “powers”
that is limited in time. It produces a series of artefacts com-
(i.e. centers of vital force) in dance are created beings – cre-
memorating the event. By having it performed by a feminist
ated by the semblance of gesture’ (FF 175). The dance turns
surgeon, the performance raises (admittedly rather trite and
gesture into fiction, an illusion. ‘The primary illusion of dance
unexciting) political issues. And by remoulding a woman’s
is a virtual realm of Power – not actual, physically exerted
face it confronts issues of canons of beauty and how ideas of
power, but appearances of influence and agency created by
the body beautiful are projected onto women’s bodies.
virtual gesture. In watching a collective dance – say, an ar-
But the really salient issue which is present in all three cases
tistically successful ballet – one does not see people running
discussed, is the issue of audience involvement and audience
around; one sees the dance driving this way, drawn that way,
response. Obviously, all art addresses an audience. But a paint-
gathering here, spreading there – fleeing, resting, rising, and
ing, a film, a sculpture, or a novel is offered the audience as a
so forth; and all the motion seems to spring from powers be-
finished product. This is not usually the case in performance
yond the performers. In a pas de deux the two dancers appear
207
208
to magnetise each other; the relation between them is more
magnetising the dancers, is not coextensive with the space
than a spatial one, it is a relation of forces; but the forces they
of the audience. The dance illusion is given the audience as a
exercise, that seem to be as physical as those which orient
spectacle, an illusory world, to look at. In this, it differs from
the compass needle toward its pole, really do not exist physi-
sculpture and architecture. As Langer notes, sculpture often
cally at all. They are dance forces, virtual powers’ (FF 175-176).
kindles in people a desire to touch it because ‘volume is real-
But these virtual powers immediately generate another effect
ly given originally to touch, [...] and the business of sculpture
which is crucial to their success. ‘Every dancer sees the dance
is to translate its data into entirely visual terms, i.e. to make
sufficiently to let his imagination grasp it as a whole; and
tactual space visible’ (FF 89-90). With architecture, we actually
with his own body-feeling he understands the gestic forms
inhabit its ethnic domain. This does not diminish the fact
that are its interwoven, basic elements. He cannot see his
that such virtual spaces are given primarily to our perception,
own form as such, but he knows his appearance – the lines
but it does mean that the self-contained world created in
described by his body are implied in the shifts of his vision,
these arts functions in a way different from the field of Power
even if he is dancing alone, and are guaranteed but the rhyth-
in dance gestures. With dance, as with the theatre, the spec-
mic play of his muscles, the freedom with which his impuls-
tator is usually kept at a further distance from the work than
es spend themselves in complete and intended movements.
in sculpture or architecture.
He sees the world in which his body dances, and that is the
I believe that Langer’s notion of a magnetic field of powers
primary illusion of his work; in this closed realm he develops
between dancers in a dance is a crucial clue to the primary
his ideas’ (FF 197). This last observation is crucial: the dance
illusion of performance art, where the audience itself be-
creates a closed realm, a world on its own. ‘The dance cre-
comes involved in the force-field created in the work. It is the
ates an image of nameless and even bodiless Powers filling a
incorporation of audience response or participation into the
complete, autonomous realm, a “world”’ (FF 190). ‘The dance,
work rather than the action-like nature of the event that is
or dancers,’ Langer continues, ‘must transform the stage for
crucial to the primary illusion of performance art (which sub-
the audience as well as for themselves into an autonomous,
sequently may or may not also be body art, depending on the
complete, virtual realm, and all motions into a play of visible
role of the body physical in the proceedings). Performance
forces in unbroken, virtual time’ (FF 204). This recalls, to some
art can never be complete as a work without the audience.
extent, the primary illusion of the visual arts, the creation
We must understand this well. As we said before, all art re-
of virtual space in painting, sculpture, and architecture. Es-
quires an audience. But most art is finished as a work before
pecially the way sculpture inhabits and organises the empty
the audience becomes involved. In temporal terms, the work
space around it seems to be akin to the way the realm of
of art is usually completed before the audience comes in (in
Power of dance generates a world of its own. This means that
the case of the theatre or the dance, where the individual
the space of the world of the dance, its virtual field of powers
performance only starts when the audience is present in the
209
210
theatre, the work was actually completed during rehearsals,
form of art that differs crucially from all other forms of art:
and what is presented to the audience is the accomplished
it breaks open its virtual world to include the audience and
living symbol of the play or the dance as it was conceived,
in that sense becomes somehow world-encompassing. Since
achieved, and perfected through rehearsal: the play or the
performance art emerged as a full-fledged art form in the
dance that the audience will see is already finished in the
1960s, when it was charged with political and emancipatory
minds and bodies of the performers, who are ready to perform
intentions, such breaking-open towards the world should
it again, and again, and again, usually without much adjust-
not surprise us. By encompassing the audience, and hence
ment of the original form). In performance art the work cannot
the entire phenomenologically present environment, perfor-
be complete before the audience comes in. As a matter of fact,
mance art generates a sense of claustrophobia that is crucial
the audience becomes instrumental in the completion of the
to its success: the magnetic force-field that ties dancers in a
work because its response to or participation in it is crucial to
pas de deux here includes the audience, which is given a sense
the accomplishment of the work. Clearly, McCarthy’s Hot Dog
of being locked in. To be present at a performance is to have
includes the audience response (the felt experience of nausea
the feeling that one cannot get away. One is part of the event.
and the simultaneous knowledge that to give way to nausea
This means that it is far more difficult for the spectator to
might endanger the artist) as part of the work. Take away the
remain a disinterested spectator. Because one is involved in
tension between the performer and his audience and there is
the force-field, one is drawn almost physically into the per-
simply no work, only the masochistic shenanigans of a man
formance. This dynamic is especially clear in Barbara Smith’s
involved in a highly inventive form of sexual adventurous-
response to McCarthy’s Hot Dog: it is as if the audience is tak-
ness. The acts performed by McCarthy might still be mean-
en hostage by the work and is made to feel McCarthy’s nausea
ingful or (sexually, masochistically) exciting to the artist as a
instead of simply watching it. Obviously, the examples we
private person, but they would no longer be art (although we
have used here are extreme forms of performance and much
should allow for the fact that the presence of a camera docu-
performance art is far less confrontational or aggressive
menting the solitary performance might substitute for an
towards the audience. But even in more demure cases the
audience). Similarly, what would be the use of Gina Pane cut-
audience becomes directly involved because the performance
ting her face if there were no audience present to be shocked
engages both its response and, it should by now be clear, its
by her action? In performance the audience becomes part of
reflection. Given the politically charged nature of much per-
the fabric of the work itself.
formance art, which is further illustrated in its popularity
We can now endeavour a new definition of performance art. I
among artists engaged in issue-based art, the performance
suggest that the primary illusion created in performance art
often has the specific goal of triggering a political or critical
is the illusion of action within a virtual realm of power that
insight in the audience. It wants to make the audience aware
includes both the performer and the audience. In this, it is a
of some injustice. But in a good performance, this triggering
211
212
of insight in the audience is part of the fabric of the work (as
merely an illusion: the real world is still out there, beyond the
it would also be in conceptual art).
boundaries of the virtual realm of the performance. But the
But the political charge of much performance art also circles
effect of this coup is that the experience of watching a per-
back to action in the sense of Arendt. Therefore our defini-
formance becomes part of the performance itself. Hence a
tion once again states that the primary illusion created in
performance is a kind of art in which consciousness-raising
performance art is an illusion of action. This is the very aspect
can become an integral part of the virtual world because it is
that we earlier identified as profoundly problematic: it lead
integrated into the artistic fabric.
us straight into a conceptual muddle. But I believe we can
It should be clear that our definition of the primary illusion
evade the muddle this time because we situate the illusion
of performance art does not solve all our problems. But the
of action within a virtual realm of power that includes both
primary illusion does offer us a clue as to what performance
performer(s) and audience. This addition is crucial. Our ear-
art is good art. In fact, insofar as much performance art takes
lier problems with the illusion of action as a definition of the
on a decidedly discursive form by letting ideological or po-
primary illusion of performance art stemmed mainly from
litical intentions prevail over formal concerns, an unusually
the fact that it was impossible to determine whether any
high degree of performance art may be rather mediocre. It
action was real or illusory. But if we situate the illusion of ac-
is surely the challenge of the performance artist to create
tion within a power-field that is itself already a virtual world
a form that does something considerably more ambitious
on its own, this problem disappears: all action performed in
than provoke a visceral reaction in the audience (as in the
the performance pertains not to the real world, but only to
nausea experienced while watching Hot Dog), denounce some
the virtual world created in the work. The audience present
social injustice (as in the work of Karen Finley), or engage
at a performance is never really an audience and is never re-
in an exhibitionism of the ailing body (as in the work of Bob
ally in front of the stage: it is on the stage, part of the action,
Flanagan). All the objections against performance and con-
and part of the virtual realm created. In this sense we might
ceptual art that were raised earlier remain valid now that we
say that performance art has something of the ideal, which
have determined the primary illusion of the performance.
was very popular in the 1960s and 1970s, of turning one’s life
But the primary illusion should help us explain why so much
into a work of art. By creating a virtual realm that encom-
performance art is failed art, bad art, or maybe not even art
passes a realm that is not usually supposed to be part of the
at all. It is one thing to say that performance art includes the
virtual world, namely the realm of the spectator, the artist
audience in its primary illusion, it is another thing to say that
is actually performing a coup on the world: he obliterates
any work that includes the audience in its primary illusion
the world (insofar as it is phenomenologically present to the
is therefore by definition good (performance) art. It offers us
performers and the audience) by including it in his action. So
a criterion for distinguishing true works of performance art
the real and the fictional are conflated. But this is obviously
from works that are falsely seen as performance art. For in-
213
stance, it might be argued that works such as Chris Burden’s
single most notorious piece of performance art in which the
Oh, Dracula (1974), which had the artist sleep in a chrysalis-
artist put her own life in jeopardy was Marina Abramovic’s
like sheet attached to the wall of the museum, or a Peter
Rhythm 0 (1974) in which ‘Abramovic stood by a table and of-
Greenaway exhibit of a naked woman (The Physical Self, 1991)
fered herself passively to spectators, who could do what they
really belong in a survey of sculpture rather than one of per-
liked with a range of objects and her body. A text on the wall
formance art. To the extent that there is no explicit illusion of
read, “There are seventy-two objects on the table that can be
action in these works and that they are primarily presented
used on me as desired. I am the object.” The objects included
as exhibits rather than audience-inclusive events, such works
a gun, a bullet, a saw, an axe, a fork, a comb, a whip, lipstick,
seem to be extreme cases of sculpture.
a bottle of perfume, paint, knives, matches, a feather, a rose, a candle, water, chains, nails, needles, scissors, honey, grapes,
214
Lethal Objections
plaster, sulphur and olive oil. By the end of the performance
As noted before, the boundary between performance art and
all her clothes had been sliced off her body with razor blades,
body art is often blurred. This is especially the case in the
she had been cut, painted, cleaned, decorated, crowned with
most sensational, and often the most effective, kind of per-
thorns and had had the loaded gun pressed against her head.
formance art, namely the performance in which the body is
After six hours the performance was halted by concerned
shown to accomplish immense feats of physical endurance,
spectators’ (Warr 2000: 125).
often to the point of putting the artist’s physical well-being
Rhythm 0 is an extreme case of audience involvement in art
at risk. McCarthy’s Hot Dog and Pane’s Le Lait Chaud are clear
that develops ideas that can be traced back to Yoko Ono’s
examples of such performance art. But other and more noto-
Cut Piece (1964) and similar works in which the artist’s body
rious instances have become the topic of controversy. Chris
becomes the willing passive recipient of aggressive acts. It
Burden famously had a friend shoot him in the arm for Shoot
is a matter of dispute whether such performances are still
(1971), for Trans-fixed (1974) he was nailed to a car in the pos-
art. The inclusion of the audience in the virtual world of the
ture of the crucified Christ, and for the notorious Deadman
action is certainly taken to the limit in Abramovic’s piece
(1972) Burden himself explains that ‘at 8 pm I lay down on La
since it was up to members of the audience to determine
Cienega Boulevard and was covered completely with a canvas
when the performance was over; when, in other words, they
tarpaulin. Two 15-minute flares were placed near me to alert
themselves had had enough. Apart from that, the entire per-
cars. Just before the flares extinguished, a police car arrived. I
formance smacks of abject nihilism. The fact that a loaded
was arrested and booked for causing a false emergency to be
gun was held to Abramovic’s head seems to defy all reason:
reported. The trial took place in Beverly Hills. After three days
why would an artist put her life at risk simply to make some
of deliberations, the jury failed to reach a decision and the
point? Such nihilistic acts of self-destruction are usually the
judge dismissed the case’ (Hoffman 2007: 158). Perhaps the
preserve of suicide bombers or political or religious fanat-
215
216
ics who engage in self-immolation. There is no denying the
Or would he simply be deemed a fierce critic of a contentious
incredible force such extreme performances have for the
work of art? If Abramovic offers the means and the opportu-
people present. As Gina Pane remarked of Le Lait Chaud, ‘the
nity for her murder as an artistic event, an open invitation
tension was explosive,’ and we may be sure that it was even
to trigger-pulling, does that entitle me to pull that trigger?
more so for the people present at Rhythm 0. The question we
I doubt it. To the extent that killing Abramovic would have
are faced with is whether such tension has anything artistic
very real extra-artistic consequences in the real world (for
about it if it involves such reckless risk-taking. For there is a
one thing, it would certainly make prices for her works soar
very definite line that runs between Pane’s Le Lait Chaud on
in the art market) the entire event is decidedly not a work
the one hand and Deadman or Rhythm 0 on the other. Pane
of art. The fact that I hire someone to kill me does not make
is always in charge of the proceedings, as is Orlan when she
that hired killer innocent of murder in the eyes of the law (if
submits to surgery. But both Burden and Abramovic introduce
it did, the whole question of euthanasia would not cause so
an element of unpredictability by relinquishing control to
much legal and political debate). The fact that I send out invi-
coincidence or the wiles of other people. A person with mur-
tations to the act does not make it art. So it is clear that any
derous intent may well use the occasion of Rhythm 0 to act
performance that wants to include its audience in its risk-
upon his impulses. A driver passing Deadman may not notice
taking must first make sure that the audience is complicit
the flares and run over Burden. In both cases the question is
and knows exactly what it is in for. Ironically, this would
if both artists have not simply behaved in a grossly irrespon-
often spoil the shock value of the performance itself. But it
sible way rather than created a work of art. Also, the case of
need not. That prepping the audience is possible without
Deadman raises the question of the participation of people
destroying the thrill of risk was shown in Santiago Sierra’s
who are not willing members of the audience. If the hypo-
performance-slash-installation 300 Tons, created at the Kun-
thetical driver runs over Burden, has he not been made an
sthaus Bregenz in April 2004. Here is Sierra’s written concept
unwilling accomplice to murder/suicide? Does any innocent
for the event: ‘292 tons of concrete bricks were carried to the
passer-by deserve to be faced with the possible consequences
top floor of the Kunsthaus Bregenz and their weight distrib-
of Burden’s behaviour?
uted on temporary supports over the whole building. That
These are troubling questions and the fact that the works
will almost result, though with sufficient leeway, in the entire
themselves might be intended to raise and debate these
building collapsing due to the overload. For this reason the
questions hardly seems to redeem them as art. Suppose for
number of visitors present at any time may never be more
a moment that a person had actually pulled the trigger on
than 100, which represents an additional 8 tons’ (Schneider
Abramovic. How would the authorities have reacted to that?
2004: 13).
Would the trigger-puller be arrested? Charged with murder
The Kunsthaus Bregenz is designed to carry a maximum
or manslaughter (or woman-slaughter; or person-slaughter)?
weight of 300 tons. Above that limit (but, we may assume,
217
even approaching that limit from below) the building might
has anything resembling the stunning beauty of Serra’s metal
crack. So it is up to the visitor to decide if he or she wants to
constructions. If it does, I do not think this redeems the work
take the risk of hoisting inside his extra pounds of art fod-
as art (a beautiful stupid risk is still a stupid risk), but if it
der that will bring the entire construction down, causing all
does not, then all we are left with is the thrill. And the idea
present to die a gloriously artistic death. I strongly feel that,
behind this thrill, including its possible critical meanings, is
in a free world, every person has the right to behave the way
again sufficiently expressed in the written concept. To actu-
they like, no matter how stupid, as long as they don’t hurt
ally visit it would be carelessness (and just imagine making it
anybody. But this is very stupid behaviour. And I dare sug-
a family outing and losing both one’s parents in the event).
gest that those engaging in it are fooling themselves no end
218
if they think that what they are doing is artistic or artistically
The Meating of Porn and Art on a Dissecting Table
relevant. Again, the question we must ask ourselves is if the
When feats of physical endurance become enmeshed with is-
thrill of risk and of possible death makes for good art. Or, to
sues of the sexual body, the question of pornography rears it
state it another way, would it not be possible to create the
naughty head. Just like much performance art, pornographic
thrill of risk without any actual risk involved; which means:
films (and we shall restrict ourselves primarily to porno-
to create an illusion of risk, which would immediately take
graphic films, although it will become instantly clear that the
us back into the realm of art, where all realities are virtual.
argument we are about to make can easily be expanded to
Consider, for example, the imposing installations of Rich-
include erotic cabarets and stripping) offer feats of physical
ard Serra, huge constructions that loom ominously over the
endurance. Even tepidly mainstream porn films often require
viewer. Serra’s work is there to be looked at and to be experi-
performers to be contortionists: they must bend and stretch
enced. I find Serra’s work extremely successful, and part of its
their bodies to allow the camera maximum visibility. On top
success lies in the fact that it does not count upon the cheap
of that, they must be sexually active, perform sometimes
thrill of real risk to engage its audience. Serra makes us feel
challenging acts of sexual prowess, such as double penetra-
uncomfortable without putting our physical integrity at risk
tions, all the while trying to look glamorous and aroused.
(although, tragically, in the early 1970s one of his installations
That porn might be an Olympic discipline becomes especially
did collapse during construction, killing a worker; but this
clear if we look at a pornographic genre that has remark-
was a tragic accident, not something intended as a calculated
able affinities with performance and ritual: sadomasochistic
possibility). Also, Serra’s work not only deals with the per-
porn, which often includes such transgressive acts as fisting,
ceived threat of sublime sculpture, he is also concerned with
bondage, and urolagnia (it were these kinds of acts that were
issues of texture, choice of materials, architecture, and the
deemed unacceptably offensive in Robert Mapplethorpe’s
geography of space. I did not visit 300 Tons, nor would I feel
X Portfolio). Both in the performances of Marina Abramovic
inclined to, so I do not know if the sight of 292 tons of bricks
and Chris Burden and in the acrobatics of porn stars there is
219
220
a test of the body and its endurance. If Abramovic cuts her
supposed to become art when it is done in an “artistic con-
stomach with a razor or if Burden lets a friend shoot a bul-
text” (whatever that may be) but cannot be art, or at least not
let through his arm, they are submitting themselves to acts
as easily be regarded as art, if it takes place in a porn film. An
that are painful, potentially dangerous, and that require great
obvious answer would be that the two are different in kind.
endurance in the performer. The same can be said of porn
We might say that art tries to communicate, for want of a
performers. It requires considerable endurance to take anoth-
better word, deeper meanings or make critical comments on
er person’s fist or arm up the ass, submit to several forms of
certain topics. The meaning of the sex does not lie in the sex
sexual abuse, or endure the soiling of the body, both its skin
itself. This is different with pornography, which is really just
and its inside, with urine or other bodily secretions.
about instant gratification. But this difference rests on sev-
This risk-taking with the body is pushed to the limit in un-
eral unchallenged and profoundly problematic assumptions.
safe sex. In gay porn there is a vogue for what is called bare-
First, there is no reason to assume that art does not also offer
backing: performers who fuck without condoms, knowingly
instant gratification. If a work of art is beautiful, it can give
exposing themselves to the risk of contracting hiv/aids. The
us a jolt and instantly uplift our mood. Certain genres of film
odd thing is that we are apparently very willing to accept
that are usually associated with instant gratification, such as
death-defying performances by Burden or Abramovic as art,
horror films or the thriller, have practitioners who are highly
but when porn performers (or indeed any visitor of a kinky
regarded as artists, such as Alfred Hitchcock. The thrills and
sex club) engage in acrobatic sex without the protection of
shocks of these films, although integrated in a fabric of ex-
a condom this is regarded as unnecessary risk-taking and
quisite expressive form, could be considered instant gratifica-
as irresponsible behaviour (in fact, many people who prac-
tion and they are undeniably part of the reason we like to see
tice an extreme or dangerous sport take similar calculated
such films. Obviously, these films also do many other things
risks without incurring our moral disapprobation). But surely
beyond delivering effects and shocks, but it is an unwar-
Abramovic and Burden are putting their bodies’ well-being
ranted assumption to suggest that pornography by definition
equally at risk as the porn performers. And whatever mes-
does not also offer anything more in such a way.
sage these performances try to communicate could surely
But this defence of pornography is itself guilty of prejudice,
be communicated just as clearly and effectively without put-
for in making it we are assuming that the supposed instant
ting the body at risk. So there is no clear way in which porn
gratification of porn could not be valuable in itself and hence
is in any sense more “gratuitous” than extreme performance
not worthy of being considered art. This is odd. If a tragic
art: in both cases, performers willingly and knowingly take
novel or play makes us care for its characters and maybe
calculated risks with their own bodies in a spectacle. The
even shed tears because we are moved by their fate, the work
question we are facing is why such behaviour, and especially
is considered a success. If the pornographic film succeeds in
such extreme or risk-taking behaviour of a sexual nature, is
stimulating us to orgasm, it is also considered a success, but
221
222
of a rather vulgar kind. This is hypocrisy. We should not judge
films that have incorporated explicit sexual imagery. Patrice
porn on account of the fact that it is pornographic. That porn
Chéreau’s remarkable film Intimacy (2000) and Larry Clark’s
is not about telling complex psychological stories is hardly
unsettling and decidedly horny Ken Park (2002) are exceptions,
surprising. We should judge porn as a genre in itself and ap-
but usually such films turn out banal or fail both as works
ply the same standard that we apply to all other genres or all
of art and as works of pornography. They become sterile and
other arts: we should simply discriminate between good porn
unmoving. It would seem that porn is at its best when it is
and bad porn. And it is an undeniable fact that the ability to
allowed to be what it is and endeavours to excel at its usual
arouse sexual lust in the viewer is a sign that a pornographic
business.
film is a success. But we should not be naive either. Of all the
What kind of art, then, is porn and what kinds of bodies are
possible effects a work of art can have on the human organ-
represented in it? Pornography is the art of the sexual body
ism, sexual arousal is surely among the easiest to achieve.
in motion: it creates symbols, forms expressive of the ec-
Mother Nature has kindly programmed us to react swiftly
static body. It might be objected that it is glib to suggest that
and with great dedication to almost any erotic stimulus. It
the naked bodies in pornographic films are “expressive of”
does not take much artistry to push the buttons of arousal.
something else which just happens to be the naked human
But then, many other effects such as laughter or emotional
body. This formulation seems to introduce a new kind of coy
involvement with a fictional character are almost just as eas-
prudery: it’s not really dicks and cunts, its “expressive of”
ily accomplished in a mediocre way, which accounts for the
arousal. And yet the formulation is necessary, for we should
many formulaic films and novels that are about. Such works,
never allow ourselves to forget that porn, like all art, is an
whether films, novels, pornographic films, or any other art,
illusion. It is, in fact, a performance in the truest sense of the
are simply mediocre art. But in porn as in any other art
word. The actors in such films do perform in the sense that
form there are outstanding works that deserve our serious
what they are showing us is not self-expressive or spontane-
consideration. And that means, among other things, to ac-
ous. The actors in the scenes do not usually play themselves,
knowledge that the success of any kind of erotic art depends
the scenes are scripted, and the performers do not usually
to a large extent on its ability to provoke in us the desired
have the choice as to which sexual acts to perform when and
response, which is arousal. As Kenneth Clark justly remarked
with whom. Commenting on her starring but sexually ex-
in his outstanding study of The Nude (1956), ‘no nude, how-
plicit role in Curt McDowell’s cult classic Thundercrack! (1975)
ever abstract, should fail to arouse in the spectator some
actress Marion Eaton says that she ‘used an actor’s technique
vestige of erotic feeling, even although it be only the faintest
to portray sexuality as “erotic realism,” but kept a line there
shadow – and if it does not do so, it is bad art and false mor-
to prevent it from being my own personal masturbation. I
als’ (Clark 1960: 6). In fact, pornographic materials often fail if
created a bigger-than-life masturbation so that it would be
they try too hard to be “artistic,” as in many recent art-house
everybody’s masturbation’ (Stevenson 1996: 241). The porn
223
224
film is directed. The action in porn films is often filmed from
this at length. She claims that ‘pornography without obscen-
different angles, there are different takes, scenes are shot
ity is sad’ (Guilló et al. 2002: 80). Ovidie gives a very precise
several times over, the material is then edited and all kinds
definition of pornography as ‘the realistic representation
of effects are introduced, from lighting effects during filming
in film or video of non-simulated sexual acts’ (o.c. 78). So
to sound effects and dubbing on the edited scene. The fact
books and paintings or drawings are never pornographic for
that there is much bad porn and some good porn and that we
Ovidie, although photographs and performance art can be.
can very easily tell the difference (because so much bad porn
Furthermore, not all pornography is obscene, and not every-
is abysmally bad) suggests that it does take talent, or an eye
thing that is obscene is also pornographic. In fact, ‘obscenity
for the erotic, to be successful at making such films, that not
only begins when something upsets us emotionally’ (o.c. 79).
anybody can do it well and that some (a very few) people do it
This means that pornography, to be obscene, must have an
with considerable vision and dedication. The pornographic is
emotional impact on the viewer, who must be somewhat
in fact a very difficult genre, one of the most difficult, which
shaken by what he or she sees. This was not usually the case
probably explains why there is so little successful material
in the 1990s, when porn became more and more tailor-made
around (another obvious reason is that most “legitimate”
for a mainstream audience, with predictable and repetitive
directors with genuine talent tend to steer clear from mak-
action, clinical presentations, and professional actresses fak-
ing porn, leaving the field to the hacks and the cynics). So it
ing orgasms. The situation is similar in gay porn, where, as
is legitimate and necessary to say that the bodies in porno-
maverick gay porn director Joe Gage puts it, professional porn
graphic films are expressive of something else, even though
actors often ‘have that West-Hollywood-escort vibe that to
they are very explicitly present. The thing they are expressive
a large degree doesn’t interest me. Because with them, the
of is the body ecstatic: successful pornographic imagery is
meter is always running and they’re into it because they can
expressive of the felt experience of the human body in its full
do it, they’re not into it because they are compelled to do it’
sexual capacity and at its highest level of sensual alertness.
(Rodriguez 2007: 20). In such films, Ovidie explains, ‘there is
When its expressive illusion is successful, we are moved by
definitely the sexual act, but there is nothing because there is
the work and (usually) become aroused, although this is not a
only the sexual act, there is no sexual dimension. If you watch
necessary outcome: sometimes the sight of bodies in rest and
the thing, there is only the sex act itself’ (Guilló et al. 2002:
motion is so moving to watch that it transcends arousal.
80). Such pornography has lost its obscenity and therefore
To achieve this kind of expressiveness it is probably neces-
its power to shock, unsettle, or even arouse the viewer in an
sary to take pornography into the realm of the obscene. One
exciting or relevant way. This is one of the reasons why some
of the failings of much porn is its coldness, its clinical pre-
performers have tried to branch out into more challenging
sentation of body parts. French porn actress Ovidie, who is a
terrain. Virginie Despentes co-directed the film Baise-moi
vocal advocate for her chosen profession, has commented on
(2000) with porn star Coralie. And male French porn star HPG
225
226
(Hervé-Pierre Gustave) managed to attract the attention of
these first experiments, it would be two years before Bour-
an art-house audience with several short subjects, notably
don made porn again, after a chance meeting with director
Acteur X pour vous servir (2001). Even if we admit that these ef-
José Bénazéraf during a private screening of one of his films.
forts were not entirely successful, the very fact that they were
The director would put her in several of his films, notably La
being made is in itself interesting because its shows that the
Soubrette perverse (1974) and La Veuve lubrique (1975). Since
idea of pornography as a form of art is now quite accepted,
such films only included simulated sex, the experience was
especially among a younger generation of performers who
a disillusionment for Bourdon, who wanted to make porn to
see their work as more than simply a kind of videographed
further her sexual enjoyment. Her chance to do so came with
prostitution.
Frédéric Lansac’s classic Le Sexe qui parle (1975) and the highly
But this recent wave of art-porn consciousness was not the
successful Candice Candy (Pierre Unia, 1976).
first. Pornography became widespread in the wake of the sex-
In the span of about a year, Bourdon would appear in a host
ual revolution of the 1960s and many early performers and
of interesting sex and porn films, including Jean Rollin’s gor-
directors believed that their work was part of the revolution,
geous Lèvres de Sang (1976). Her sexual quest also took her to
part of the attempt to break down oppressive moral codes.
the furthest edges of sexuality. For Sylvia dans l’extase (1976)
Several early porn stars were on a mission, not just on a trip
she became the first French porn star to have sex with a dog.
down exploitation road. One of the best examples of a porn
She saw this scene as an ideological statement: ‘It is time,
star whose work was equally the expression of an ideologi-
dear cinephiles, to destroy the hypocrisy of loving animals
cal belief in sexual liberation was French porn legend Sylvia
without giving them the legitimate satisfactions of a real
Bourdon. When her memoir L’Amour est une fête (1976) was
relationship. But truth compels me to admit that I was royally
republished in 2001 Bourdon added a preface in which she
paid for this scene: but I did it with pleasure because it was
wrote that, for her, pornography, along with her many other
one of my fantasies made flesh’ (o.c. 82). She also became
sexual exploits, ‘was simply part of my exploration’ (Bourdon
the subject of Jean-François Davy’s documentary Exhibition 2
2001: 8). As a sexually liberated and adventurous woman,
(1976), which painted a rather one-sided portrait of her as a
Bourdon wanted to explore all the aspects of her sexuality.
sexually voracious obsessive with dangerous ideas border-
And as exhibitionism was part of her sexual character, por-
ing on the fascist. Davy had earlier made Exhibition (1975), a
nographic films were a logical venture. In 1972 an acquain-
fascinating and intelligent portrait-as-exposure of porn star
tance brought Bourdon into contact with porn pioneer Lasse
Claudine Beccarie. The film on Bourdon included scenes of
Braun, who made a set of three 8mm shorts with her, most
sadomasochistic torture and culminated in a dinner party
famously Cake Orgy (1972), in which a group of people have
where Bourdon first gorged herself on food and then sat on
sex with each other and six cakes on a beach (this short sub-
the table, shat, and ate her own excrement. When the film
ject also featured the future star Claudine Beccarie). After
was forbidden by the censor (and later released in a heavily
227
228
truncated form, purged of its scatological finale) Davy all but
ity of the performers or characters involved are portrayed
distanced himself from his star, whom he called ‘a pathologi-
as being profoundly sexual. In a porn film everything, even
cal case,’ something for which Bourdon has never forgiven
the most commonplace situations or persons, are occasions
the man whom she in 2001 still referred to as (in deliciously
for sexual adventures. There is nothing in porn that cannot
scatological French) ‘ce lâche et ignoble salopard, cet infâme in-
become sexual. Most kitchen appliances have by now been
dividu,’ a man who grovelled before authority in the hope of
called upon to perform sexual services upon some human
salvaging his investment rather than defend his work. She
orifice. Any kind of fabric, from black lace stockings through
calls the film her one regret in life (o.c. 9). In 1977, Bourdon
rubber masks and latex briefs, have lifted fetishists up to
quit the porn business because it had become repetitive
the highest transports of ecstasy. In pornography the whole
and unchallenging. Bourdon next opened a gallery for erotic
body becomes responsive to sexual impulses, no touch is
art where she hosted, among other things, artist Journiac’s
ever innocent of sexual meaning, and our sexual desires are
performance Action érotico-patriotique (1978), a ritual piece in
projected onto everything around us. The whole world is a
which Bourdon herself partook and that was documented in
sexual cornucopia. It is a world of plenty where pleasure, and
a rarely seen 8mm film (Gayet 2002). Clearly, Bourdon’s brief
people willing and able to administer it, are amply available.
but highly publicised involvement with pornography was
Every orgasm is a blast and all desires are fulfilled. In short,
first and foremost about achieving her own aims in life: a
the world as portrayed in pornography seems like an alto-
full development of her sexual experience. She expected the
gether more desirable world than the one in which we have
projects in which she became involved to rise to the occa-
to live out our everyday lives. But it is this all-over-field of
sion. When they failed to do so, the challenge was gone and
sexual responsiveness that is often singled out as the major
she quit the scene. What remains, is a body of work that is a
moral issue in porn. Especially feminist criticism of porn has
fascinating mixture of politics, pornography, art, and sheer
complained that women in porn are portrayed as objects for
provocation.
sexual use and that their bodies are presented as automata to be used and abused at will. It is bootless to disagree with
Do Androids Wank to Electric Wet Dreams?
such an observation because it is an undeniable fact that
Now that we have agreed to take porn seriously as art we
much porn usually presents all bodies (and not just female
will have to explore more fully what we mean when we say
bodies, for there is also such a thing as gay porn and straight
that the image of felt life created in pornography is the rep-
porn in which dominant women are seen to objectify men)
resentation of the fully sexual body. I suggest that we take
as automata for sexual fulfilment. The body in porn is in-
this expression very literally for in much porn the body is
deed one huge erogenous zone that can be bent, stretched,
shown as entirely sexual: not just the sexual organs but the
and penetrated at will like an inflatable doll or a mechanical
entire surface of the body and in fact the entire personal-
bride. And instead of taking issue with this fact (for is it not
229
230
the very automaton-like quality of pornographic bodies that
there saw two androids of young boys who could write entire
makes them such a turn-on?) we should accept and applaud
sentences and which had first been exhibited in 1774.
it and try to understand its importance for the primary illu-
One of the most interesting characters in the history of the
sion of porn.
automaton or android was Jacques de Vaucanson (1709-1782),
A first way to reach such understanding takes us into the
who created several such inventions. In 1738 he exhibited
world of the mechanical body. Ken Russell’s film Gothic (1986),
his life-size Flute Player, who actually played the flute be-
an energetic and highly idiosyncratic recounting of the night
cause the mechanism Vaucanson had devised was a detailed
Mary Shelley allegedly conceived the story for her novel Fran-
imitation of human anatomy: ‘There was a mechanism to
kenstein (1818), is set in the Villa Diodati on the shores of lake
correspond to every muscle. [...] Inside the mouth was a
Léman near Geneva, where Lord Byron lived in exile with his
moveable metal tongue, which governed the air let through
personal physician and sometime lover Dr Polidori. Among
and created pauses. There were four levers to operate the
the many exotic and outrageous objects that people Byron’s
tongue and to modify the wind’ (o.c. 22-23). The only differ-
abode is a set of life-size mechanical dolls of women. One
ence between this automaton and a human flute player was
of these mechanical ladies plays the harpsichord when her
that the automaton never grew tired and could go on playing
mechanism is cranked up by a handle in the back, while an-
indefinitely. A year later, in 1739, Vaucanson improved upon
other more exotic looking specimen performs a rudimentary
his invention and diverted audiences with the automaton of
belly-dance. Such automata were very much en vogue in the
a figure that played a pipe and drum. But his most famous
eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. In fact, in 1776 a
invention was a mechanical duck, also created in 1739 and
“Musical Lady” who played he harpsichord had been exhib-
subsequently included in Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclo-
ited in London. It was the handiwork of the father and son
pédie as an example in the entry for “androïde” (o.c. 21). The
team of Pierre and Henri-Louis Jaquet-Droze. ‘As she played
mechanical duck was small in stature, but it was a great ac-
the five tunes in her repertoire,’ Gaby Wood notes of the
complishment because it actually ‘ate food out of the exhibi-
Musical Lady, ‘her eyes would move coyly from side to side,
tor’s hand, swallowed it, digested it, and excreted it, all before
and her bosom would heave lightly, as if she were breathing’
an audience. It became Vaucanson’s most famous creation;
(Wood 2002: xiv). The automaton in Russell’s film behaves in
without the shitting duck, Voltaire commented wryly, there
exactly this way. Interestingly, Gaby Wood suggests that it is
would be nothing to remind us of the glory of France. It was
possible that Mary Shelley was first inspired with the idea for
made of gold-plated copper, but it was the same size as a
the novel Frankenstein, which is after all the story of the cre-
living duck, and it moved just like one. Aside from its main
ation of an artificial man, when she saw another of the Ja-
digesting function, it could drink, muddle the water with its
quet-Drozes’ inventions. When touring Europe Shelley visited
beak, quack, rise, and settle back on its legs, and, spectators
Neuchâtel, home of the inventors, and it is possible that she
were amazed to see, it swallowed food with a quick, realis-
231
232
tic gulping action in its flexible neck. In a single wing alone,
After Kempelen’s death the Chess Player was sold to Johann
it was later revealed, there were more than 400 articulated
Nepomuk Maelzel, who is often credited with the invention
parts’ (o.c. 27). It was claimed that the digestive process was
of the metronome. Maelzel was court mechanician ‘or, as one
achieved in a small chemical laboratory Vaucanson had in-
evocative translation put it, “philosophical instrument maker,”
stalled in the duck’s intestines. However, a later owner of the
to the Hapsburgs. He was a close friend of Beethoven, whom
duck, the German writer Christian Friedrich Nicolai, ‘found
he persuaded to compose what became his “Battle” Sym-
that it did not digest its food at all. There was no “chemical
phony (Opus 91), for Maelzel’s Panharmonicon, an automated
laboratory,” he revealed – the food was simply aspirated into
orchestra of forty-two mechanical musicians’ (Wood 2002: 72-
the neck with the aid of bellows and tubes, and a separate
73). Somewhat less grand, but just as fascinating, is the fact
substance made to look like the digested version was held at
that the first mechanised waxwork in Madame Tussaud’s was
the ready in another compartment near the bird’s rear end’ to
Sleeping Beauty, who was reportedly modelled on Louis XV’s
be expelled at the desired time (o.c. 33).
mistress, Mme. du Barry. Sleeping Beauty’s ‘sole mechanical
There were other such marvels to baffle audiences of the
feature was a heaving chest’ (o.c. 25).
eighteenth century. In 1769 one Wolfgang von Kempelen cre-
In modern philosophy the idea of man as an automaton is
ated an Automaton Chess Player, a mechanical man dressed
closely linked to the context of libertinism and materialist
like a Turk who apparently played chess of his own accord
philosophy. The materialist atheists of the eighteenth century
and managed to beat even the best chess players at the game
launched an assault on the church and its moral dogmas.
(Faber 1983). It was later revealed that the Chess Player was
They combined this assault with a philosophy of pleasure
actually handled by a man hidden in the big box under the
and physical enjoyment. Such ideas were hardly new. In fact,
chess set on which the games were played. Through an in-
they originated in the thought of Epicurus and his Roman
genious system of magnets attached to the bottom of the
follower Lucretius. The rise of materialist philosophy in the
chess board the hidden man could follow the moves of the
modern era was closely linked to the rise of science in the
opponent. He would then guide the mechanical arm of the
Renaissance. Several scientists and thinkers took up ideas
automaton to make the desired counter-move. The Chess
that belonged to the atomist-materialist tradition. One such
Player hardly ever lost a game because the automaton was
thinker was Giulio Cesare Vanini (1585-1619), who set forth
often operated by several of the century’s greatest chess play-
a theory of evolution that predates that of Darwin by several
ers. In fact, the secret of the Chess Player was several times
centuries. For Vanini the entire world consists of a kind of
revealed in the press, but the public was so keen on being
primal substance which begins to mutate under the influ-
tricked that it simply ignored the common knowledge that
ence of the heat of the sun. Through this process of mutation
a man was hidden inside the automaton and assumed that
objects and creatures take form and finally man arises. This
here indeed was an automaton that had the gift of thought.
means that man himself is the object and temporary result
233
of evolution. In fact, Vanini claims that man has evolved from primate ancestors, as Darwin would later hold. Man’s mental life is a brain function. Mechanistic materialism subsequently became all the rage in the French Enlightenment, especially in the circle of the Encyclopédistes. Diderot developed a materialistic and mechanistic view of the world that was expressed in the remarkable dialogue Le Rêve de d’Alembert, written in 1769 but not published until 1830. In this dialogue Diderot has his characters expound an evolutionary view of the world that has several fascinating features. Movement is seen as inherent in matter. So Diderot does away with the dieu horlogier that the deists had kept handy to set the machinery of nature in motion. No such push was needed anymore for nature could now move of her own accord. Movement is in fact a process 234
of fermentation which causes dead matter to come to life and live matter to die. This means that all change takes place through internal processes that inhere in matter. Second, Diderot sees nature as one huge organism that constantly develops and engenders new life-forms. The key to this evolution can be found in the so-called monstra or monsters: the freaks of nature. Since nature is in constant change, some changes are bound to be unsuccessful and are discarded. That is how freaks of nature come about: they are nature’s failed experiments. Continual experimenting means that nature is in constant flux. Change is the rule, not constancy. No species, not even the human species, has an essence: ‘All things change into and out of each other; consequently all species... everything is a perpetual flux... Every animal is somewhat human; every mineral has something of the plant in it; every plant is partly animal. There is nothing distinct in nature’ (Diderot 2002: 103).
235
236
This means that mankind as we know it today is probably
l’individu’), which is simply ‘a need; and if one weren’t invited
merely a transitory phenomenon, a way-station in the con-
to do it by need, it would still be a pleasant thing’ (o.c. 173).
tinuing process of fermentation, and not something necessary
It is a small step from Diderot’s materialistic views to the
or final. Man is not the goal or purpose of nature, but a mere
idea of the human as an organic machine, a notion that was
phenomenon in it: a life-form that has emerged and will dis-
quite popular among the libertines and materialists. Pierre
appear again. ‘Who can say if fermentation and its products
Jean Georges Cabanis (1757-1808), for example, ‘summed up
have run their course? Who can say at which point in the suc-
his view of man in the words Les nerfs – voilà tout l’homme and
cession of animal life-forms we have arrived? Who can say if
declared that the brain secretes thought as the liver secretes
this deformed four foot high biped that is still called a man on
bile’ (Copleston 1960: 51). But the writer most readily associ-
the North pole, but who will surely loose this name as soon
ated with the idea of man as a machine is of course Julien
as his deformation advances, is not simply the image of a
Offray de La Mettrie (1709-1751), whose most famous work
passing species? Who can say whether everything isn’t about
is entitled L’Homme machine (1747). La Mettrie, who makes
to reduce itself to a great inert and immobile sediment? Who
explicit mention of Vaucanson in the course of his book, of-
can say how long this inertia will last? Who can say which
fers a radically materialistic view of the world (Israel 2001:
new race could emerge from such a huge mass of sensitive
704-709). He studied with the Dutch medical writer Hermann
living points?’ (o.c. 95-96) Such a materialistic view obviously
Boerhaave, whose books he translated and edited. The pub-
entails radical consequences for morality. Since the organism
lication of L’Homme machine caused so much uproar that La
is merely a collection of biological and chemical processes,
Mettrie had to flee France, seeking refuge in The Netherlands.
it is senseless to attach moral values or judgements to the
La Mettrie held that there was only one substance and that it
organism’s actions. Diderot makes this point in the third part
was governed by a force called “Nature”. This means that man
of the Rêve, where he applies this logic to sexuality. The organ-
is simply a link in a chain of mechanical causes and events.
ism has yearnings, desires, needs, drives. These are neither
This obviously leaves no room for a spiritual dimension. La
good nor bad in themselves: they are simply there. ‘So despite
Mettrie further claimed that religion is a political and social
the magnificent praise the fanatics have wasted on them,
device that is instituted for the benefit of the community and
and despite the civic laws that protect them, we will remove
to ensure social order. Many of these teachings were Spinozist
[chastity and temperance] from the catalogue of virtues. And
in origin. As we saw in Chapter One, Spinoza was at that time
we shall be agreed that, besides evil acts done on purpose,
considered to be one of the most evil thinkers in the history
there is nothing so childish, nothing so absurd, nothing so
of the world. For that reason, La Mettrie was recalcitrant to
detrimental, nothing so contemptible, nothing worse than
out himself as a follower of Spinoza. But as Romanticism ap-
those two rare qualities’ (o.c. 172). This rejection of morality
proached, Spinoza’s fortunes took a turn for the better. If Less-
famously leads Diderot to a defense of masturbation (‘plaisir à
ing could be a Spinozist, anyone could. And they would.
237
238
Mathesis Sexualis
the spirit to achieve its opposite. He applies reason to a cel-
The man whose work most clearly reflects the materialism
ebration of crime, debauchery, and licentiousness. Religious
of the eighteenth century is of course the divine Donatien
sentiments are mocked and the holy host is inserted into
Alphonse François, Marquis de Sade (1740-1814), who might
inappropriate orifices to defile it. Chastity is ravished all over
best be typified as the ‘Anti-Rousseau’ because he believed
the place. Man is an animal in search of pleasure and lust at
that cruelty was man’s deepest nature. Sade rejected the
the expense of others, who are objectified and treated like
humane pieties of both Christianity and optimistic Enlighten-
living automata to be used in the ritual of sexual gratification.
ment. He was an atheist and a blasphemer and subsequently
The cerebral nature of Sade’s work becomes manifest in the
rejected all moral principles based on anything other than
inordinate amount of talk his novels contain. Sade’s charac-
individual desire. He was a radical materialist for whom there
ters are forever discoursing on philosophy, on the pleasures
was no essential difference between humans, animals, and
of the flesh, or on some parodist version of Enlightenment
plants. In this he echoes La Mettrie, who followed his treatise
pursuits. They discourse on sex even as they are experiencing
on L’homme machine with a further treatise on L’homme plante
it. During sex, Sade’s characters speak prose. They continue
(1748). Philosophically, Sade’s work represents the triumph of
to speak prose as they reach orgasm. The diarrhetic flow of
mind over matter: it is the ultimate intellectualisation of the
elegantly phrased obscene language that pours forth from
body, which is merely used as a medium in which to inscribe
these characters is as constant and as abundant as the flow
a libertine philosophy of unbridled pleasure. In spite of its
of bodily fluids pouring forth from every excreting orifice.
obscene and scabrous explicitness Sade’s work is profoundly
Sex is not just an occasion for orgasm, but for philosophical
cerebral in its attempt to systematically organise bodily plea-
discourse on carnality. Sex and talk become interchangeable.
sure. His infamous unfinished novel Les cent-vingt journées
As Camille Paglia points out, ‘the excretory voiding of one
de Sodome (recovered in 1904 and published in 1931-35) was
person into the mouth of another is Dionysian monologue, a
written on a long roll of paper during his imprisonment in
pagan oratory’ (Paglia 1992: 239). Since there are no tradition-
the Bastille in 1785 (it appropriately resembles a roll of toilet
al values in this universe, and since the body is intellectu-
paper). This very fact proves to Camille Paglia that Sade’s
ally reduced to a pleasure automaton with sexual functions,
work was in the first instance a feat of mental defiance: ‘He
every fetish and every perversion or passion is wholeheart-
was trying, in prison, to reach the limits of the human sexual
edly embraced by Sade’s libertines. Sucking, fucking, coming,
imagination, and put it down on paper’ (Paglia 1995: 125).
swallowing, shitting, and pissing become intellectual activi-
But because Sade uses the freedom of the mind from the
ties. Everything about the body is sexualised and fetishised.
shackles of the material world to create a libertine paradise
Sade’s characters eat and defecate and eat each other’s excre-
of sexual crime his entire oeuvre ridicules the very Enlighten-
ment as if they lived in a miniature natural universe where
ment belief in progress and reason. He uses the freedom of
everything dissolves into everything. It is the world as flux
239
240
as dreamt by d’Alembert, with no clear boundaries between
society, economic exploitation, oppression of the masses.
species. It is blind nature or, as Freud would say, an infantile
The endless sexual combinations and inexhaustible inven-
sexuality that rejoices even in its own waste products (which
tion of ever new kinds of sexual acrobatics that fill the pages
are, after all, fertile manure). Nature is a continuum and the
of Sade’s novels read not like Descartes’ mathesis universalis
body ecstatic is a link in its chain. Sade shows us nature’s
but as a sarcastic mathesis sexualis, a sexual mathematics
true face. It has always been an Enlightenment belief that,
where enjoyment is calculated to maximum effect. This is
without civil society or a social contract, the world would
nowhere more clear than in the Sodome, which begins with
come to chaos, a jungle where the struggle for life reigns
an exposition of the novel’s architecture. Sade introduces
supreme. Sade accepts the struggle for life but does not see
his characters and describes how their exploits will be struc-
it as chaotic. If you do away with morality and social order,
tured. He explains the way the number of participants and
Sade claims, you are not left with anarchy or chaos, but with
the number of possible sexual positions that can be achieved
rigid hierarchy, a world in which the stronger kill the weaker
in twosomes or in group will be calculated to make sure that
and the powerful exploit the powerless. In this respect, Sade’s
everyone copulates with everyone in a series of sexual com-
work offers a devastating critique of economic liberalism and
binations and perversions. Furthermore, there is a sequence
capitalism, which are not modes of civilisation: they are or-
from day to day, with specific perversions reserved for spe-
ganised nature, the well-structured exploitation of the pow-
cific days. So if torture or scatology are on the menu for
erless by the powerful. The nature we find in Sade is what I
Monday one cannot indulge in them on Sunday or Tuesday.
would call “une nature claire et distincte,” a Cartesian parody of
It is sex like clockwork, as if one were proceeding through
the Rousseauist belief in the fundamental goodness of man
a sexualised version of Dante’s Inferno, starting with heavy
and nature. It is the genius of Sade that he rejects both Rous-
petting and ending with the bludgeoning of pregnant women.
seau’s naive romantic optimism and the equally preposterous
Sade calculates how many combinations of how many sexual
optimism of the rationalists. Instead, Sade makes us look at
positions are possible with the participants available and
and acknowledge the blind materiality of nature.
then draws up the graph of debauchery. The novel itself sim-
Reason is nature and nature is reason. This is in fact a very
ply puts the meat on this skeleton. And when the narration
old thought. It is at the heart of the christian belief that na-
breaks off because Sade couldn’t finish the work, he takes
ture is God’s creation, therefore has order and that science
recourse to a simple enumeration of the sexual activities that
amounts to reading the book of nature. What Sade rejects, is
still had to be executed. At some point he even introduces a
the underlying assumption that nature is beautiful and well-
note to himself pointing out an error in the numbering. This
ordered because it is divine creation. In reality it is no such
is the cerebral triumph of Sade’s work: it is pornography with
thing. Reason simply reproduces the power relationships
the detached coldness of science. It is Enlightenment logic
already present in nature in a more sophisticated way: class
turned against itself.
241
242
The structure of the Sodome is also a parody of Boccaccio’s
steady resolve towards its logical conclusion. As in the day-
Decamerone and Chaucer’s Canterbury Tales, those neatly or-
by-day increase of outrage in Sade’s novel, there is no need to
ganised epics of sexual bawdy. But sex is neither bawdy nor
hurry the pace for nobody is going anywhere anyway. There
fun in Sade, except for the torturers. There is no uplifting
is no sensationalism in Pasolini’s film as there is no pas-
sense of vitality, as in the delightful shenanigans of Boccac-
sion in Sade’s novel. We are simply locked in a self-sufficient
cio, there is only the sordid mechanism of jaded debauch-
universe where, as in mechanical nature, all moves steadily
ery that reaches ever deeper into the abyss of depravity to
towards its inevitable end in death. The logic of this universe
find yet another more extreme thrill that might trigger the
is the logic of the libertine who tries and tests the sexual
stumped senses. Sade’s characters go all the way, and then
automata at his disposal. The bodies of the victims are me-
some. Just like Boccaccio and Chaucer, Sade sets his story
chanical dolls to be toyed with, to be opened and scrutinised
in a secluded environment. Boccaccio’s narrators flee the
and to be submitted to any and every imaginable cruelty,
plague-ridden city of Florence and take refuge in a pleasant
similar to the way the wanton gods kill flies for their sport.
villa in the country. Chaucer’s merry company of pilgrims are
The detached frontality and theatricality of Pasolini’s film is
gathered in a coach on their way to Canterbury, a pilgrimage
a parody of the scientific principles at work in Sade’s novel. It
that, as Harold Bloom points out, was the fourteenth cen-
is a parody of absolute visibility: all that is obscene is brought
tury’s equivalent of our cruises (Bloom 2002: 107). Sade locks
on-scene, literally, as the victims are made to parade around
his libertines and their victims in a secluded castle on the top
in long-shot, filling the screen as if we were looking at a the-
of a mountain, where the outside world cannot reach them.
atre scene. All is exposed, either in word or in deed (and there
There, in sublime isolation, no rules apply but the rules of
is much talk in Pasolini’s film, as there is in Sade’s novel). It
excess. This excess is presented to our inner eye with all the
is a voyeuristic gorge-fest, a visceral indigestion of disinter-
clinical detachment of an operating theatre. It is here, in his
estedness that either nauseates or leaves us stone cold. It is
cold detachment, that Sade mocks modern science and its
sexual pleasure as the ultimate parody of the disinterested-
quest for total visibility. Autopsy is the visual logic at work in
ness of Kantian aesthetics: sexualised murder as a cold, cal-
Sade: a theatre of visibility that is the perverse double of the
culated, classicist spectacle. In Pasolini’s version it is Art Deco
belief that science could and should make visible all that lies
murder in bare halls of beige.
hidden in the human innards. Sade displays the body and its manifold functions. Pier Paolo Pasolini understood this very
Scientia Sexualis
well when he translated the cold and distanced theatricality
The spectacle of sex is the logic of porn as it is the logic of
of Sade to the screen for Saló (1975), his film version of the
voyeurism. Linda Williams has tried ‘to define film pornogra-
Sodome which is presented as a slow-paced, measured, and
phy minimally, and as neutrally as possible, as the visual (and
unhurried sequence of theatrical tableaux that moves with
sometimes aural) representation of living, moving bodies en-
243
244
gaged in explicit, usually unfaked, sexual acts with a primary
sible reason why so many (especially early) porn films engage
intent of arousing viewers’ (Williams 1999: 29-30). For the
in scenarios where women are overwhelmed, ravaged, or
viewer this material offers the promise of true knowledge.
even raped because in such scenes ‘the unwilling victim’s
Viewers watch pornography because they want to see the re-
eventual manifestations of pleasure are offered as the genre’s
ality of sexual pleasure in others. This is why Williams speaks
proof of a sincerity that under other conditions might seem
of a scientia sexualis, a sexual science: the intent is to know the
less sure’ (o.c. 50).
body and to penetrate its mysteries with the gaze. Williams
The voyeuristic elements in pornography are put to work in
explains that ‘I call the visual, hard-core knowledge-pleasure
an interesting way in several of the short films that photogra-
produced by the scientia sexualis a “frenzy of the visible”’ (o.c.
pher and filmmaker Richard Kern made in the 1980s as part
36), which is ‘a voyeurism structured as a coginitive urge’
of the Cinema of Transgression movement. Kern has built a
(o.c. 48). Porn strives to ‘maximum visibility’ (ibid.) and ‘ob-
career on his (male heterosexual) voyeurism and usually in-
sessively seeks knowledge, through a voyeuristic record of
vited friends and hangers-on to perform some sexual fantasy
confessional, involuntary paroxysm, of the “thing” itself’ (o.c.
in front of his camera. This resulted in collage-films such as
49). The involuntary aspect is both the most crucial and the
Submit To Me (1985) and Submit To Me Now (1987) and a series
most problematic aspect or porn, especially in its most com-
of brief films of female stripping routines. As the titles of the
mon form: the pornographic film aimed at the heterosexual
films suggest, there is an element of dominance in Kern’s
male. The involuntary aspect is crucial because it is only
films. The voyeur, especially if he is looking at a person with-
when action becomes involuntary that we can have any kind
out himself being perceived, is in a dominant position: he is
of assurance that what we are seeing is real. In the moment
gaining intimate knowledge of another body. In Kern’s films
of orgasm, there is no holding back: for a brief moment, we
this dominating aspect is stressed by the often sadomas-
lose control over our body and are surrendered to its spasms.
ochistic routines the performers engage in and by the bird’s-
To be in orgasm is to exist in an involuntary mode. This is
eye point of view that Kern himself often uses to film their
an instance of certified reality: it cannot be faked. Except, of
performances. But voyeurism also entails a distancing: the
course, by women, who apparently fake orgasm all the time
looking device, whether it is a camera, binoculars, or a key-
to spare their spouses’ feelings. But in porn it is quite impos-
hole, keeps the desired object at a distance. This is a defence
sible to tell whether a woman, and especially a professional
mechanism, allowing the voyeur to look at the world without
porn actress, is actually experiencing orgasm or merely fak-
having to partake in it. Kern has acknowledged that the voy-
ing one. This problem does not pose itself in relation to the
euristic element in his films allows him to maintain a safe
male body, where the penis is either erect/aroused or not and
distance: ‘if there’s something I want to do and I’m nervous
where orgasm is a visible event through ejaculation. Williams
about doing it, I’ll turn on the camera and do it in front of the
suggests that the impenetrability of the female body is a pos-
camera and then it’s okay’ (Sargeant 1995: 101). The only risk
245
246
involved for the voyeur is being caught more or less literally
prise us since voyeurism is all about auto-eroticism: it is a fe-
with his pants down. This risk is in itself an exhibitionistic
tish that uses the person looked at as a canvas on which the
thrill that seems to be part and parcel of a voyeur’s delight.
voyeur can project all his fantasies. Because no real contact
But such exhibitionism is conspicuously absent in voyeuristic
is ever made, the person looked at never becomes a specific
cinema, where the performers know they are being filmed
individual and can therefore never disappoint the fantasies
and the filmmaker cannot get “caught” red-handed, or at
projected onto him or her. This way voyeurism avoids the
least with cum on his fingers. In two films, however, Kern
disappointment of mere flesh, as when a body desired from
has dramatised his role as voyeur. The first is The Evil Camera-
afar turns out, upon closer inspection, to have flaws, a nasty
man (1987-1990). The title refers to Kern himself, sneaking
body odour, a foul breath, or another unpleasant feature that
up on his subjects and cinematically stealing their private
renders it at once undesirable. The voyeur’s fantasy is never
moments. The evil in the cameraman is the spectre of the
shattered and therefore it can go on indefinitely. In this sense
male gaze, objectifying and visually raping all females in
voyeurism is probably the sexual fetish closest to the arts
sight, making Victims of them all. The first part of the film
because it seems to exemplify Kant’s principle of purposive-
clearly plays on this violence and shows several aggressive
ness without purpose: as long as the voyeur is looking, his
sexual rituals. The second part of the film was made after an
desire goes on and on, turning upon itself, feeding off itself. It
interval of several years and is markedly different in tone:
is not unusual for the confirmed voyeur to prefer voyeurism
it is more ironic and also shows Kern himself displaying his
to actual sex. As Kern confides, ‘the best part of anything is
penis and a swastika drawn on his stomach. The second film
watching’ (o.c. 102). And the best part of watching is the illu-
to dramatise Kern’s voyeurism is My Nightmare (1993), which
sion of intimate knowledge obtained from watching people
is literally presented as a masturbatory fantasy in which Kern
who do not know they are being watched and who therefore
is overpowered by sexually aggressive women. The explicit
have no reason to fake their behaviour. To observe people in
dream sequences are interrupted by shots of Kern lying on
private without them knowing you are watching is to see
his bed naked and masturbating. There is something decid-
them as they really are. One is witness to private gestures
edly auto-erotic about these scenes. There are several full
and intimate movements that seem to contain traces of what
shots of his body, but mostly Kern focuses on his penis, film-
that person is really like. It suggests deeper, more intimate
ing it with the camera positioned at his knees so that his
knowledge. This, in essence, is also the illusion that porn
body appears extremely foreshortened and his penis fills the
tries to create. Speaking of his own use of pornographic vid-
screen. When he reaches orgasm, Kern again fills the screen
eos, Kern comments that ‘you can use the same tape over
with his penis, but now filmed from the chest, so that his
and over, and you have to develop relationships with people
sperm shoots up at the lens of the camera.
in the movie... that’s the whole thing. I think the way most
The auto-erotic elements in this short film should not sur-
people watch is, you scan the entire movie to find the people
247
248
that appeal to you and the action that appeals to you and you
in the copious couplings and orgasms put on display) it can-
watch these scenes over and over. [...] It’s like having little
not really deliver for what is shown always remains an illu-
relationships’ (o.c. 116).
sion. The same thing occurs in voyeurism. The voyeur can
The very idea that you might develop a relationship with a
only maintain his erotic haze by keeping the desired object
person in a pornographic movie presupposes that some kind
at bay: he looks from a distance. But the voyeur, very much
of intimacy is involved (despite the fact that pornographic
like the spectator of porn, has never seen enough or has never
films are obviously about performance). But I think that Kern
seen what he really wanted to see. Therefore there is always
might be too idiosyncratic in his description of the uses of
the promise (in porn) or the possibility (in voyeurism) of
pornography. One of the cardinal features of the genre is
more knowledge the next time. A voyeur may have watched his
its endless trotting out of new and fresh faces. Porn careers
neighbour a hundred times, but every day there will be the
rarely last longer than several years, except where the really
anticipation that maybe today he will see something hitherto
big stars are concerned. Porn faces get used up and discarded
unseen that will reveal “it” truly and fully for the first time.
real fast. The reason for this seems obvious: there are limits
Obviously, “it” never occurs. And even if something like “it”
to the amount of times you can stage the revelation of the
does occur, as in an unexpected event that offers unusual in-
real in the same body. But paradoxically the fact that the real
sight in the object’s privacy, this seeing of something special
is staged is also the key to the success of the genre because
will not quench the desire to see “it” but will simply make the
the staged nature of its content is what makes us come back
voyeur thirst for more. This is why voyeurism and pornogra-
for more. This calls for an explanation. Porn is probably one
phy are so addictive.
of the most predictable genres about. Usually the spectator
The mechanism of non-fulfilment that is at work in voyeur-
knows exactly what he is going to get. Often the number of
ism and pornography is a structural component of the so-
scenes or sexual encounters is announced on the packaging
called soft-sex film: erotic films in which erotic action is not
of the film, so that the viewer knows that the fourth or fifth
real but only suggested. This genre is built on the public’s
encounter is the point for orgasm because no more sex will
desire to be led on. If the public did not want to know that
be forthcoming after that. But given that porn can never re-
the Automaton Chess Player did not really play on its own
ally give us a true revelation of the real thing, especially in
but was operated by a man inside the box, then the public
the female body, and given that the real thing in a male body
flocking to see soft-sex films wilfully overlooks the certain
(ejaculation) can only ever be watched and never experienced
knowledge that they will yet again not see the real thing
in the body itself, porn has the mechanism of disillusionment
in the film they are about to see. The entire business of the
built into it. Porn promises the gratification of the real yet
erotic (as opposed to explicit pornographic) film is built on
cannot deliver. Even if it tries to deliver by giving us plenty
the principle of the tease: you did not get to see it today, but
of truth to gape at (and some porn films are very generous
come again tomorrow and perhaps you will see it then. Of
249
250
course, you are not going to see it tomorrow either, but the
Pleasure Machines
public apparently likes to be lead on. It seems unpersuasive
There is a heroics at work in pornography. The performers
to me to condemn this tease as a ploy to con the public out
in these films descend into the maelstrom of material life:
of their money. People who go and see erotic films (or went
the sex performer faces the deep material truths about our
to see them, for the paying public for cinematic showings of
physical bodies and is not afraid of being reduced to them.
erotic films is very much a phenomenon that died in the mid-
To explain this, we might refer to medical textbooks, where
1980s, when video technology made cinematic screenings of
the naked material facts of the human body and its physi-
erotic and pornographic films redundant) know exactly what
cal functions are displayed. This is not attractive, except for
they are in for and it might be argued that the tease that is
those for whom the abject is a particular sexual fetish. Just
never fulfilled works for them in the same way that the voy-
like the pictures and graphs in such manuals, the sex per-
eur and the spectator of porn are constantly looking forward
former reduces his or her body to the pipes and tubes, the
towards a more intimate knowledge. I suggest that this is an-
valves and ligaments that constitute it. But this reduction
other instance of the Kantian idea of purposiveness without
to matter is deliberate. The medical manual shows the body
purpose: more than anything else, we want to keep desire,
reduced to its material facts despite itself. The sex performer
which is the felt experience of the body physical in a state of
chooses to display his body as material fact, and to do this
sensual alertness, going. To perpetuate this experience by any
he or she must transcend materiality: the body is trained to
and all means possible is one of the leading pursuits in hu-
look fit, it is often decorated (with make-up, with seductive
man life. The one thing we sometimes want more than to be
clothes that can be shed, with elaborate tattoos), a sexual
fulfilled, is to desire. Or, as legendary gay porn director Fred
sequence, whether performed for the camera or on stage, is
Halsted once said about his sex-life, ‘coming is not the point.
scripted, lighted, and perceived from different angles. The
The point is revelation – the why. Orgasm is fun, but you can
experience of the sexual body on display is an aesthetic
do that anytime, anywhere. I am not interested in orgasms. I
construct. The body thus displayed is indeed presented to
am interested in me. I can jack off better than I can have sex
resemble an automaton, but unlike an actual automaton it
with anybody. Celibacy is great. I like it. It is more pure, more
is not soulless, dead, or mechanical. It has a soul. It wills. It
strong, more real than sex’ (Jones 2008: 27). This, in essence,
even wills its reduction to matter. Its objectification, which
is the dual mechanism of voyeurism and narcissism at work
feminists object to, is knowingly engaged in. The performer
in pornography: the indefinitely extended dialogue of the
descends into materiality.
aroused with himself. It is purposiveness without purpose
This is the illusion at the heart of pornography, striptease,
with a vengeance: all that one desires is to maintain desire,
and prostitution: the allure of the performance (for even
like an engine running stationary, not going anywhere, but
prostitution is a performance: the prostitute must incarnate
burning fuel nevertheless.
the client’s fantasies) lies in the performer’s ability to present
251
252
him- or herself as a human android, a human toy. But in doing
phy (or the masochist in total submission) is in fact trying to
this, the performer does not become a victim or a soulless
symbolically resemble just such a digestive tract; a human
object. On the contrary, the performer gains enormous power
tube in which to insert things. Many porn films include im-
for he or she is seen as inhabiting a realm most of us would
ages of a man or woman on all fours who is being penetrated
not care or dare inhabit, except in fantasy: the realm of sheer
from behind while also giving a blow job. Seen from the side,
physicality. Since the performance creates the illusion of a
this can create a back-and-forth motion: as the penis glides
body existing in brutal physicality, physical reduction is not
into the mouth, the backside penis glides out of the ass or
something that befalls the performer, but something that the
vagina; and vice versa: when the body glides over the penis
performer actively stages as an illusion, an act, a creation.
in the back, the other penis is pulled out of the mouth. This
And the illusion created is that of bodily regression. The body
way, the body in the middle can be seen as if it were glid-
is presented as reduced to its fundamental status of passage-
ing back and forth on a string or a pole that penetrates the
way for matter. It is a machine or organism where something
body from ass to mouth. Something similar can be seen in
enters on one end and exits again on the other end. This is
an iconic image from the cult film Cannibal Holocaust (Rug-
almost literally a regression to the embryonic stage. In one
gero Deodato, 1979) in which a woman has been pierced on a
of its earliest stages, the human embryo consists of three
vertical pole. The pole enters her from behind and reappears
primary germ layers that lie on top of each other ‘like a three-
from her mouth. Presumably, she will slowly slide down the
layered cellular pancake’ (Marieb and Hoehn 2010: 141). The
pole until she touches the ground. In many ways, this is the
most superficial of these is the ectoderm, the middle is the
ultimate objectification of the human body, being reduced to
mesoderm, and the third is the endoderm. Out of these three
a tube without feelings or thoughts. But obviously, in sexual
layers all organs will develop. This process begins with the
situations this regression is being enacted as a source of
flat three-layered embryo being folded into a tube. The ecto-
pleasure. The sex performer creates an illusion of being an
derm then becomes the outside of the tube, the endoderm
automaton, whereas the masochist revels in the humiliation
lines the inside of the tube. The tube of the endoderm is
of being treated as nothing more than a digestive tract, some-
called the primitive gut. At about four weeks, it extends from
thing you can plug, fill, and empty at will. We should also not
one end of the small embryo to the other. The top end will
underestimate the great liberating power that can be found
develop into the mouth, the bottom end will become the anal
in such theatre of physicality. We live in a world in which
opening. The tube in-between will develop into the digestive
almost superhuman demands are being made on our bodies
tract, including oesophagus, stomach, and bowels (o.c. 1084-
and minds. We are exposed to inordinate amounts of stress.
1085).
For those who can stomach it, there is undoubtedly a terrific
In presenting himself as a machine for sex or as a receptacle
sense of relief to be found in the experience of becoming, for
for semen or other bodily fluids, the performer in pornogra-
the duration of a sexual ritual, mere body, mere tube, mere
253
254
sperm spittoon. To be subjected and annihilated into sexual
has been suspended from a crane for airborne copulation.
nothingness is the dark side of nirvana. It’s emptiness laced
One of the most notorious instances of machine sex is J.G.
with pheromones.
Ballard’s novel Crash (1973), about people who derive erotic
The human body as organic machine allows of many modifi-
pleasure from car-wrecks (in 1970 Ballard had also organised
cations. Prostheses can be added to it, from the strap-on dil-
an exhibition of crashed cars). And in Dean R. Koontz’s novel
do for everyday use to the electronic extensions attached to
Demon Seed (1973) a computer accomplishes sexual congress
Stelarc’s body. But it is also possible to create machines that
between human and machine when it uses its control over
act upon the body, almost as if they were partners in the sex-
the computer system that governs a house to imprison and
ual game. The photographer Timothy Archibald has produced
rape the woman who lives there and impregnate her with its
a volume of portraits of ordinary people who are ‘reworking
offspring.
domestic hardware into complex sex machines’ (Archibald
But the first place to look for sexual machines and the
2005: 6). Household appliances, steel boxes, electric drills, and
sexual attraction of metal, chrome, and grease, is probably
even a dentist’s chair are transformed into sexual automa-
the world of gay SM films, whether they be the avant-porn
tons designed to provide pleasure. Although several of these
of Fred Halsted’s Sex Garage (1972), where a man reportedly
inventions have been successfully marketed, most originated
fucks the exhaust pipe of his motorcycle (Stevenson 2002:
as devices created with a specific body in mind, usually the
113), or Kenneth Anger’s seminal film Scorpio Rising (1963),
body of a lover or spouse. Making the machine started out as
which evokes a stylised vision of the aggressive eroticism of
a labour of love, both in the sense that it was a sexual gift for
motorcyclists and the gleaming fetishism of their customised
a loved-one and in the sense that it was created with great
bikes. Scorpio Rising is a four-part film that consist of thirteen
dedication in the privacy of their own home, without any
sections linked to pop songs. The film combines new mate-
prior intention of marketing the object. The idea of the ma-
rial shot by Anger with stock footage and excerpts from older
chine as a pleasure-inducing extension of the body is taken
films, which are used, along with the pop songs, as ironic
to the limit in French porn director John Love’s film Chantier
commentary on the action of the film. P. Adams Sitney has
interdit au public (1999), which shows the sexual goings on at
called Scorpio Rising ‘a mythographic film. It self-consciously
a construction site, including a woman being fucked by an
creates its own myth of the motorcyclist’ (Sitney 2002: 106).
electrically powered drill mounted on a small fork-lift truck
The motorcyclist Scorpio presents himself as a kind of pagan
(the drill is wearing a condom for safety). Similarly, Matthew
demon god who proclaims his godhead in a homosexual orgy
Barney has more than once used machinery in sexual con-
of sadomasochistic ritual, including the humiliation of the
structions, notably in his segment for the portmanteau film
male body (by, among other things, smearing hot mustard on
Destricted (2006), which shows a naked man rubbing his hard
exposed genitals) and the desecration of an altar by pissing
dick against the spinning innards of a giant bulldozer that
in a helmet and elevating it as if it were a chalice. At the end
255
256
of the film Scorpio demands the sacrifice of a young motor-
films are more akin to the experimental cinema of the under-
cyclist who is killed in a race. Throughout the film Anger uses
ground than to commercial porn. Where later porn is often
low-key lighting that creates ‘a lush pastel view of motorcycle
filmed in studio-built sets that are crisp and clean, these
cushions, lights, and portions of chrome with stars of light
early films were filmed on location with actors who actu-
reflecting off them’ (o.c. 104). Significant parts of the film are
ally had dirty feet from walking barefoot on the dirty floors.
spent looking at the ‘unveiling, greasing, shining, and com-
Sex scenes were filmed in actual urinals, not on studio sets.
pleting of motorcycles’ (ibid.). But the male bodies in the film
The sex acts in such early films often have the intensity of
are equally customised. We observe them getting dressed in
real abandon. They thrive on the male body as a customised
a ritual that is almost equivalent to the finishing of the bikes.
organic sex machine. The same gritty and realistic approach
As an exercise in highly charged erotic imagery, the film jux-
to sex was also visible in the early shorts produced by Falcon
taposes ‘slow, sensuous, vertical pans down the toned, rip-
Studios. Films like Weekend Lockup (1976), starring gay porn
pling chests, navels and crotches of the Brooklyn biker-gang
legend Al Parker, Ramcharger (1978), or Biker’s Liberty (1982), to
boys as they ceremonially deck their bodies with leather and
name but a few, have a sweaty intensity. They are cinematic
chains’ with ‘horizontal pans acres the garage floor, motor-
miniatures, capsules of living testosterone, executed with
cycles, tools and spare parts’ (Hutchison 2004: 133).
total focus on the body as fetish-object. Asked in an interview
This heady atmosphere of grease and chrome made its way
how he would describe himself in a personal ad, director Fred
into some of the most interesting gay porn of the 1970s. For
Halsted replied: ‘Five feet nine and a half, sixteen-inch biceps,
Fred Halsted there was never any question that his films
under ten inches, thirty-three years old, smooth skin. Into
were works of art and not merely porn. ‘Up to that time,
scat, S&M, bondage, water sports, wrestling, Levi’s, jockstraps,
porno was always considered something you made money off
motorcycles, dirty socks, boots, leather, amyl nitrate, belts,
of, but never a thing you were proud of, something you did
whips, masks’ (Jones 2008: 26). If you’re talking about the
secretly. Well, I just barged into fucking New York and said,
body as a customised sex machine, this is the package.
“This is film, a work of art.” It also happened to be hard-core
In later porn, this gritty approach would often deteriorate
gay porno. A sadomasochistic, fistfucking faggot film, but that
into a pose, a game of dressing up and playing at thugs.
is not the point. No one had ever done this before with a sex
Halsted himself remarks that ‘almost all gays are masoch-
film. To me sex is the most viable area of human interest, it
ists, if not overtly, at least subliminally’ (Jones 2008: 26). This
is the most important area, so I was proud of what I was do-
is maybe a reason why the straight thug, or rough trade
ing’ (Jones 2008: 27). Besides Halsted’s films, there was also
(straight men who have sex with other men for money), are
the work of Joe Gage, who made the famous trilogy Kansas
so much part of gay lore. If real masculinity is hard to find in
City Trucking Co. (1975), El Paso Wrecking Corp. (1978), and LA
the gay community, the aggressive straight fucker becomes
Tool & Die (1979). In the way they are filmed and edited these
an object of attraction. Whether it is rape by a gang of sailors,
257
as in Kenneth Anger’s seminal underground film Fireworks
It’s like Dr Frank N. Furter in The Rocky Horror Picture Show, in-
(1947), or assault by skinheads or scally lads, as in a host of
viting us all to come up to the lab and see what’s on the slab.
recent porn films from British production company Triga,
In the case of the blood-red fisting scene in Deviant Detours
your local beer-heaving thug is a gay sex icon. It is interest-
the menu reads much like a Matthew Barney performance.
ing that recent porn films have attempted to return to the
The performers in such films are themselves objets d’art: lean
style of early porn, with heavier action and grittier settings.
and muscular men, intricately tattooed, going about their
A case in point are the films produced by Triga in the United
brutal business with the fearful symmetry of a tyger in heat.
Kingdom and by Cazzo in Germany. Triga’s trilogy of Lost In-
It is obvious that the worlds of porn and performance do
nocence films (2007), for example, directed by Maxwell Barber,
meat somewhere in the middle ground between a good fuck
sometimes seems like a series of performance pieces for star
at The Anvil and a mental fuck at the MoMA.
Ashley Ryder, whose ass can take anything, turning the performer’s body into a receptacle for any manner of penetrative
258
Bodice Rest And Motion
object or organ. Two other examples of what ambitious porn
No artist ever wanted to be a machine more than Andy War-
can look like are Cazzo’s films Original Options (2003) and Devi-
hol did. In a famous interview with G.R. Swenson for the
ant Detours (2003), both directed by Hans Peter Hagen. These
November, 1963 issue of ARTnews Warhol famously said that
films, shot in crystal clear high definition digital video, use a
‘I want to be a machine, and I feel that whatever I do and do
minimal story to present a series of sexual encounters that
machine-like is what I want to do’ (Goldsmith 2004: 18). In
involve serious edge-play. In Original Options a man is beaten
the same interview he also suggested that ‘everybody should
up by skinheads (the beating is quite real, although staged
be a machine’. And being a machine is the same as ‘linking
for the camera) and another is hung upside down with a
things’ because ‘you do the same thing every time. You do
gas mask on his face and lowered into a tank of water. Devi-
it over and over again’ (o.c. 16). The idea of the human body,
ant Detours contains a bizarre scene featuring two heavily
the artist’s body, as a machine for the production of art is the
tattooed men in white butcher’s aprons and boots. One of
prime metaphor for Warhol’s practice. He was, after all, the
them is hacking meat while the other is fisting another man.
artist who turned his studio into a Factory, cranking out art
But instead of using grease to make a smooth entry into
in the steady flow of a conveyor belt. Several commentators
the man’s rectum, he uses a red goo that literally makes the
on Warhol’s work have linked this preoccupation with the
whole affair look like a bloody mess. The link between animal
mechanical to Warhol’s many traumas. Andy Warhol was a
and human meat being manhandled by impressive-looking
profoundly injured man who spent most of his life and not a
bastards makes clear that the attraction of this kind of porn-
little of his art trying to cope with the traumas the world had
as-performance relies to a large extent on the presentation
bestowed upon him. Warhol’s entire life and art, the way he
of human flesh as an object for penetration and pummelling.
made them and the style he devised for them, are an attempt
259
260
to cope with the trauma of living. But that does not mean
because it causes uncontrollable spasms in the body. It also
that Warhol’s work is in any way self-expressive. Rather,
causes the pigmentation of the skin to change, which possi-
his work is an extended philosophical quest for insight into
bly explains Warhol’s extremely pale complexion. The severe
embodiment, which is his prime subject as an artist. Warhol
bouts of shaking terrified the young child: he feared he would
spent a lifetime coming to terms with the fact that he had a
never regain control over his body. Wayne Koestenbaum has
body. His work is the symbolic expression of this quest, it is
persuasively argued that Warhol’s mature desire to be a ma-
the text of his findings. What does it mean to have a body?
chine was a response to the trauma of Saint Vitus Dance: to
What does it mean to exist in time? These are the questions
be a machine is to be automated. Just like Warhol’s shaking
that troubled Warhol. But Warhol’s work cannot be reduced
body, the machine operates on its own. But uncontrollable
to the life, the neuroses, or the anxieties that fuelled it. Four
shaking was not the only humiliation Warhol had to suffer.
topics are at the heart of Warhol’s work: body, sex, time, and
Julia, his mother, who would later come to live with him, was
death, and they are intrinsically linked to each other. War-
an immigrant from Eastern Europe who had a firm belief
hol’s favoured way of dealing with them was through voyeur-
that enemas were a certain cure for just about everything.
ism, the art of looking; or rather: the art of gazing. A voyeur
So she administered enemas to the young Andy, making the
maintains a safe distance from the object of his desire, push-
intestines and their excretory function a point of obsession
ing fulfilment of desire, and hence physical gratification,
for the boy. At school, his shaking hand caused the other stu-
forward in time. Voyeurism is a disembodied sexuality: it
dents to laugh at him and Warhol refused to go back. When
thrives on not reaching climax. It keeps the yearning body in
he seemed cured of the disease, Warhol still didn’t want to go
suspension.
back. When he was forcefully dragged to school, the boy had
This yearning body, at least in Warhol’s case, was riddled with
a nervous breakdown and was bedridden for four weeks.
trauma. Warhol’s biographers (David Bockris, David Bourdon,
His time in bed was made more pleasurable by Julia, who
and Wayne Koestenbaum chief among them) have done a
brought him magazines to read with pictures of movie stars.
good job of assembling and analysing the sad story of Warhol
Warhol wanted to be Shirley Temple and imagined having sex
the youthful body, so we need do little more than refer to
with Popeye. But then, when he was thirteen, Warhol’s father
their insights and check the list of physical humiliations that
died after a long illness. Andrew Warhola senior had suffered
would haunt Warhol his entire life. At the age of six, young
jaundice for which he had had his gallbladder removed. He
Andrew Warhola (he would drop the a when he became a
fell ill again after drinking soiled water (ironically, Andy War-
professional artist) got scarlet fever, which inflames the nose
hol would die after routine gallbladder surgery in 1987). The
and mouth. It is possible that this inflamation caused the
body was laid out in a coffin in the house and Warhol refused
disfigurement of his nose. When he was eight, Warhol fell ill
to go see his dead father. He was so terrified he hid under
with Saint Vitus Dance, a terrifying affliction for the sufferer
the bed and went to stay with a friend. But the trauma of
261
262
his father’s death would instill in the young artist a lifelong
sessed with his body and his image. The two are closely
obsession with motionlessness and death. The final trauma
linked, because one’s image is how one chooses to present
came when Andy was sixteen. Julia was diagnosed with colon
oneself to the world. It is through our physical bodies that
cancer. To save her life a colostomy was performed, a proce-
we are present in the world. The body physical is the car-
dure that was then still experimental and in which part of
rier of both our inner self and our image. Warhol’s response
the intestines was removed and replaced with a bag outside
to his many traumas was to treat the outward appearance
the body. Henceforth, Julia would carry her insides on the
of his body like a screen, something to hide behind. In time,
outside. It is impossible to comprehend what this dramatic
the body itself would become screened by further screens,
change in his mother’s physiology did to the young Warhol,
usually mechanical in nature. These layers of protective
but one thing is clear: intestines, and the threat of having
coating became especially prolific after the Solanas shoot-
them spill uncontrollably out of the body, would occupy him
ing, when Warhol felt extremely vulnerable. One of Warhol’s
for the rest of his life and would become a central element in
most famous screens was the wig (or the long series of wigs)
his work. And again, ironically, Warhol would somehow suffer
he started to wear to hide the fact that he started balding
through a similar affliction as his mother. If Warhol’s death
at a very young age (another instance of his body escaping
mimicked his father’s gallbladder ailment, then Warhol’s
control). As his reputation grew, Warhol exploited his image
first death mimicked his mother’s scarred body. Obviously,
as a fey waif by dressing up in a thrift shop style. He affected
Warhol’s first death refers to Monday June 3, 1968, when Val-
his speech and deliberately cultivated a more feminine way
erie Solanas shot Warhol. When he arrived in the emergency
of walking and behaving. He tried to disappear behind his
room, Warhol was declared dead. Only when the doctors
masks. But from behind the screen, Warhol looked at the
were informed of the fact that he was rich and famous did
world with a keen and often cold eye. In Stargazer (1971),
they spend an hour bringing him back to life. But Warhol
the first serious study of Warhol’s film work and still one of
would carry the scars of Valerie’s attack for the rest of his life,
the best and most insightful books about the artist, Stephen
both inside and outside. The bullet had pierced just about
Koch has argued that Warhol is a classic example of what
every vital organ in Warhol’s body. The surgeons had to open
Baudelaire called the dandy. ‘The dandy refuses to be moved,’
up his chest and sow it closed again. Warhol’s body was now
Koch writes, ‘he will not respond’ (Koch 1991: 114). This is
permanently scarred, and just like his mother he had had his
Warhol’s affected coldness, his seeming lack of emotional
insides taken out to save him. Humiliatingly, he would have
involvement. ‘The passions are mute but immanent within
to wear a corset for the rest of his life to keep his intestines
him’ (ibid.): obviously, Warhol did have feelings; in fact, he
in place. Warhol’s body had become a container of insides
was almost pathologically sensitive to his surroundings,
about to spill, forever under threat of falling apart.
to people, and to outward impulses. That is why he had to
It should come as no surprise, then, that Warhol was ob-
screen this input out and hide behind a mask of distanced
263
264
coldness. The image that Warhol created for himself ‘looks
geous Italian American, to assist him in the process. Warhol
isolated and luminous, an image on the silver screen. But
would screen pictures over a prepared canvas on which the
there is no image of the self that does not entail – invisibly,
background colours had already been applied. This means
perhaps, out of frame – the image of others. And the dandy’s
that the image often does not fit the screened picture. This is
narcissistic isolation is haunted by the spectre of others’ (o.c.
again ironic, for this supposedly mechanical way of making
114-115). The dandy is mute and betrays no need, no desire,
paintings has produced hundreds of canvases that superfi-
no sentiment. ‘Need is humiliation,‘ Koch explains, ‘it is loss
cially look alike but no two of which are identical. His works
of self; it is death’ (o.c. 119). This is what Warhol feared most:
are just as unique as every painting of a more traditional art-
to lose control of his self again, like a child surrendered to the
ist; it’s just that the uniqueness is less obvious. As the 1960s
spasms of Saint Vitus Dance. But inside this muted exterior
progressed, other machines were placed between Warhol and
lived a voracious animal, a man who fed on those around
the world, first and foremost the camera he bought in 1962
him. Warhol surrounded himself with weirdos, artists, per-
to start making films. In 1964 he added the tape-recorder he
formers, and hangers-on through whom he lived vicariously.
used, among other things, to tape his telephone conversa-
He observed them and urged them on as they performed
tions and to write his novel a: a novel (1965), which is the
the many physical feats that Warhol did not dare engage in
transcript of a twenty-four hour monologue by Ondine, one
himself: anonymous sex, dirty sex, drugtaking, self-exposure.
of Warhol’s greatest superstars. Finally, after he had been
In this sense, Warhol’s entourage was a physical extension
shot, the Polaroid camera became one of Warhol’s most trust-
of himself. It was part of his world and hence part of who he
ed companions. Flashing away at everyone and everything
was. Warhol was the sun around whom the entire universe
and thrusting the microphone of his tape-recorder into other
of his entourage evolved. He was, as Stephen Koch has very
people’s faces Warhol maintained a safe distance and man-
aptly described him, ‘a star who is in fact a stargazer’ (o.c.
aged to screen himself out. A muted presence, he succeeded
122).
to get others to open up and expose themselves to his cam-
To eliminate his body physical Warhol replaced many of
era/microphone while he himself lingered in the shadows.
its functions with machinery. The most obvious example is
The star as stargazer is a black hole: it never shows itself but
the Factory, a studio for industrial art production where, as
sucks in everything around it.
he explained, ‘we’re turning out a painting every day and a
As Wayne Koestenbaum argues, Warhol’s preoccupation with
sculpture every day and a movie every day’ (Goldsmith 2004:
the body is also of central concern to his most important
89). By silkscreening his works, Warhol deliberately sought to
work as a painter. Consider his famous images of Campbell’s
make his work less personal, taking out the trace of the hand
soup cans. There are many ways to read these paintings,
of the artist. Ironically, the silkscreening process is actually
although David Bourdon has suggested that they may have
very laborious and Warhol hired Gerard Malanga, a gor-
been nothing more than a desperate attempt by the artist
265
266
to do something so outrageous that the artworld would be
the world, time is stopped and the chemical balance of the
forced to take notice of him (Bourdon 1989: 90). If we look for
food remains unchanged. Soup cans are bodies in temporal
meaning in these works, as we should with all works of art,
suspension.
then it certainly seems that these are pastiches of a tradi-
Stopping time in the body is tantamount to trying to cheat
tional theme: the Baroque still lives of vegetables and other
death, another of Warhol’s major concerns. Death is every-
food, spread out on a counter in rich and elaborate Dutch
where in Warhol, who is probably one of the most morbid
paintings. Warhol’s soup cans are also such a banquet, but
of the Romantics. One of his most iconic series of images
customised and condensed in a tin can. The artist is playing
is that of Marilyn Monroe, the first of which, Gold Marilyn
a joke on art history. Also, the images are not identical. When
(1962), was produced within days of the star’s death on
Warhol first exhibited the series of soup cans, every flavour
August 5, 1962. This canvas, which shows a small image of
of the Campbell’s brand was represented. Warhol would also
Marilyn silkscreened onto a gold canvas, was Warhol’s first
paint soup cans with torn labels, or crushed and destroyed
silkscreen. The gold ground recalls his youth: Warhol grew
cans. Big Torn Campbell’s Soup Can (Vegetable Beef) and Big Torn
up in a Greek-Orthodox church community where icons with
Campbell’s Soup Can (Pepper Pot) (both 1962) are like memento
gold ground were very common. Warhol also used gold in his
mori, reminders of the hurtability of the body. For that is
gorgeous A Gold Book (1957) with drawings of street boys that
what they most conspicuously are: bodies. The soup cans are
have ‘a rare, contemplative intensity’ (Bastian 1996: 25). After
containers holding intestines. In fact, they hold the mixed
Gold Marilyn, many more Marilyns would follow, along with
foodstuffs of soup, which often looks like half digested food,
a series of so-called Death and Disaster Paintings. Violent
the stuff one finds in the stomach. The soup can contains this
death, whether by food poisoning (Tunafish Disaster, 1963),
stuff in the same way that Julia’s and Warhol’s bodies contain
car crash (a whole series, in various hues, in 1963), race riot
intestines. And just like Julia’s and Warhol’s bodies, the inner
(for example, Red Race Riot, 1963) or suicide (several Suicides
stuff can fall out if the can is crushed or opened. In the 1970s
of 1963), obsessed Warhol. Hal Foster has called Warhol’s
Warhol would start another collection of cans with his time
method in these works “traumatic realism”: an attempt to
capsules: hundreds of cilinder-shaped boxes in which he kept
cope with a world experienced as traumatic. In these works
all manner of objects, from issues of magazines over film
Warhol is trying to understand and master death. Like many
tickets and unopened mail to film scripts and personal ob-
of his silkscreens, the Death and Disaster paintings contain
jects. Each of these boxes contains a part of Warhol’s life, as
series. Within one canvas, the same image of violent death is
if in an attempt to stop time and hold it there, enclosed. This
often repeated several times. But repetition is a way of trying
again links to the soup cans, because food can keep a mighty
to stop time. Repetition also neutralises the threat of death:
long time in a tin can: as long as it is untouched by oxygen,
by repeating the same image again and again, it becomes
the food will not spoil. In other words: contained away from
more and more abstract and less painful or threatening.
267
What is traumatising when first seen, soon becomes a mere
good a place to start a discussion of his films as any other. For
visual motif, an arrangement of forms on a canvas. As he told
several years, but ending somewhere in early 1966, every in-
Gretchen Berg in what is probably the most famous interview
teresting visitor to Warhol’s silver Factory was required to sit
he ever gave, ‘when I read magazines I just look at the pic-
for their portrait. This was a moving portrait: the subject was
tures and the words, I don’t usually read it. There’s no mean-
sat on a chair in front of some nondescript background, lit,
ing to the words, I just feel the shapes with my eye and if you
and required not to move or blink for the next three minutes,
look at something long enough, I’ve discovered, the meaning
which was the duration of a reel of film. Once the camera had
goes away’ (Goldsmith 2004: 95). To cheat death by casting
started filming, Warhol abandoned it and everybody went
a cold eye upon it: this is Warhol’s method. And it found its
about their business, leaving the sitter to sit. Every sitter in
strongest expression in his films, where the impersonal eye
this catalogue of moving pictures makes an effort to comply,
of the camera strengthened Warhol’s gaze and turned it into
but not moving, and especially not blinking, is a strenuous
a scalpel with which he could open up the psychical bodies
exercise. Sooner or later the subject has to give in. They blink.
of the stars that moved in orbit around it.
Their eyes begin to water. They look sideways because they are distracted. They become visibly uncomfortable. They
268
Moving Towards Stillness
move, often involuntarily and spontaneously.
Time and the body: these are the axes around which Warhol’s
This is exactly what Warhol hopes to achieve. By leaving his
cinema turns. What happens when we gaze at something?
subject alone with the camera Warhol forces the person to
What do we see or hope to see when we gaze? Warhol’s cine-
confront himself. Three minutes is a very long time if one is
ma is grounded in the belief that if you wait and look long and
waiting for it to elapse. One becomes very self-conscious. One
hard enough, something will be revealed. A gift will be given;
may ask oneself if one is doing it well, even though one is not
a gift of knowledge. Intimate knowledge at that. The reward
supposed to be doing anything at all. Many of the sitters have
for gazing is illumination. Just like his paintings, Warhol’s
testified to the uncomfortable and even traumatic experience
films are about the tension between the inside and the out-
of having one’s Screen Test made by Warhol. In fact, the Screen
side. By staring at things, you can break the shell of the out-
Tests were a form of torture. By confronting the sitters with
side and see what is within. The gaze waits for a revelation.
themselves, Warhol is soliciting a crack in their image. At first,
It is a patient way of looking. It is waiting for it to happen, as
every sitter tries to maintain some dignity, some image, some
Warhol would put it. The “it” he waits for, is the point where
facade. But unable to maintain this facade, they sooner or lat-
something unexpected, something revealing breaks through
er become themselves. Their real personality breaks through.
the surface of the ordinary and offers us a glimpse of the hid-
It is these glimpses of reality that Warhol is hoping to see.
den, the inside, the real. In this sense, Warhol’s hundreds of
The camera is the disembodied and cold machine eye that is
Screen Tests are the paradigm of his cinematic activity and as
preying on the innocent sitter until the inevitable cracks ap-
269
270
pear, just like a portrait in oil-paint might crack. ‘The screen
gaze and thoughts inwards, as it does for the sitters in the
tests were explicitly acts of coercion, of psychological torture,’
Screen Tests who have three excruciatingly long minutes of
Wayne Koestenbaum explains. ‘The experience of watching
time on their hands to contemplate their existence, then and
these tests in bulk has permanently changed my attitude
there, in front of the peering camera eye. But if extended time
toward the human face: I realise that I have never looked with
turns us inwards, it is by extension possible to afford insight
enough love or forgiveness at the features of strangers. Not
into another person. This, too, is the logic of the Screen Tests:
that Warhol’s gaze is loving: to judge by their expressions,
the moment time becomes unbearable and the sitter retreats
the sitters experience the screen test as an ordeal, a punitive
into himself is usually also the moment he cracks and his hid-
sounding-of-depths, which they resist by not emoting’ (Koes-
den inside becomes visible. This desire to see the unseen and
tenbaum 2001: 99-100). Until the facade cracks and the victim
the hidden is the key to the pornographic gaze. The viewer
is provoked ‘into a visible breakdown’ (o.c. 100). This visible
of pornography hopes to see a moment of release, of loss of
breakdown is the emergence of the invisible interior: some-
control, when reality breaks through the surface. This is the
thing that was hidden and is therefore more real than what
moment of orgasm. Wayne Koestenbaum writes that Warhol
can readily be seen on the surface. In spite of themselves the
‘reconfigured the pornographic impulse into a sage, serious
sitters reveal themselves, in a way that is similar to the sur-
quest for the essence of matter – to approach, more and more
render in orgasm: you cannot hold back and are overtaken,
closely, the miraculous core of the material world by watch-
briefly, by something irrepressible. This is the erotics of the
ing (and reproducing) other people’s bodies [...]. The puritani-
gaze at work in Warhol’s cinema: to provoke the emergence of
cal moralism that surrounds the contemporary debate over
the hidden. It is coerced intimacy, cinema as ocular rape.
pornography overlooks the honest, near-religious motive for
Warhol’s early films were projected at silent speed. Sound
sexually explicit images: curiosity, or the laudable hunger to
speed is twenty-four frames per second; silent speed can be
see more than the eye can hold’ (Koestenbaum 2001: 9).
as slow as eighteen or sixteen frames per second. This means
The main virtue the pornographic perceiver in this meta-
that Warhol’s silent films take longer to show than they took
physical sense must have is patience: the willingness to wait
to film. Here, Warhol is extending time. This is the ultimate
it out, to wait for it to happen, for revelation to come. Warhol
preoccupation of Warhol’s cinema. Time is related to embodi-
was certainly a master of patience, to such an extent even
ment: we experience time because we are physical beings in
that Stephen Koch has rightfully dubbed him ‘the tycoon of
the world. It is especially when we are bored and nothing is
passivity’ (Koch 1991: 23). One of Warhol’s greatest exercises
happening that we can almost feel time dragging at our bod-
in gazing was one of his earliest films, Sleep (1962). This is
ies. Time becomes something viscous, something that stifles
an extended portrait of the sleeping body of the poet John
and irritates. We become acutely aware of the fact that we are
Giorno, who was Warhol’s boyfriend at the time. Contrary to
here, a body in space. Awareness of time’s passing turns our
popular lore, Sleep is not an unmoving six hour long shot of
271
272
Giorno’s sleeping body. It is in fact a highly crafted film and
is receiving the titular service of the film. We do not know
nothing like the primitive document it is often made out to
whether the blower is a man or a woman. In fact, we do not
be. The film was not even made in one night. Over a period
even know whether the blow job actually occurs or whether
of six weeks Warhol filmed a series of three-minute reels of
the entire film is a put-on, for Warhol’s camera stubbornly
Giorno sleeping (the same kind of reels used for the Screen
refuses to move and show us anything happening below the
Tests). With the help of the British student Sarah Dalton he
blowee’s shoulders. Throughout the film the young man goes
edited this mass of footage into one extended sleep in which
through all the movements that are associated with a blow-
the point of view of the camera changes from reel to reel,
job: enjoyment, ecstasy, boredom, and, finally, in the eighth
with several reels being repeated throughout the film (Watson
reel, orgasm. We know this because in the ninth reel he lights
2003: 133-134). Sometimes Giorno is lying on his back, then
a cigarette, which is a standard post-coital practice among
on his side. Sometimes the camera teasingly reveals the edge
nicotine fiends. The “real” orgasm is never shown. Instead, the
of his pubic hair, at other times it focuses on the movement
film experiences it for us. Every reel (also those used for the
of his belly, which slowly rises and falls with the rhythm of
Screen Tests and other Warhol films) ends with a leader. This
Giorno’s breathing (an extended, slowed-down rise and fall
is a stretch of white film. First it is announced in the form of
projected at silent speed). This film is a highly charged erotic
a white blur that momentarily mists up the screen, notifying
document. It offers us something we never again will see for
us of the impending end of the film. Moments later, the whit-
while Giorno is sleeping, he is unconscious and everything he
ing returns to engulf the image entirely and the reel ends. In
does is involuntary. So despite the fact that the film contains
Blow-Job the leader seems to climax by proxy. It ejaculates in
no action or events in the traditional sense, every detail of
the place of the young man (and maybe even in the place of
Gionro’s body, every movement, even the slightest shift in the
the aroused viewer).
way the body is present on the screen, is an event. Everything
Ironically, these white-outs circle back to the possible put-on
that happens is real, and hence meaningful. We see Giorno as
of the film, because it is remarkable that reel after reel the
he really is, an erotic revelation of the highest order.
young man seems to attain some kind of climax as the white-
This erotics of the cinema can even be inscribed in the mate-
out engulfs the screen. One gets the feeling the young actor
rial of the film itself. This happens in another one of Warhol’s
was being directed by Warhol, or by someone. In the third reel
legendary early films, Blow-Job (1963). This film is composed of
the young man briefly nods and smiles to someone off screen.
nine three-minute reels. Each reel shows the same thing: the
Is he reacting to something Warhol said? Was he not aware
head and shoulders of an anonymous young man in a leather
that the camera was rolling again? At the end of the fourth
jacket (since identified as the actor DeVerne Bookwalter; An-
reel his gaze goes ecstatically skyward at the moment the Er-
gell 2006: 41) against the brick wall of the Factory. To judge
satz ejaculation takes off. This remarkable coincidence repeats
from his facial expressions and movements, the young man
itself at the end of the fifth reel. And at the end of reel six he
273
274
opens his eyes in amazement, as if experiencing a vision (like
eyes. One of the most disconcerting experiences of watching
Bernini’s Theresa of Avila, which is sometimes called the first
a Warhol film is that they make time tangible by being any-
female orgasm in art). The game is given away at the start of
thing but boring. Images remain on the screen for so long that
reel eight, the climactic reel. First, the young man can be seen
we are able to take in every detail. We can gorge ourselves on
saying something to someone off screen (possibly Warhol),
the image. And yet, when the image finally does change, one
then he looks at that person (his look is clearly the look of
is still left with the feeling that one has not yet seen enough.
someone looking at another person) and then becomes (starts
The longer we stare at a Warhol film, the more intense be-
acting?) ecstatic. Shortly after, the unmistakable orgasm is
comes the unrest that is kindled within us: we actually start
attained. Since Blow-Job is a silent film, we cannot know how
fearing the approaching moment when the image will be
much of all this is real and how much staged. Some of the
taken away from us. The gaze becomes searching, agitated,
reaction shots in which we “catch” the young man being
active. It is looking for anything, any minute detail, any kind
spontaneous towards people off screen may be actual reac-
of revelatory aspect that it might have overlooked. It wants to
tion shots, but they might just as well have been created in-
find it before the image is taken away. This, again, is the black
tentionally to confuse the audience. And even if most of the
hole of Warhol sucking us in. Warhol creates images that fas-
film is staged, this would not preclude the possibility of real
cinate beyond the limits of the tolerable. His is a cinema that
orgasm at the end or, perversely, in one of the earlier reels (for
it is impossible to turn away from. Watching Warhol’s films is
who can say with any amount of certainty that the reels have
an oddly transformative experience. Afterwards, one can nev-
been edited in the actual chronological order in which they
er look at moving images again with the same innocence one
were filmed or the blowee was blown?).
had before Warhol. One becomes acutely aware of the sexual
One thing is for sure: Warhol gives us plenty of time to con-
nature of every act of looking. To be ocular, to be a creature of
template all these questions as the erotic proceedings unfold
sight, is to be sexual, sensually in, within, and of the world.
in time. Roy Grundmann has commented that Warhol’s obses-
The sensory is the sexual in its fullest dimension. ‘Warhol
sion with extended looking at people is linked to his desire
didn’t sublimate sex,’ Koestenbaum has correctly noted of
to create his own miniature Hollywood in the Factory. In his
Warhol’s work, ‘he simply extended its jurisdiction, allowing
famous interview with Gretchen Berg, Warhol suggests that
it to dominate every process and pastime. For Warhol, every-
‘people usually go to the movies to see only the star, to eat
thing is sexual. Contemplation is sexual. Movement is sexual.
him up, so here at last is a chance to look only at the star for
Stillness is sexual. Looking and being looked at are sexual.
as long as you like, no matter what he does and to eat him up
Time is sexual: that is why it must be stopped’ (Koestenbaum
all you want to’ (in Goldsmith 2004: 90). Warhol isolates this
2001: 5).
obsessive element of star-worship and makes it into the topic
I started this discussion of Warhol’s films with the claim that
of his films, which are all about devouring people with our
his cinematic work is a conscious philosophical exploration
275
276
of the problem of embodiment. This claim is supported by
The Belly of a Dyslectic
the fact that Warhol very consciously chose to be the kind
Just like Hollywood before him, Warhol evolved from silent
of filmmaker he was. Among his early films we find several
films into talkies, films with sound. This forced him to change
projects that are decidedly different in style, flirting with the
his approach to filmmaking. For one thing, screening films at
camp style of film-making that was very influential in the
slowed-down silent speed was now out of the question. This
early 1960s. The biggest star of the camp film was Jack Smith,
meant other means of truth-gathering had to be devised. The
director of the legendary Flaming Creatures (1963) but also a
introduction of sound meant that Warhol’s films were now
gifted performer in front of the camera. One of Warhol’s earli-
more involved with plot. At least the semblance of a story or
est films is a reel called Andy Warhol Films Jack Smith Filming
event had to be created. But narratives were never Warhol’s
Normal Love (1963), a record of Smith and his collaborators
strong suit. On top of his many other traumas, Warhol had
filming Normal Love (1963), a camp film in which Warhol also
a severe case of dyslexia. He basically could not write. Para-
made an appearance. Warhol made several films in this ex-
doxically, he published a great many books, almost entirely
cessive camp style. One such film is Tarzan and Jane Regained...
ghostwritten by others. For his novel a he simply taped On-
Sort Of (1963), featuring the waif-like underground superstar
dine’s monologue extérieure and had someone type it up. The
Taylor Mead as an unlikely Tarzan and boasting a cameo ap-
transcript was published with all the typing errors intact.
pearance of a hunky, loin-clothed (actually towel-wrapped)
Later, he would dictate his diaries to Pat Hackett. Since con-
Dennis Hopper. Another was the epic but uncompleted Bat-
structing language was a problem for Warhol, he feigned not
man Dracula (1964), featuring Jack Smith in the double lead
being able to think, which requires the use of language. Lan-
role. Significantly, Warhol soon abandoned this line of film-
guage was alien to Warhol. As he told Gretchen Berg, ‘I always
making to concentrate on his own minimalist, near-abstract
feel that my words are coming from behind me, not from me.
way of filming, doing what he did best: stare and wait for it
The interviewer should just tell me the words he wants me
to happen, but obviously giving “it” a hand by coaxing coin-
to say and I’ll repeat them after him. I think that would be
cidence out of hiding, as in the torture tactics of the Screen
so great because I’m so empty I just can’t think of anything
Tests. But gazing was the name of the game. As Warhol him-
to say’ (Goldsmith 2004: 96). That Warhol was a dyslectic also
self once testified: ‘Everything is interesting. Years ago, people
means that he had trouble with the progressive nature of
used to sit looking out of their windows at the street. Or on a
language, which moves, letter by letter, from one side of the
park bench. They would stay for hours without being bored
page to the other. Language is another manifestation of time.
although nothing much was going on. This is my favourite
And it troubled Warhol. So he decided not to have plot in the
theme in movie making – just watching something happening
talkies. Ronald Tavel, the playwright for the Theatre of the Ri-
for two hours or so’ (Bockris 1997: 327).
diculous, scripted a series of Warhol’s most important talkies. But Warhol resisted elaborate scripts and demanded ‘No plot,
277
278
but incident’ (Koch 1991: 63). It was Tavel’s job to devise situa-
two scenes. The second reel of the film is a traditional Warhol
tions in which the actors would have to perform. Within that
talkie with two people confined in a small space for the dura-
framework Warhol’s usual torture practices would take over.
tion of the film. Paul America and another man, an ageing
As a rule, reels for sound film ran for something more than
hustler played by Ed McDermott, are in the bathroom of the
half an hour. As with the Screen Tests, Warhol would turn the
beach house. America has taken a shower and has a towel
camera on and let it run until the film ended. The end of the
wrapped around his waist. He is combing his hair, primping
reel signified the end of the film, regardless of whether the
his body, and takes a piss while MacDermott looks on, hoping
events evolving in front of the camera had reached any kind
to score with America. The tension in the film arises from the
of climax or resolution. For the duration of the reel, the actors
fact that these two men are circling around each other like
had to perform for dear life. There were no pauses, no second
animals, trying to fathom each other’s intentions without giv-
takes. No matter what happened, the show had to go on. As
ing away too much about their own desires. In the confined
with the Screen Tests, this process of filming was devised to
space of the bathroom, however, they cannot help but touch
make the actors crack by confronting them with themselves.
each other. Within this erotic huis clos, which (like all Warhol’s
But the body and its secrets were still a central concern in
best films) is very stylishly and intelligently filmed, making
these films. Witness My Hustler (1965), the first Warhol film on
the most of the frame of the bathroom door, the bathroom
which Paul Morrissey played an important role as Warhol’s
mirror, and the cabin of the shower to create a multi-layered
assistant. It was Morrissey’s idea to introduce the panning
sense of spatial depth, the seemingly banal situation of two
movement of the camera in this film: the camera moves back
men talking to each other in the bathroom becomes an event
and forth horizontally between two scenes: the porch of a
of the highest erotico-voyeuristic import.
beach house and the beach itself where a young man is sit-
The high point of Warhol’s cinematic endeavours in this
ting in the sand. On the porch a conversation can be heard
second, talking part of his career is undoubtedly The Chelsea
between a man, played by Ed Hood, and several of his friends.
Girls (1966), more than three hours of double-screen projec-
The blond hunk on the beach is played by Paul America. It ap-
tion that encompasses a whole series of one-reel films and
pears that Hood has rented the stud via a Dial-a-Hustler ser-
situations. Two such segments have become deservedly fa-
vice. In the first reel of the film Hood’s envious friends make
mous and are of the highest importance for our discussion of
catty comments on America, who is oblivious to what is be-
Warhol. Both are outstanding examples of what Warhol could
ing said. During this dialogue the camera pans back and forth
accomplish by letting his performers expose themselves. The
between the conversationalists and America. Some of these
first segment is ‘Eric’s Trip’. This is a monologue by angelic
pans are very fast and involve a quick zoom of the camera.
blond Eric Emerson, who was required to talk about himself
The effect is disorienting: it is difficult for the viewer to es-
for half an hour while Warhol projected coloured lights on
tablish the exact distance and spatial relation between the
him. But Eric is on an LSD-trip. As he slowly disrobes in what
279
280
must be one of the most gloriously extended stripteases in
go, so he decides to give himself a shot of heroin, after which
film history, Eric starts grooving on his own body. His im-
he rinses his syringe with Coke. The psychological theatre of
provised monologue is sheer verbal poetry. Metaphors and
this stunning piece of cinéma vérité shows the great strength
images seem to come effortlessly to Emerson, who ambles
of Warhol’s cinema. It is the finale to The Chelsea Girls, and
through expressive language with a relaxed ease that Warhol
after the almost three hours of double-projected film that
surely must have envied. His speech is a sensual revelation
preceded it, it still packs a wallop. But it also shows how
of his holistic consciousness of himself as part of the physi-
the psychological tactics of the performers can turn against
cal world. He speaks of ingesting particles of the world and of
them; something Ronald Tavel also experienced while shoot-
the connection between body and world. ‘Eric’s Trip’ is glori-
ing Screen Test #2 (1964), which is not a screen test as such
ous cinema, especially because it was not tortured out of the
but a film about a screen test. The star being tested is Mario
actor. Rather, it blooms forth from him. As his high rises, War-
Montez, a drag queen who named herself after Maria Montez
hol trips up the lighting effects until the image explodes into
and who had attained underground fame in the films of Jack
an abstract pattern of light and darkness that seems to recall
Smith, notably in Flaming Creatures. Screen Test #2 is a classic
the work of Francis Bacon. As Eric looses himself in himself,
exercise in Warholian torture cinema. Tavel, who scripted
the image disintegrates into a stroboscopic vision of shooting
the film, tests Montez by giving her directions. Tavel himself
colours. It is one of the most stunningly beautiful pieces of
remains disembodied, off-screen. Only his voice is present.
film ever made and it remains profoundly moving even after
As the film progresses, Tavel clearly tries to make Montez
one has seen it several times.
break down in front of the camera by asking prurient and
Equally revealing, but driven by an entirely different dynamic,
humiliating questions. The film reaches something of a nadir
is one of the most famous segments Warhol ever filmed:
when the star is asked, as an exercise in diction, to clearly
‘Pope Ondine’. In this segment Ondine, verbal author of a and
and repetitively pronounce the word “diarrhoea”. Tavel also
proprietor of the Factory’s sharpest tongue, holds court as the
forces her to confess that she is not really a woman. When
Pope. He hears confession while sipping Coke from a bottle.
the completed film was shown to the Factory crowd, Tavel
He is clearly high. But events take a turn for the worse when
was mortified at how much the film revealed about him, and
one of the confessors, a young woman named Rona Page,
not about Montez.
accuses Ondine of being a “phoney,” a poseur. Ondine looses
One of the greatest sites of Warholian revelations, and
his temper with her and smacks her in the face. From then
also one of Warhol’s greatest but least discussed films, is
on, the scene degenerates into a fascinating deconstruction
Vinyl (1965), a two-reeler vaguely based on Anthony Bur-
of Ondine, who is lost somewhere between his character and
gess’ novel A Clockwork Orange (1962) to which Warhol had
his real identity. After he has chased Page off the set and has
bought the rights (in the event also making a masterpiece
calmed down again, he still has about ten minutes of reel to
that far outshines the tepid exercise in épater la bourgeoisie
281
282
that Stanley Kubrick was to concoct from the novel). In Vinyl
Malanga really suffers through this film, for the poppers are
Gerard Malanga plays Victor, a juvenile delinquent dressed
clearly real, as is his helpless high (interestingly, Malanga is
Brando-style in a white T-shirt and a fake black leather jacket
a heterosexual who performed several homosexual acts in
(fake leather is vinyl). As the film starts, the camera shows a
front of Warhol’s camera, actually engaging in gay sex in a
close-up of Victor as he is training with weights. The camera
segment of the 1964 film Couch).
then slowly pans back to reveal the other performers who are
But all of the above is merely what happens middle and left
grouped around Malanga in a composition that will be main-
of the foreground of the image. Warhol’s camera is positioned
tained more or less throughout the film. This means that
very high, creating an extreme bird’s eye point of view that
throughout the film the image is actually split up in several
creates a very strong sense of depth. So the camera sees
areas of action that are highlighted in the darkened space of
much more than the scenes involving Victor/Malanga. And
the Factory. That way the image is stuffed with visual infor-
this is where Warhol’s aesthetic is put to work: the image is
mation, for the viewer has several strands of action to follow
crowded with information and all manner of incident. While
in the several segments of the image. On the foreground the
Victor is being tortured in the foreground, Jacques Potin (a
main action takes place: a young student (Larry Latreille) is
marginal member of Warhol’s crew of performers) is loung-
hassled and beaten up by Victor, then dragged to the back-
ing in the background, waiting to get involved in some of
ground where, in a second area of action, he is subjected to
the subsequent action. In the left top corner, in the back of
an SM session by Ondine and Tosh Carillo. After this, Victor
the space of the film, stands the Factory’s famous mirrorball,
himself gets into a fight with Ondine, who roughs him up and
sparkling away regardless of the events. The image is cut in
hands him over to the police (J.D. MacDermott), who forces
half vertically by a slender pole, which is first used by Victor
Victor to sign a waiver allowing the police to subject him to
to tie the hapless student to. While Victor is being tortured,
aversion therapy. This therapy consists in a ‘doctor’ (Carillo)
the space to the right of this pole is occupied by another SM
strapping Victor to a chair on the left side of the foreground,
scene, with Latreille being liberated from the pole only to be
where Victor is forced to watch violent films. This is supposed
tied to a chair and tortured. This is where Potin gets involved,
to make Victor feel so sick that it will cure him of his violent
dripping hot wax on Latreille’s chest and whipping him softly
behaviour. We do not get to see the films that are projected,
with a leather belt. Ondine tears the boy’s pants. And finally,
but Victor describes them to us, adding another, merely ver-
on the right side of the image but prominently in the fore-
bal narrative layer to the film. In the course of this treatment
ground, is the only female in the film. This is Edie Sedgewick,
Victor is forced to inhale poppers until he gets so high he
sitting on a trunk, sipping a drink from a paper cup, having a
sinks to his knees, all but catatonic. Completely out of it, Vic-
smoke, and pretending none of the above is going on around
tor tries to dance with Carillo and clutches the knees of his
her. Throughout the entire film, she does not utter a word.
torturer. Part of Vinyl’s fascination stems from the fact that
She just sits and is fabulous. She sometimes moves. At one
283
284
point, she exits the screen for a while (she needed to go to
closed, while the other actors move around him in the frame.
the toilet). Edie would become one of Warhol’s most legend-
It is a stunning tableau that comes and goes for a brief mo-
ary performers, making a string of films with him in 1965,
ment. Just before the second reel runs out, Carillo cuts a lock
and Warhol had added her to the cast of Vinyl as a last-min-
of Malanga’s hair. Just as abruptly as it started, the film ends.
ute decision to balance the all-male cast.
Its reel was up.
All of this is going on in Vinyl and it is all going on at the
The effect of watching Vinyl is quite unlike any other a cine-
same time within the cramped space of the film image. It is
phile might have experienced in his movie-going career. It
simply too much for the viewer to take in. One must see Vinyl
is a mesmerising and profoundly disturbing work. It has a
several times to register everything that happens in it. One
visual intelligence that is rarely seen even in the most so-
moment one is following or trying to follow the main story,
phisticated of films. Few films I know of are able to squeeze
but the next moment something in the background catches
so much information into one frame and maintain that nar-
the eye. The eye is next pulled towards Edie’s luminous pres-
rative tension for more than an hour. But if we stick to analy-
ence, losing the thread of the main story, causing it to keep
sis, I believe that all Warhol’s concerns as I have sketched
on roaming through the events. And Warhol adds even more
them come together in this film. I submit that Vinyl, as a film,
distracting elements. As was usual for the talkies, there are
is a transit-machine: the claustrophobic image, stuffed to
no credits. Warhol had the habit of having someone, either
the limit with visual information, should be read as a visual
on screen or off, read the credits out loud at a moment when
equivalent of the digestive system. This digestive system is
the action in a film seemed to flag. The actors are not at all
literally filled with debris. At the beginning of the film the
convincing. Their acting is stilted, and sometimes they are
student is carrying a pile of books, which are really issues
clearly reading their lines from cue cards. Warhol consciously
of magazines. These are ripped, torn, and thrown about by
sabotaged Malanga’s performance by taking the actor out on
Malanga and Ondine. As the film continues and chaos takes
the town on the eve of the filming, so that he would not have
over, the film is literally cluttered with actions (the several
time to memorise his lines, which outraged Tavel. But this
areas of events), violence, torn clothing, and a collage of loud
matters very little since the dialogue is hard to follow any-
music, sounds, movement, and dialogue. As the film nears its
way. The in-camera sound of Warhol’s films is often less than
end, Warhol doesn’t even play songs anymore, but fragments,
crystal clear, something that is exacerbated near the end of
snippets of songs following each other in nervous succes-
Vinyl by the fact that Warhol starts playing pop records (vinyl,
sion. In this way, Vinyl is a case of cinematic indigestion, a
again) at maximum volume. At that point, total chaos erupts.
digestive system in which the waste keeps sloshing about
Malanga is liberated from his chair, but is so high that he falls
without ever being excreted. In this, the film resembles the
to the floor, crawls around and then, for one magical mo-
Campbell’s soup cans, which contain soup, which resembles
ment, sits on his knees, with his back straight and his eyes
half-digested food. It also resembles the time capsules, in
285
286
which Warhol randomly collected all manner of items and
and unexpectedly converge in an Andachtsbild. The composi-
trash. And in light of these resemblances it is surely no coin-
tion is maintained for a moment. Then chaos returns and the
cidence that reels of film like Vinyl are usually stored in cans.
moment is gone. But the moment, however brief, is not with-
A finished scene is often said to be “in the can”. And finally,
out importance. It is like those coincidental constellations of
the brackish slosh of Vinyl’s visual content resembles the
beauty that sometimes come about between elements that
inside of Julia’s and Warhol’s bodies with their tortured, mal-
are not connected to each other. Every body is moving on its
functioning innards. In the final reckoning, Vinyl is an anally
own, but for a moment they are configured in a pattern. This
retentive film: it derives its pleasures from not excreting. It is
is what happens in that tableau in Vinyl. It is sheer coinci-
an exercise in controlling one’s bowels. The debris is inside
dence, to be sure, but it is Warhol’s art to provoke coincidence
the body, and the form of this particular cinematic body is
(there are limits to the amount of gorgeous coincidences one
pristinely antiseptic and streamlined: it is a can, a cylinder, a
can be granted by coincidence; a strong artist can force the
frame, a factory.
hand of Fate a bit and create a fertile environment for such
But this cannot be the end, for if Warhol’s torture tactics
coincidences to occur). Warhol’s patience in waiting for it to
serve any purpose, it is to bring out the long-awaited revela-
happen has been rewarded. Sooner or later, if you wait long
tion of the unsuspected miraculous event of “it happening”.
enough, chaos will yield harmony. For if bodies are moving
And “it” does happen at the end of Vinyl. The “it” of Vinyl is
about at random, it is a statistical fact that sooner or later
the visual tableau I mentioned earlier. Near the end of the
(but possibly later rather than sooner) some ordered constel-
second real, chaos erupts and all performers become free
lation will occur. Not because the moving bodies are geared
radicals, moving about at will, degenerating into licentious-
towards harmony, but because that visually pleasing constel-
ness and other naughty doings. Latreille tries to impress
lation is just one out of the virtually endless series of possible
Edie by acting tough and placing his booted foot on helpless
constellations that are available with these variables. There
Malanga’s behind. SM, indeed. For this final descent into
is no order in the bodies: they merely move. Therefore, the
disorder even the camera joins in. It leaves its immobile posi-
tableau that is the crowning achievement of Vinyl is a gift in
tion and, like the eye of the viewer, starts roaming through
the true sense of the word. It is a revelation. If anything (and,
the visual space, veritably eating up (like the movie-goer’s
to be sure, there is much more) Vinyl teaches and urges us to
voracious eye) Malanga’s malleable but tortured flesh. The
appreciate such gifts of beauty. It teaches us to celebrate the
camera joins in the chaos, dancing to Warhol’s tune of dis-
beauty of coincidence, the splendour of the unexpected. By
connected pop records. Until, suddenly, the image of saintly
playing the game of authenticity and improvisation, Warhol
Malanga, kneeling centrally in the frame, appears, with the
has created a space for real beauty to occur: a beauty that is
other performers arranged around him. It is a glorious sight,
not classical or academic, but emergent.
as if all the variables of the film’s visual universe suddenly
287
Chapter Four
Making the World In her book on The Body in Pain (1985) Elaine Scarry asks what the felt experience of pain is like and how this experience
ENGAGING
affects our physical and mental existence. What does pain
THE WORLD
she mean by this? Clearly, it cannot mean that the experi-
do to us? What does it do to our sense of self? Scarry claims that ‘intense pain is world-destroying’ (BP 29). But what does ence of pain within my body somehow wreaks havoc upon the objects and buildings around me. On the contrary, the world often seems infuriatingly indifferent to our pain or
288
In the new millennium art has swerved away from the philo-
the pain of our loved-ones. So the destruction of the world
sophical condition and beauty has taken centre stage again.
through pain should not be taken literally, in the sense of
The next two chapters are devoted to that rediscovered
a physical destruction of the material world. It is therefore
beauty. But to get to it, we must first go through the mire.
our first business to determine what Scarry means by “the
Beauty must often be salvaged from chaos. It is often found
world”. What world is she talking about? As will become
in fragments, in little scraps of reality that seem of no con-
clear, the world she writes about is phenomenological: it is
sequence whatever in the greater scheme of things. In the
the world for me, the environment I inhabit, the whole of ob-
case of the American philosopher Elaine Scarry, beauty was
jects and structures that is present to my senses and which
a topic she came to after she had descended into the worlds
establishes the space in which I move and live. World must
of pain and torture. We will follow her there and learn that
be understood as Lebenswelt: not the whole physical universe
to gain beauty we must re-establish contact with the world.
but the extent of my sentient extension into that world as it
This will lead us into an exploration of the Dionysian, the
presents itself to my felt experience.
dark undercurrent of reality. Following Scarry and the work
According to Scarry, Marx ‘throughout his writings assumes
of Hermann Nitsch we will immerse ourselves in the muck
that the made world is the human being’s body and that,
of brutal nature, only to emerge cleansed on the other side,
having projected that body into the made world, men and
ready to experience beauty, and possibly in possession of a
women are themselves disembodied, spiritualized’ (BP 244).
metaphysical foundation for the processes of sadomasoch-
This is the basic idea behind Das Kapital (1867): through la-
ism that were explored in the previous chapter.
bour people invest themselves in the world and make that world human. This, in essence, is the process at work in commodity fetishism. We create artefacts through the labour of our bodies. A certain amount of human labour was
289
expended in the production of the commodity and the duration of the labour required to produce it is the measure of value. So two objects will have the same value if the same amount of time was required to produce them. Marx is very acutely aware of the almost magical or alchemical process that this implies and that is surely one of the reasons he called it a fetishism: a perception of value that is projected rather that objectively present in an object. We create the world, and the value we attach to it, by extending ourselves into it, by investing our labour and through our labour a piece of ourselves in the material world. So, in a very real sense, we are part of the world. ‘For Marx, material making is a recreation of the body and the body is itself recreated in that activity’ (BP 256). Through our labour, we are present in the world. This means that it is not sufficient to say that
290
we, being organisms, are part of the world in the sense that we are dependent on the eco-system of our planet or on the cosmos in general. We must add that we are also part of the non-natural and made world of manufactured objects. They too are part of us and we are part of them. Humans and their world are coextensive. In creating objects, we become invested in them. This is one-way magic, for once this investment has been established, the composing parts cannot be separated again: ‘the human creature is immersed in his interaction with the world, far too immersed to extricate himself from it’ (Scarry 1994: 52). Created objects, artefacts, are expressive of who we are. This investment is also expressed in our attachment to the objects around us. Even if an object has very little objective value in itself it can still mean a lot to us because of some Elaine Scarry
emotional attachment (this pen is not simply a pen but my
291
late grandfather’s pen) or because it is simply part of the everyday world in which we feel at home, our Lebenswelt. Our investment in the world is most clear in the comforting feeling of being at home in our own living space, the space that we assembled (we picked the furniture, the wall-paper, the paintings on the wall) to express who we are. The worldbuilding ability of humans was of central concern to Hannah Arendt. In The Human Condition (1958) she famously distinguished three types of human activity: labour, work, and action. Labour is an activity that is involved in the cycle of life. What is created through labour is immediately consumed again. I bake a bread to eat it, I till the earth to grow vegetables to feed my family. Labour is the sphere of consumption: what is made is immediately reinvested in the digestive cycle of human existence. What is consumed, disappears
292
again from the world. Nothing remains. Work, on the other hand, is the realm of worldliness. This means that the activity of work results in the creation of a shared world. We make things that outlast us. If we build a house, the house is not demolished when we die: other people come to live there and very often this change of inhabitants will repeat itself many times over the generations. Finally, the third and most distinctly human activity Arendt distinguishes is action. Typical of action is the fact that nothing is produced. There is no product, only an endless process that is undertaken for its own sake and because we deem it meaningful. The greatest example of action is politics, where people gather and speak up in public for the common good. To act is to take action in the world, to stand up for something, not because this gives immediate results (because every political deciKarl Marx
sion can always be overturned and every action can always
293
294
be undone by a counter-action) but because we take upon us
disabled because our disability is too widespread or common
the burden of responsibility for the world we share. Action
to be seen as a disability. Furthermore, nobody is able to get
is the realm of the unpredictable: we never know what the
to the second floor of any building without the prosthetic
effects of our actions will be.
use of stairs or an elevator. We are all disabled to some ex-
In our present context the activity of work is the most fasci-
tent. Imperfection is our nature. And we build the world in a
nating because of its lasting effects. It is a kind of production
way that helps us overcome our physical shortcomings. That
that does not get spent in the digestive cycle of consump-
is what tools are for: they are prostheses, extensions of the
tion. Through work we change the world, we turn resources
body that help us get about in the world. But for the person
into lasting artefacts. And we most commonly do this with
labelled “disabled” the fact that a tool is an extension of the
the help of tools. Marx and Scarry perceive tools as exten-
body becomes especially salient. If one needs an artificial leg
sions of the self and they are therefore considered to be
to walk, the tool is literally an extension of the body.
readily at hand. We do not reflect upon the tool-character of
As extensions of the body, tools and objects are an attempt
a door handle when we use it to open a door. We do not re-
to deal with our awareness of the world in a way that is
flect upon the tool-character of the hammer when we pick it
beneficial to ourselves. The shape of a chair, for example, is
up to drive a nail into the wall. We unconsciously treat these
designed to alleviate the burden of our spine. It gives rest to
tools as a self-evident presence in our world and therefore
the body by mimicking the body. So ‘the chair [can] be recog-
as part of our own extension into our world. This point be-
nised as mimetic of sentient awareness. [...] The shape of
comes more clear if we consider that we usually use our
the chair is not the shape of the skeleton, the shape of body
hands to handle tools. As Scarry notes, Friedrich Engels once
weight, nor even the shape of pain-perceived, but the shape
pointed out that the human hand ‘is itself an artefact, gradu-
of perceived-pain-wished-gone’ (BP 289-90). Chairs exist as
ally altered by its own activity of altering the external world’
an expression of the human wish to prevent pain that fol-
(BP 253). In Hiding from Humanity (2004) Martha Nussbaum
lows from being on our feet too long. But chairs no longer
has written about the use we make of prostheses in our
come about because of my individual desire to alleviate a
everyday existence. We distinguish healthy from disabled
back-ache, they are now being industrially manufactured.
people, assuming that people are disabled because their
And this, to Scarry’s mind, is a positive and world-building
body is imperfect in a way that makes it impossible for them
aspect of industrial labour that is easily overlooked. ‘It is
to have unrestricted access to (everyday human activities in)
almost universally the case in everyday life that the most
the world. A paralysed person, for example, needs a wheel-
cherished object is one that has been hand-made by a friend:
chair to get about and blind people need a stick or a dog to
[...] the object’s material attributes themselves record and
guide them. But Nussbaum points out that we are all dis-
memorialize the intensely personal [...] feelings of the maker
abled. Many of us need glasses, but we do not call ourselves
for just this person [...]. But anonymous, mass-produced
295
296
objects contain a collective and equally extraordinary mes-
goes to the very nature of man. Man is only happy if he is
sage: Whoever you are, and whether or not I personally like
able to express himself through meaningful activities. If we
or even know you, in at least this small way, be well’ (BP
introduce Arendt’s distinction between labour and work into
292). So even mass-production is engaged in the building of
Marx’s thought, we might say that what Arendt calls labour
a communal human world in which we can be at home. The
is related to what Marx would call exploitation: bodily activ-
most fundamental example of the body-extensiveness of the
ity that does not break the body free from the cycle of sub-
world is probably the nature of our homes and the rooms
sistence. If the worker gets fair earnings that are expressive
we inhabit within them. For Scarry ‘the room, the simplest
of the value he produces, he will be able to use his earnings
form of shelter, expresses the most benign potential of hu-
to buy goods for the sole purpose of expressing his human-
man life. It is, one the one hand, an enlargement of the body:
ity. This means that to become human is to be able to buy
it keeps warm and safe the individual it houses [...]; like the
luxury goods, namely goods that no longer contribute to our
body, its walls put boundaries around the self [...], yet in its
subsistence. We have already mentioned Susanne K. Langer’s
windows and doors, crude versions of the senses, it enables
claim that such expressive action is not at all frivolous or
the self to move out into the world and allows that world
some kind of surplus activity to indulge in when our more
to enter’ (BP 38). Scarry has further elaborated this view in
fundamental needs have been met. On the contrary, man has
Dreaming by the Book (2001), where she addresses the meta-
‘a primary need’ that she calls ‘the need of symbolisation. The
phor of the eyes as the windows of the soul. ‘It is estimated
symbol-making function is one of man’s primary activities,
that the total skin surface in an adult human being is three
like eating, looking, or moving about’ (PNK 40-41). Langer
thousand square inches. Compared to that expanse, the
writes that ‘the organism yearns to express’ ideas and feel-
surface covered by the retinas is a tiny patch of membrane
ings ‘without practical purpose’ (o.c. 43). This she sees as
[...]. Yet, physiologically, 38 percent of all sensory experience
the source of religion, ritual, art, and all kinds of expressive
takes place against that tiny surface. Eyes are, according to
behaviour in the human. In his anthropological survey of
neurobiologists, the direct outcropping of the brain: not con-
ancient Greek ritual Walter Burkert explains the sacrifice
tent to receive messages by mediation, the brain has moved
of food in the form of libations from this perspective. ‘Milk,
out to the surface of the skull in order to rub up against the
honey, oil, and wine, the precious commodities of a society
world directly (no wonder it is overwhelming to look into
familiar with dearth and hunger, were poured away irretriev-
another person’s eyes; one beholds directly the moist tissue
ably; similarly, grain was mashed into pap so it could drain
of the person’s brain)’ (DB 68).
into the ground. In southern regions, even water is a pre-
A final point on world-making must be made. As we saw,
cious commodity and hence played a part in some libations.
humans build a world that is an extension and a projection
[...] No other act of destruction can be expressed by gestures
of themselves. It was one of Marx’s assumptions that this
so noble and sublime: Achilles pouring wine for his dead
297
298
friend Patroklos, an unforgettable poetical image. The artful-
ing, better food, or medical care. This should not surprise us.
ly shaped libation vessels stress the grandeur of the proceed-
To feed, clothe, or medicate oneself does not yet make one
ings. By renouncing personal profit, man can uplift himself;
human. People prefer televisions over food because the tele-
by humbling himself in spite of his needs, he displays his
vision is a way of expressing who they are. It is also a way
wealth or at least his freedom. Alexander the Great acted in
of being part of the world, as it is literally a window on that
this way in the Gedrosian desert when he emptied into the
world. To indulge in expressive deficit spending (or comfort
sand a helmet filled with water’ (Burkert 1983: 54-55).
shopping) when one is poor is a way of claiming one’s hu-
This can help us understand why human beings are so fond
manity in the face of dehumanising poverty. It is to say: I am
of beautiful things, and especially of useless beauty. Art for
not an animal, I am a creature of expression. On this logic,
art’s sake or acquiring commodities for commodities’ sake, is
to keep social benefits intentionally (too) low as an “incen-
not an absurd concept. There is something profoundly hu-
tive” to work is to blackmail people with their very human-
man and healthy in our quest to gather around us objects we
ity. It denies people the means to be expressive. It is to deny
value. As Elaine Scarry has pointed out, we have a tendency
them access to the world. It is, in effect, to deny them their
to ‘verbally disavow and discredit our immersion in materi-
humanity.
alism, sometimes even scorning the tendency of less materi-
299
ally privileged cultures to aspire to the possession of these
Unmaking the World
same objects: that blue jeans are cherished in the Soviet
Marx’s analysis of the creation of the world through object
Union, that a picture from a Sears Roebuck catalogue should
fetishism is also the basis of Scarry’s analysis of the unmak-
appear on the wall of a hut in Nairobi, that Sony recorders
ing of the world. Labour is the basis on which capital is ac-
are prized in Iran, are events sometimes greeted by Western
cumulated. In the most primitive state of man, labour value
populations with bewilderment, as though the universal
would be exchanged for labour value: I exchange one hour’s
aspiration to such objects [...] were a form of incomprehen-
worth of baking bread for your one hour’s worth of knitting
sible corruption or an act of senseless imitation rather than
sweaters. In this way we all labour and trade the products
itself a confirmation and signal that something deep and
of our labour. This is the circuit of commodities: created
transforming is intuitively felt to happen when one dwells in
objects change hands in a constant dynamic of trade. But
proximity to such objects’ (BP 243). Humans like beauty for
with the emergence of money something changes in the
beauty’s sake, they like useless things, gadgets, and decora-
circuit of commodities. Originally commodities are traded
tive trivialities because of their potential for expressiveness.
for commodities, which could be schematically rendered as:
This, incidentally, explains why the poor often exasperate
C-C. With the introduction of money an intermediate stage
other people by spending their limited social benefits or
is introduced into this process. One will now exchange an
other resources on luxury goods instead of on better hous-
amount of goods for an equal amount of money, which in
300
turn can be used to purchase an equal amount of other com-
hen wir den Inbegriff der physischen und geistigen Fähigkeiten, die
modities. I sell you a loaf of bread for one euro if and only if
in der Leiblichkeit, der lebendigen Persönlichkeit eines Menschen
it takes me one euro’s worth of labour-time to produce the
existieren und die er in Bewegung setzt, sooft er Gebrauchswerte
loaf of bread. With the euro I thus acquire I can go and buy
irgendeiner Art produziert’; o.c. 181). It is noteworthy that Marx
one euro’s worth of vegetables, clothes, or any other com-
considers both our physical and our mental abilities to be
modity I desire. Schematically, this circuit of metamorphoses
part of our physicality (‘Leiblichkeit’), for there is nothing,
(for, remembering the magical nature of commodity fetish-
not even voice, that man can express without the use of
ism, it is apt to speak of a metamorphosis in this regard)
his physical being. There is no soul without the brains. But
runs as follows: C-M-C, Commodity is exchanged for Money
how can this labour power be used to generate capital? The
is exchanged for Commodity. But the emergence of money
value of labour power is determined the same way all value
immediately causes a new circuit to come into play. This is
is determined: by the average amount of labour necessary to
what Marx calls the circuit of capital. The aim will now no
produce it. In the case of labour power this amount of neces-
longer be to exchange equivalent values but to generate a
sary labour is ‘the time it takes to produce the commodities
profit at the end of the circuit. Schematically, the circuit of
necessary to sustain the worker for the day. Not only food,
capital runs as follows: M-C-M’. Two changes have taken
but a contribution to the cost of housing, clothes, and so on’
place. The circuit no longer starts with commodities but
(Wolff 2002: 71). In essence, the value of labour is the money
with money. Money is used to buy a commodity. The second
the worker needs to buy the goods that keep him alive. Let
change occurs when that commodity is sold again: it is sold
us now suppose that the average amount of time required
for profit. That means that it is sold for an amount of money
to generate these necessary commodities is four hours of
that is higher than the price originally paid for it (hence M’
labour. So the worker must work for four hours to earn the
instead of M).
wages necessary to sustain himself. However, the capitalist
The profit is what Marx calls surplus value: ‘Diese Inkrement
employs the worker for a full day’s work, namely (in our rela-
oder den Überschuss über den ursprünglichen Wert nenne ich –
tively humane times) eight hours. So the worker is required
Mehrwert (surplus value)’ (Marx 1962: 165). Surplus value
to work the last four hours for free. The worker exchanges
generates capital. If equivalents are exchanged, no surplus
a day’s labour for a day’s worth of sustenance. However, he
value can emerge and by consequence no capital can be
need only work half a day to obtain a day’s sustenance. The
acquired. The capitalist will therefore have to seek out a
four supplementary hours of work generate surplus value for
commodity that allows to generate surplus value. Labour
the capitalist. This is what Marx calls exploitation.
power is this kind of commodity. Labour power is man’s
This raises the obvious question why the labourer would be
physical and mental ability to create objects that can be sold
so stupid as to sell his labour so cheaply; indeed to some-
in the market (‘Unter Arbeitskraft oder Arbeitsvermögen verste-
times work for an amount of money that barely amounts
301
302
to subsistence wages. The answer to this question lies, per-
force will wear itself out and ultimately die, which is coun-
versely, in what Marx calls the labourer’s double freedom.
terproductive. Whatever the capitalist does, he will keep la-
The labourer is free in the sense that he is an individual in
bour force alive. But if at all possible, he will do nothing more
free control of his own commodity, namely his labour. He is
than that. It is of course not inconceivable that, for some rea-
free to trade its value in the market-place. But the labourer
son or other, labour force becomes scarce, causing the price
is also “free” in the sense that he has no access to what is
of labour force to rise. In that case one of the great spectres
needed for him to make his labour work for him. That is to
of Marxism appears: the replacement of the labourer with
say that the labourer has no access to the means of produc-
machines. This is the image of poorly paid labourers who are
tion or the resources to practice his skills. ‘Zur Verwandlung
making the very machines that will make their labour super-
von Geld in Kapital muss der Geldbesitzer also den freien Arbeiter
fluous. As a consequence of the introduction of machines,
auf dem Warenmarkt vorfinden, frei in dem Doppelsinn, dass er als
unemployment will rise and this will restock the labour force
freie Person über seine Arbeitskraft als seine Ware verfügt, dass er
market, enabling the capitalist to cut down labour prices, so
andrerseits andre Waren nicht zu verkaufen hat, los und ledig, frei
that labourers will be re-hired to work the machines at lower
ist von allen zur Verwirklichung seiner Arbeitskraft nötigen Sa-
wages than the ones they got before. It is a vicious cycle in
chen’ (K 183). So the labourer finds himself with many skills
which only the capitalist ever wins because he holds the key
and much labour power but with no way or means to put
to both resources and means of production.
these skills and this force to work. What good is your skill at
The overall result of this capitalist system for human beings
baking bread if you do not have an oven? This means that
is what Marx has famously called alienation. Alienation is
the labourer may be free in theory, but to the extent that he
not just a subjective perception but an objective state of af-
is poor, he will still be forced to submit to the capitalist. The
fairs that consists of three factors. First, the worker is alien-
labourers ‘must both be able to work for capitalists and need
ated from the product he makes. His labour or work produc-
to. They acquiesce in their own exploitation only because
es a product over which he has no control: once it is made,
they have no alternative. They cannot work for themselves
it belongs to the capitalist. The worker cannot take it home
as they have nothing to work on or with, no land or other
with him. He simply invests his labour and is then separated
resources. Thus they must hire our their labour power to
from it. As a result, we rarely think of the world as created
the highest bidder’ (Wolff 2002: 73). Capitalists will take
by humans. We fail to see the human labour expended in
advantage of the enormous amount of labour force avail-
bringing it about because we are not even aware of the way
able on the market to keep the prices for labour low. This
our own labour has been invested in this world. The second
can be maintained as long as the price for labour does not
element of alienation is the division of labour which results
fall beneath subsistence wages, which is the ‘Minimalgrenze
in a de-skilling of the worker, who only needs to mechani-
des Werts’ (K 187). If it does fall below this minimum, labour
cally repeat the same action over and over. This kind of work
303
304
is repetitive, numbing, and depressing. It reduces the worker
ten find it nearly impossible to verbalise and share their pain
to an element in a machine. Finally, there is alienation from
with others. ‘Physical pain does not simply resist language
our species-being. Here we reach the most fundamental
but actively destroys it, bringing about an immediate rever-
presupposition of Marx’s philosophy: man creates the world
sion to a state anterior to language, to the sounds and cries
in which he lives. Animals also create a world, but only to
a human being makes before language is learned’ (BP 4). This
the extent that their instincts incite them to build a nest or
reversion is due to the fact that pain ‘has no referential con-
other requirements for survival and reproduction. Man goes
tent. It is not of or for anything. It is precisely because it takes
far beyond the necessary changes required for subsistence.
no object that it, more than any other phenomenon, resists
For example, humans also embellish the world and make
objectification in language’ (BP 5). Pain, Scarry writes, ‘is it-
art. These world-changing activities are what makes humans
self alone’ (BP 162). Thus to have pain is to be locked inside
human. It is Marx’s belief that work under capitalism de-
one’s body. This is also a form of alienation from the self
stroys this world-making capacity. Capitalism limits our free
because ‘the person in great pain experiences his own body
ability to shape ourselves and the world because it makes
as the agent of his agony. The ceaseless, self-announcing
our work subservient to the needs of capital. This way it per-
signal of the body in pain [...] contains not only the feeling
verts our very humanity. In light of this it should come as no
“my body hurts” but the feeling “my body hurts me”’ (BP 47).
surprise that Marx claims that ‘many of us feel human only
Pain leaves no room for the self because ‘the pain itself is
when we are not working’ (Wolff 2002: 36): ‘Der Arbeiter fühlt
felt from the inside where, by appropriating all attention, it
sich daher erst ausser der Arbeit bei sich und in der Arbeit ausser
has become total [...]. Pain sabotages and subverts person-
sich. Zu Hause ist er, wenn er nicht arbeitet und wenn er arbeitet,
hood.’ That is why Scarry calls pain ‘the monolithic destroyer
ist er nicht zu Hause’ (Marx 2005: 59).
of persons’ (Scarry 1994: 31): ‘as the body becomes the only world, so pain becomes the only body’ (o.c. 34).
The Brutality of Fact
The felt experience of pain explains why torture is such a
But it is not only exploitation that alienates us. The analysis
powerful political tool. By torturing people, one takes away
of commodity fetishism and its projection of value can also
their world. This is done in many small and less small ways.
be extended into an analysis of the way the experience of
If a chair is an extension of the spine, relieving it from the
pain can destroy our world. Scarry has analysed the world-
burden of carrying the body, then kicking a chair from under
destroying power of pain in chilling detail. People who suf-
a prisoner is an efficient way of undermining the prisoner’s
fer extreme pain retreat into themselves and gradually lose
trust in the world. What was once comfortable and reliable,
interest in the world. According to Scarry, this regression has
now becomes a source of pain and uncertainty. Similarly,
to do with the “unsharability” of pain, which is linked to “its
giving prisoners spoiled food to eat and brackish water to
resistance to language”. This means that people in pain of-
drink not only makes them sick, which is temporary, but
305
306
undermines their faith in the essentially beneficial and
ternalisation) are wholly self-isolating. Only in the culture
life-giving qualities of food and, especially, water. And this
of language, ideas, and objects does sharing originate’ (BP
is a much less temporary intrusion into a person’s sense of
256). It is through language, through voice, that we com-
world. Finally, to actually inflict pain, often debilitating pain,
mune with mankind, not through our body. In fact, our body
to disorient the victim, or to make them feel as if they are
can (be used to) impose limits on this voice if it is made to
drowning, or to expose them to extreme changes in temper-
feel extreme pain. It is, however, not through our bodies but
ature, or to extreme and disturbing sounds: all these actions
through our voice that we share the world with other human
undermine a person’s ability to extend themselves into the
beings, for ‘so long as one is speaking, the self extends out
world. They withdraw upon themselves and, sooner or later,
beyond the boundaries of the body, occupies a space larger
they break. Efficient torture can bring a person on the brink
than the body’ (BP 33). So speech is revealed to probably
of psychosis in a matter of hours. But we need not even turn
be an even more fundamental form of world-making than
to torture to see the world-destroying power that people can
the collective efforts of work. ‘Through his ability to project
wield over others. There is an unsettling Wolfgang Tillmans
words and sounds out into his environment, a human being
photograph called Anti-homeless device (2000). It shows a
inhabits, humanises, and makes his own a space much larg-
homeless man sleeping on the sidewalk outside a building.
er than that occupied by his body alone’ (BP 49). This neces-
But he cannot huddle up against the wall of the building
sarily leads us back to Arendt’s claim that it is action, which
because the tiles that line the wall are featured with pyra-
usually leaves no material trace, that distinguishes humans
mid-like spikes that make it impossible to walk, let alone
from other animals. The activity of speaking to other people
sleep on them. Such features, which are part of the way the
and engaging them in debate about the shared world is what
system structures our shared environment to induce desired
makes us human. By robbing people of this voice, pain de-
patterns of behaviour in us, show how viciously easy it is to
humanises people in a way that is very similar to, but even
turn part of our environment into something uninhabitable;
more destructive than, alienated labour: ‘the absence of pain
something anti-human.
is a presence of world; the presence of pain is the absence of
In view of the phenomenological structure of pain we must
world’ (BP 37).
also rethink the distinction between body and mind, be-
The felt experience of being incarcerated within the body by
tween public and private. ‘The notion that everyone is alike
pain is memorably expressed in the work of Francis Bacon
by having a body and that what differentiates one person
and Scarry has commented on the way his paintings exhibit
from another is the soul or intellect or personality can
the debilitating and world-destroying power of pain. Pain
mislead one into thinking that the body is “shared” and
destroys the boundaries between the inside and the outside
the other part is “private” when exactly the opposite is the
of the body and so causes ‘an almost obscene conflation of
case. The mute facts of sentience (deprived of cultural ex-
private and public. It brings with it all the solitude of abso-
307
308
lute privacy with none of its safety, all the self-exposure of
ness in the image that is achieved if one narrows the space
the utterly public with none of its possibility for camaraderie
around a figure by framing it. Bacon returns to the question
or shared experience. Artistic objectifications of pain often
while discussing the introduction of a hypodermic syringe
concentrate on this combination of isolation and exposure.
into the arm of a Lying Figure with Hypodermic Syringe (1963).
[...]. The solitary figure in the typical canvas of Francis Bacon
He explains that he painted the syringe ‘as a form of nail-
is made emphatically alone by his position on a dais, by an
ing the image more strongly into reality or appearance. [...]
arbitrary geometric box inserted over him, and by his naked
I put the syringe because I want a nailing of the flesh onto
presence against a uniform (and in its uniformity, almost
the bed’ (o.c. 78). This explanation simply shifts the problem
absolute) orange-red background; yet while he is intensely
to the area of reality and appearance, two very important
separate from the viewer [...] he is simultaneously merciless-
notions that Bacon uses in a very specific way. Bacon con-
ly exposed to us [...] because his melting body is turned in-
sidered his art to be a realistic art, painting images ‘as ac-
side out, revealing the most inward and secret parts of him’
curately off my nervous system as I can’ (o.c. 82). This means
(BP 53). The sense of extreme alienation that pain entails is
that realism for Bacon is related to expressiveness and not
also expressed in the motif of the scream: ‘the open mouth
to representational fidelity in painting. He illustrates this by
with no sound reaching anyone in the sketches, paintings, or
contrasting an illustrational style of painting, which ‘tells
film stills of Grünewald, Stanzione, Munch, Bacon, Bergman,
you through the intelligence immediately what the form is
or Eisenstein, a human being so utterly consumed in the act
about,’ with a non-illustrational way of painting where ‘form
of making a sound that cannot be heard, coincides with the
works first upon sensation and then slowly leaks back into
way in which pain engulfs the one in pain but remains un-
the fact’ (o.c. 56). If this non-illustrational manner is suc-
sensed by anyone else’ (BP 52).
cessful it gives you more than a mere likeness of a person: it
Despite the fact that many critics have read Bacon’s work
gives you their appearance, it reveals something about who
this way, the artist himself was not very hospitable to such
they are and how they experience the world. This is where
an interpretation. As early as 1962, talking to David Sylvester,
the deformation of the figures comes in because ‘I’m always
he dismisses the idea that the frames in his work should be
hoping to deform people into appearance; I can’t paint them
read as glass boxes in which the figures are imprisoned. ‘I
literally. For instance, I think that, of those two paintings of
use that frame to see the image,’ Bacon claims, ‘for no other
Michel Leiris [Portrait of Michel Leiris, 1976 and 1978 respec-
reason. [...] I cut down the scale of the canvas by drawing
tively], the one I did which is less literally like him is in fact
rectangles which concentrate the image down. Just to see it
more poignantly like him’ (o.c. 146).
better’ (Sylvester 1987: 22-23). It remains somewhat unclear
From a Langerian point of view such remarks are very inter-
what Bacon means by “seeing better” but presumably he is
esting because they show how close Bacon’s working meth-
talking about an enhanced vividness and increased direct-
ods and his ideas about them were to Langer’s theory of
309
310
expressive form. ‘Every form that you make has an implica-
have an overall image of what I want to do, but it’s in the
tion,’ Bacon explains, ‘so that when you are painting some-
working that it develops’. Talking to David Sylvester Bacon
body, you know that you are, of course, trying to get near
has further explained that ‘I don’t really think my pictures
not only to their appearance but also to the way they have
out, you know; I think of the disposition of the forms and
affected you, because every shape has an implication’ (o.c.
then I watch the forms form themselves’ (o.c. 136). In an-
130). Chance plays a considerably part in the process of mak-
other interview, discussing his habit of rubbing paint with
ing such works. As is well known, Bacon would sometimes
pieces of cloth, Bacon remarks that in such gestures he is
simply throw paint at a canvas and work from the accidental
trying ‘to break the willed articulation of the image, so that
patterns that this created. But no matter how much coinci-
the image will grow, as it were, spontaneously and within its
dence and accidental elements are incorporated into a work,
own structure, and not my structure. Afterwards, your sense
it is always a moment of conscious deliberation that deter-
of what you want comes into play, so that you begin to work
mines its success as a work. ‘It’s really a continuous question
on the hazard that has been left to you on the canvas. And
of the fight between accident and criticism. Because what I
out of all that, possibly, a more organic image arises than if it
call accident may give you some mark that seems to be more
was a willed image’ (o.c. 160).
real, truer to the image than another one, but it’s only your
The aim of this to and fro between accident and criticism
critical sense that can select it. So that your critical faculty is
is expressiveness, which Bacon calls appearance. It is also
going on at the same time as the sort of half-conscious ma-
‘what I think of as art. One brings the sensation and the
nipulation’ (o.c. 121-122). The critical sense, however, is not
feeling of life over the only way one can’ (o.c. 43). Foreshad-
an objective faculty and it has ‘no defined criteria; it’s a pure-
owing the end of artistic narratives as proclaimed by Danto,
ly instinctive kind of criticism’ (o.c. 149) which can be justifi-
Bacon adds that ‘when you’re outside a tradition, as every
ably linked to Langer’s idea of the commanding form, which
artist is today, one can only want to record one’s own feel-
is a constant measure for the work being created without
ings about certain situations as closely to one’s own nervous
being an objective standard that exists outside the creative
system as one possibly can’ (ibid.). Such suggestions are very
process. This means, in fact, that the critical function that
close to Langer’s philosophy of living form. Expressiveness
Bacon talks about is simply the fact that the creative process
in art is the creation of a symbolic form that represents the
is continually self-reflexive, holding up everything it brings
felt experience of life. This would seem to be exactly what
about to the standard of the commanding form that draws
Bacon was aiming at in bringing together accident and criti-
the lines beyond which the form would loose its expressive
cism. And although Bacon seemed keen on minimising the
power. This is further corroborated by Bacon’s own descrip-
anxiety expressed through his distortions, undoubtedly
tion of the creative process. In an interview with Melvyn
wanting to stress their formal properties, it is clear that their
Bragg for the South Bank Show (1988) Bacon explains that ‘I
precarious position between form and feeling is an effect
311
312
of their immense success as forms. It is because they are so
says that when the eye sees something beautiful, the hand
well-achieved through criticism that they become expressive
wants to draw it. Beauty brings copies of itself into being’
of the person represented and become this person’s appear-
(BBJ 3). This experience can give rise to ‘the idea of eternity,
ance. This all becomes quite clear in Bacon’s own description
the perpetual duplicating of a moment that never stops. But
of the difficulty inherent in painting portraits: ‘The living
it also sponsors the idea of terrestrial plenitude and distri-
quality is what you have to get. In painting a portrait the
bution, the will to make “more and more” so that there will
problem is to find a technique by which you can give over
eventually be “enough”’ (BBJ 5). The urge to produce beautiful
all the pulsations of a person. It’s why portrait painting is
things (and not just soulless commodities) is a fundamental
so fascinating and so difficult. Most people go to the most
human need, as Marx and Langer also suggested. And once
academic painters when they want to have their portraits
beauty is in the world it sponsors a continual reproduction
made because for some reason they prefer a sort of colour
of itself. ‘The simplest manifestation of this phenomenon
photograph of themselves instead of thinking of having
is the everyday fact of staring’ (ibid.). As an example, Scarry
themselves really trapped and caught. The sitter is someone
cites Leonardo da Vinci’s habit of following beautiful people
of flesh and blood and what has to be caught is their ema-
through the streets of Florence. Another example is the
nation. [...] There is the appearance and there is the energy
desire of people in love to have children together because
within the appearance. And that is an extremely difficult
‘when the eye sees someone beautiful, the whole body wants
thing to trap’ (o.c. 174-175).
to reproduce the person’ (BBJ 4). Lovers are forever seeking each other’s distinctive facial features in the face of their
The Quickening
child, which is the physical continuation of what they love in
Elaine Scarry has followed her philosophical investigations
their partner.
into pain with reflections on aesthetics. This is not as big a
It is interesting to note that Scarry’s suggestion about the
leap as it might seem. Especially in her beautiful little book
unceasing repetition of the beautiful can be linked to Kant’s
On Beauty and Being Just (1999) Scarry explains how beauty
idea of purposiveness without purpose. This is the third mo-
makes us aware of the preciousness and vulnerability of the
ment in the aesthetic judgement, where Kant writes that
world and all things in it. Through this awareness beauty
the experience of beauty, as felt experience, has no goal or
invites us to extend human sympathy to lifeless things that
purpose other than to perpetuate itself. When we experience
suddenly appear to us as “hurtable” as human beings. Let
beauty we want to make that moment last. A good example
us track this argument step by step. ‘What,’ Scarry asks, ‘is
is the difficulty we often have to tear ourselves away from
the felt experience of cognition at the moment one stands
a beautiful work of art in an exhibition. We compulsively
in the presence of a beautiful boy or flower or bird? It seems
return to it, unable to satiate our desire to be in its presence.
to incite, even require, the act of replication. Wittgenstein
It is here that I believe the root of obsession can be found,
313
314
especially with regard to voyeurism, the obsession with look-
become aware of an object’s vulnerability and to experience
ing at things that quicken us. The urge to repeat or maintain
an urge to protect the object perceived as vulnerable. ‘A vase
the sensation of being engulfed by sensual rapture is noth-
crafted by Gallé [...] can, although nonsentient, be harmed by
ing other than an attempt to maintain this purposiveness
being mishandled. Noticing its beauty increases the possibil-
without purpose. The voyeur, or any other fetishist, will often
ity that it will be carefully handled’ (BBJ 65). This increased
collect a library of images and experiences that he may draw
awareness of the ease with which things can be hurt and the
upon in future fantasies. That is why such fetishes become
demand for care that this awareness entails are the effect
addictive: they are in need of constant new input, as in
of all experiences of beauty, which leads Scarry to conclude
pornography’s constant flow of new faces and new starlets,
that ‘the concern demanded by the perfect vase or god or
which is reminiscent of beauty’s capacity for bringing copies
poem [introduces] a standard of care that [is then extended]
of itself into the world. The fetishist never reaches a point
to more ordinary objects’ (BBJ 66). By noticing beauty we
where he feels fulfilled: there is always the possibility of a
notice vulnerability and start noticing it everywhere and not
more exciting, more profound experience to collect. For the
just in the objects traditionally categorised as beautiful. ‘It is
fetishist, as for the aesthete who loves to surround himself
as though beautiful things have been placed here and there
with beauty, there can never be enough beauty. Even a world
throughout the world to serve as small wake-up calls to
of plenty is never enough. But there is no perversion in this
perception, spurring lapsed alertness back to its most acute
obsession: it is the very dynamic of creation, the same dy-
level. Through its beauty, the world continually recommits us
namic that propels the continual production of new goods
to a rigorous standard of perceptual care: if we do not search
that continue to find new purchasers in the market. As long
it out, it comes and finds us’ (BBJ 81). That is why beauty
as there are beautiful things to look at or to buy, there will be
can be found anywhere and everywhere. Beauty is not an
people wanting to look or buy.
abstract Idea, it is everywhere apparent, in ‘the moon, the
One of Scarry’s aims in her book is to deflate the politically
Milky Way, individual stars, the daylit sky, birds, birdsongs,
correct claim that it is aggressive, demeaning, or otherwise
musical instruments, meadows, dances, woven cloth, stones,
hurtful or simply wrong to look at beautiful people or things
staircases, good prose certainly, airplanes of course, math-
because to look or stare at them is (among other evil things)
ematical proofs, the sea, its surf, its spray’ (BBJ 72).
to objectify them. This is the spectre of the infamous “male
Beauty is the world’s way of reaching out to us. And by
gaze,” a rapacious ocular predator that ravages all it lays its
making us aware of the vulnerability of people and things,
greedy little eyes on. ‘Beauty, according to its critics, causes
beauty ‘assists us in our attention to justice’ (BBJ 86) because
us to gape and suspend all thought. This complaint is mani-
it makes clear to us that it is important to treat all people,
festly true’ (BBJ 29). But there is nothing wrong with this
all creatures, and all objects with care and fairness. ‘Beauty
because to notice beauty and to stare at it in admiration is to
seems to place requirements on us for attending to the alive-
315
316
ness or (in the case of objects) quasi-aliveness of our world,
cess should really be extended to include the entire human
and for entering into its protection’ (BBJ 90). The importance
world. As extensions of ourselves the objects in the world
of this quasi-aliveness for our argument is dual. On the one
come to share in our humanity and in our emotions. This is
hand, it refers us back to Scarry’s own argument, made in
made very clear in Alexander Kluge’s mammoth cinematic
The Body in Pain, that the world we make is an extension of
essay Nachrichten aus der ideologischen Antike (2008), which
our own body and therefore shares in its aliveness. But it is
investigates Sergei Eisenstein’s failed attempt to film Marx’s
quasi- or only seeming aliveness because paintings, books,
Kapital in 1927. The second part of Kluge’s film is called Alle
and other objects of beauty are not, as a rule, actual living
Dinge sind bezauberte Menschen, which expresses the idea
entities (but flowers, birds, and beautiful boys are). On the
that the line between subject and object is blurred because
other hand the quasi-aliveness of beautiful objects (which is
we invest part of our humanity in the things we make. At
in fact a pleonasm as it is their quasi-aliveness that renders
several points in his film Kluge shows that objects can also
objects beautiful) is simply a restating of the principle of liv-
project their humanity back at us. In the chapter Lamento der
ing form proposed by Langer. As we remember, living form is
liegengebliebenen Ware he describes how the composer Wolf-
expressive of the felt experience of life. Beauty is intrinsical-
gang Rihm was struck by the sight of a bottle left behind on
ly linked to aliveness. Through these two meanings of quasi-
the shelves of a supermarket. It made him notice the sad-
aliveness, a dual dynamic lights up: the perceiver and the
ness of unsold goods that are sent back to the manufacturer
object of beauty perceived mutually bestow life upon each
to be destroyed. Many goods remain unsold, loved by no
other. The perceiver is a human being, who takes part in
one, and are therefore deemed useless and dispensable. This
the continual making of the world, which invests the world
continual destruction of perfectly good goods is a daily holo-
with quasi-aliveness and therefore the potential for beauty.
caust, for with each object a piece of humanity is destroyed.
The beautiful object perceived in turn reflects the projected
There is a profound sadness in waste. This melancholy of
aliveness and its concomitant beauty back at us as a symbol
the objects is expressed and given voice in Rihm’s Lamento.
of the felt experience of life that is the stuff of beauty. If this
Even more clear is Kluge’s chapter on Max Brand’s industrial
process seems circular, its circularity is not a weakness but
opera Maschinist Hopkins (1929), which has the abandoned
its essence: all meaning is created by human beings, there-
machines in a nocturnal factory lament their servile exis-
fore there is no meaning, and no beauty, in the world which
tence as slaves to the production process. By giving voice to
is not in our consciousness, in our mind. Man is constitutive
the machines, Brand’s opera brings their spirit back to life,
of beauty. The world is how we reflect this beauty back at
extending it into the world to appeal to our human compas-
each other. To destroy beauty is to destroy mankind.
sion. But if Brand’s opera tries to give voice to objects in their
Children are very happy to bestow aliveness on inanimate
quasi-aliveness, then German band Einstürzende Neubauten
objects. They do it all the time with their toys. But the pro-
go one better: they actually extract voice from the objects
317
318
themselves. As they put it in their song ‘NNNAAAMMM’,
gut in a knot and makes us tremble with anxious or grateful
songs simply lie dormant in machines (‘das Lied schläft in
anticipation. It quickens the pulse and wreaks havoc upon
der Maschine’) and it is up to us to wake them up and make
our bodily functions. Reflexes become uncontrollable, people
them sing. The music of the Neubauten is like an extended
tremble, some shudder or shiver, others break out in hyster-
urban symphony conjured up from the inanimate waste of
ics of tears or laughter, our eyes go blurry, and we gener-
so-called civilisation and its destructive industry. Especially
ally feel our mind contracting like a sponge, with a strange,
their early music was often extremely aggressive and atonal,
stinging sensation in the lower neck: the control over our
an explosion of anger at the world, an aural manifesto of re-
body eludes us and yet the sensation is vaguely pleasurable.
jection, isolation, and alienation. Many of these soundscapes
Obviously, not all experiences of sudden aliveness have such
were created by relentless banging or scraping on scrap
an intensity; it would in fact be most detrimental to the
metal or debris, or simply by drilling into concrete. But mak-
orderly practice of everyday life if they were. But it is clear
ing art out of refuse, as the Neubaten do, implies a cyclical
that apart from forms of beauty that have a very general
view of the world: to appropriate the rejected and turn it into
attraction (the beauty of roses, say) there is for each person
poetry is to salvage humanity from destruction and bring it
a realm of quickening which is highly idiosyncratic, deeply
back into the shared world.
personal, and profoundly private.
We are now sufficiently prepared to answer the question
These private sensations are entirely legitimate as the stuff
what exactly triggers the experience of beauty in us: it is that
of beauty and art. As we saw in our discussion of Langer,
which quickens, which gives us a jolt of life. To experience
such private interests are legitimate and often even neces-
beauty is to experience a quickening, a sudden uplifting and
sary as motifs in art: they are transformed into something
invigorating gust of aliveness and its concomitant assent
artistic if they are integrated into the fabric of an expressive
to the world. For a brief moment (or, if we are lucky and the
form, lifted up from a symptom of experience to a symbol of
sensation is particularly intense, an extended period of time)
life. That is why the private role-play of mistress and slave
we feel reconciled to the world. Obviously, what quickens
in the bedroom is usually not considered to be a work of art,
one person is not necessarily what quickens another. Many
whereas Sacher-Masoch’s novel Venus in Furs (1869) or Hans
things may give many people a sense of enhanced aliveness,
Bellmer’s obsessively lurid photographs of his obscenely
but some such jolts are bound to be highly personal. One
twisted sex-doll are: they are not (or not primarily) about
of the most intimate experiences of enhanced aliveness is
private gratification for the artist. In creating such images
the electrifying effect of a sexual fetish, which is more than
the artist is not seeking sexual release. On the contrary, the
mere arousal: the sudden presence of the object of our deep-
creation of the image might even require the artist not to
est fetish (be it a piece of clothing, a shoe, the exposure of a
release any tension, so that he may work in a mood of hight-
body-part, a scent, a situation, or a word whispered) ties the
ened alertness bordering on the feverish. But if he is not
319
320
releasing or gratifying his sexual desire, he is expressing it
ever level of intensity it operates, it is a fuse that is being lit
in a symbolic way, which is to say that he is articulating it:
and that gets, as is said colloquially, our juices flowing. But
presenting its many moments and aspects in a unified image
the colloquialism is very apt, for the quickening is indeed
that aims to express the felt experience of the actual fetish-
a biological process: at the very least, it is a mild release of
istic sensation. As I argued in the previous chapter, the pres-
adrenaline or some other chemical into the bloodstream.
ence of actually aroused performers in pornographic films
And once the jolt is delivered it is the hand, as Wittgenstein
(or, we might add, in theatrical presentations in an erotic
noted, or the imagination that takes over. That this dyna-
cabaret) has often blinded critics to the artistic potential of
mism is sometimes born from our most private sentiments
such films. There is nothing inartistic about pornography, it
and desires is no blight: all art arises from felt experience.
is simply a sad fact that most pornography is abysmally bad.
What lifts it up into the realm of art is the genius of concep-
But in good pornography the aroused bodies are integrated
tion: the artist’s ability to translate something personal into
into the greater work of the film (which may be a success-
a symbol of potentially universal appeal. And this, inciden-
ful work of art or, as is often the sad case, a dismal failure).
tally, again chimes with what Kant wrote in his critique of
Similarly, the erotic dancers performing as strippers are not
aesthetic judgement: that our judgement on beauty is at
as a rule aroused while performing: it is work to them. The
the same time subjective and universal. The paradox was
stripper must control her own desires to achieve the erotic
resolved, for Kant, by pointing out that the subjectivity of our
dance as a work of art, which is a performance.
judgement was impartial, not tainted by any personal inter-
This, then, I would argue to be the nature of fascination: the
est, and therefore immediately entailed the illusion (and it is
sustained gripping force of an object or form that delivers a
an illusion for Kant, who calls it an als ob) of universality. In
jolt of aliveness to our physical or psychical system. Fascina-
our view, which builds on the Kantian tradition, the personal
tion is a quickening that sets the mind and the imagination
and the universal are linked through the genius of concep-
on their way on a journey of endless repetition of and varia-
tion: the work of art that lifts the particular up to make it
tions on the particular motif or form that triggers our most
into a potentially universal symbol of life vitally felt.
profound sense of vitality and thus enhances our felt experience of aliveness. It can be modest, as when we notice the
The Order of Things
first flowers of spring or the scent of rain on a hot summer
With fascination we have entered a part of our being that is
night, but it can also be a fierce and terrific jolt, as when we
often experienced as dark and unruly. It is linked to sexual-
are suddenly in the presence of our deepest sexual fetish or
ity and its hidden urges. We have entered the realm of the
an object of overwhelming beauty. Whether beauty is over-
uncontrollable. There are many things in life that we cannot
whelming is simply a function of the intensity of the sense
control. To be surrendered to events or forces that are be-
of aliveness it triggers in us. But whatever it is and on what-
yond our grasp often feels like submission to some kind of
321
322
violence. The uncontrollable is a force that manifests itself,
work in it. So to be kosmos is to be logos, to be orderly is to
it exerts power over us and we are unable to get away from
be governed by some rule, and the rule is the order (Peters
it. Anything that affects our being in a profound way with-
1967: 111). But that there is such a rule does not mean that
out our being able to master or direct it is a manifestation
we, mere mortals, can grasp it. That is the rupture we ex-
of the uncontrollable. In this sense the uncontrollable is not
perience in the intrusion of the unruly into our lives: there
simply an act of violence that disrupts our life or the order of
is something out there, a kosmos, that does not operate ac-
society, it is often perceived as a meaningless interruption:
cording to our human logos. There is alter-logos at work in
it is an act or an event that literally has no place in the order
the world. It is the function of rituals to remedy the rupture
that we have created for ourselves. That is why the uncon-
of kosmos by the violence of the uncontrollable. Whenever
trollable is often situated in those aspects of human life that
we experience such a rupture, we feel as if the logos of the
are particularly difficult to contain. The Greeks called it Fate,
kosmos is suddenly in retreat, beyond our grasp. We fail to
others call it destiny. In our mass democracies there is much
see the logic or order of events in the broader whole of our
talk of the threat of random violence. It is exactly its unpre-
meaningful existence. Rituals are ways to try and represent
dictable nature and the fact that it can strike at any time and
that violence as something that we can comprehend after
that any of us can be its victim that makes random violence
all. They give violence a controllable place in the order of
such a fearful thing. In the aftermath of the attacks of Sep-
things. Rituals represent violence to make it containable and
tember 11, 2001, it sometimes seemed as if a mass psychosis
imaginable as part of the larger whole of existence or kosmos.
had overtaken the world: we were all in danger, all possibly
That way it seeks to tame the violence of the uncontrol-
under attack, but nobody could be sure when or where or
lable. This means that rituals are a form of symbolic action:
against whom violence would strike. However, the locus clas-
they are actions that have a symbolic function. As we saw
sicus of the uncontrollable is obviously human sexuality. Sex
already in the first chapter, a symbol is ‘any device whereby
is an urge that manifests itself in our body without invita-
we are enabled to make an abstraction’ (FF xi). So rituals are
tion. And once it is there, it is very difficult to resist.
schematised actions that are expressive of meaning, they are
People introduce rituals to try and give the violence of the
abstract representations of our felt experience of life. The felt
unexpected, the unpredictable, and the uncontrollable some
experience expressed in ritual is the irruption of the violence
place within the social order. Another way of putting this is
of the uncontrollable and our desire to restore the kosmos. In
to say that rituals are attempts to give violence a place in the
this sense rituals are expressive of what we feel is our place
kosmos. For the ancient Greeks the kosmos was not simply the
in the universe and our relationship to the kosmos. They
entirety of all existence, the word also referred to order or
express our relationship to a higher order that eludes our
logos. The kosmos as the system of the entire existing world
control. By expressing that relationship the ritual helps us
was perceived to be logos, reasonable. There was a logic at
to accept it and integrate it into the fabric of our lives. This,
323
324
in essence, is the root meaning of “religious,” which refers to
that of communication’ (Burkert 1983: 23). He returns to this
the Latin religio or bondage to a higher Power.
point several times and his discussion is very corroborative
Rituals serve absolutely no practical use. Rituals, and by ex-
of Langer’s approach. ‘Ritual is a pattern of action redirected
tension all symbolic actions (including art), do not contribute
to serve for communication, and this means that the terms
to the survival of the species, although we have suggested
of expression are open to substitution, i.e., symbolisation.
that they are inscribed into the very nature of the human
[...] Every communication is symbolic inasmuch as it does
animal, which is a creature of expression. Nor do rituals
not use the real object it wants to communicate, but sub-
have any real impact on the world. Offerings to the gods,
stitutes a sign that is familiar to and, hence, understood by
ritual dance, magic charms, works of art: all these are expres-
the addressee. The object serving as sign is exchangeable.
sions of our felt experience and our desires, but they have no
If the sender and the receiver are sufficiently familiar with
practical value whatsoever. As Langer has correctly pointed
one another, the complex of signs can be greatly reduced. On
out, ‘no savage tries to induce a snowstorm in midsummer,
the other hand, when in competition with rival communi-
nor prays for the ripening of fruits entirely out of season,
cations, the sign is exaggerated and heightened. Substitute
as he certainly would if he considered his dance and prayer
signs thus used – whether consisting of natural or artificial
the physical causes of such events. He dances with the rain,
objects, pictures, cries, or words – may be called symbols in
he invites the elements to do their part, as they are thought
a pregnant sense’ (o.c. 41). So ritual is a symbolic action and
to be somewhere about and merely unresponsive. This ac-
‘its function is to dramatise the order of life, expressing itself
counts for the fact that no evidence of past failures discour-
in basic modes of behaviour, especially aggression’ (o.c. 33).
ages his practices; for if heaven and earth do not answer
There are three elements that are almost universal ingredi-
him, the rite is simply unconsummated; it was not therefore
ents of ritual: killing, eating, and sex (o.c. 58). This is hardly
a “mistake”’ (PNK 158-159). The Indian performing the rain
surprising since the triad goes to the core of human survival:
dance is not so naive to think that he can induce the rain
we must kill in order not to be killed, we must kill to eat, and
to fall, he simply expresses his own dependence upon the
we must procreate. Violence is inherent in all three elements
rain for his survival. So the purpose of rituals is not to attain
and is especially important in ritual because ‘a sense of com-
practical goals but ‘to symbolise great conceptions’ and ‘to
munity arises from collective aggression’ ( o.c. 35). But the
aid in the formulation of a religious universe’ (PNK 49). In his
ritual contains the violence (or the killing, or the sexuality)
anthropological study of ancient Greek ritual Walter Burk-
because it is made discontinuous with the ordinary world.
ert used a similar concept of ritual and symbolism. Burkert
‘In a sacrifice the circle of participants is segregated from the
explains that ‘biology has defined ritual as a behavioural
outside world. Complicated social structures find expression
pattern that has lost its primary function – present in its
in the diverse roles the participants assume in the course
unritualised model – but which persists in a new function,
of the ritual, from the various “beginnings,” through prayer,
325
326
slaughter, skinning, and cutting up, to roasting and, above
Similarly, a monk in his cell or an artist working in the se-
all, distributing the meat. There is a “lord of the sacrifice”
clusion of his studio may be profoundly isolated from the
who demonstrates his vitae necisque potestas [...]. And as for
outside world and yet not feel the least bit lonely. Isolation
the rest, each participant has a set function and acts ac-
is simply a physical circumstance, a situation in which we
cording to a precisely fixed order. The sacrificial community
find ourselves, usually only temporarily. Loneliness, on the
is thus a model of society as a whole’ (o.c. 37). In this sense
other hand, is an existential condition. To be lonely is to feel
rituals have a “cosmic” meaning: they express the order or
cast out of the company of mankind. When there is no-one
logos/kosmos of things. But despite their cosmic nature rituals
to turn to (despite the possible presence of a great many
often consist of very commonplace actions. Usually everyday
people), when one is entirely thrown back upon oneself, one
gestures and actions such as washing, preparing foods, eat-
feels lonely. That is why Arendt writes that loneliness ‘is
ing and drinking, the slaughter of an animal or even forms
closely connected with uprootedness and superfluousness
of sexual communion are chosen to figure in ritual. It is the
[...]. To be uprooted means to have no place in the world,
intimate familiarity of these actions that makes them eli-
recognised and guaranteed by others; to be superfluous
gible for ritual. But in ritual these actions lose their prosaic
means not to belong to the world at all’ (Arendt 1968: 475).
nature and acquire a new symbolic meaning. ‘Before a be-
Panajotis Kondylis has claimed that such an experience
haviour-pattern can become imbued with secondary mean-
of loneliness is part of the existential condition of man in
ings, it must be definite, and to the smallest detail familiar.
postmodern mass society. If we recall his master metaphor
Such forms are naturally evolved only in activities that are
for postmodernity, which is characterised by an analytical-
often repeated. An act that is habitually performed acquires an
combinatory mode of being, it was the image of an infinite
almost mechanical form, a sequence of motions that prac-
space, a plane on which all humans, all values, all ideas, and
tice makes quite invariable’ (PNK 160). It is only what is most
all objects are simultaneously present in total equality. It is
intimately known that can carry the force of new meanings
the condition of ultimate relativism. Every individual has the
without disintegrating.
fundamental right, but by extension also the fundamental
Rituals are used to symbolically heal a rupture between man
duty, to construct his own identity from the myriad choices
and his kosmos. This rupture is most acutely experienced as
available. However, there are no more master narratives (as
a form of profound loneliness. In The Origins of Totalitarian-
Danto would call them) to fall back upon for guidance in this
ism (1951) Hannah Arendt distinguished between loneliness
project. The individual is an atom left to its own devices in
and isolation. It is quite possible for us to be isolated without
the construction of his identity. Those of us who cannot cope
being lonely, just as we can be lonely without being isolated.
with the pressures of self-creation will perish. They are des-
We can experience abject loneliness in a crowd, where we
tined to loneliness, an existence without any kind of anchor-
are anything but isolated from our fellow human beings.
age in the world. Self-creation is a freedom that often entails
327
328
cruelty, for not only is it challenging and often paralysing to
is not a coincidence: as she would argue in her Lectures on
try and construct one’s identity, there is a veritable pressure
Kant’s Political Philosophy, which were published posthumous-
to do so, because everywhere in society we are constantly
ly, it is only our ability to share our experiences of the world
urged to identify ourselves and say who and what we are.
with others that makes our experiences, and therefore the
From our sexual identity to our tastes in music and furni-
world, real. This was also Kant’s belief in the first and third
ture: everything is now supposed to be highly individual and
critiques, where he suggests that the only reason we can
articulated. We must define ourselves. This is the burden and
even talk with each other is that we must have some kind of
terror of identity.
Gemeinsinn or common sense. For Kant this meant that the
Obviously, for Arendt it was the experience of the extermina-
structure of perception was the same in all humans. Because
tion camps that signified more than anything else the pro-
our minds all share the same categories to structure our sen-
foundly dissociative experience of the atomised individual.
sory experience, we all see the same world and can therefore
The people transported to the extermination camps were
talk to each other about that world. That is the source of
literally erased from the world, they were taken out of the
our companionship. Incidentally, it is also the source for his
communal world and placed in a non-place of which many
claim that a disinterested and universally valid judgement
Germans would later claim that they “had not even known”
on beauty was possible: if we look at the world disinterest-
such a place existed (or could exist). For the people in the
edly, and if we all perceive the world in the same way, then
camps the experience was dissociative because their world
it follows that we should all experience beauty in relation to
had been taken away from them, an existential condition
the same objects. Of course, Kant knew that this was false
that was exacerbated by the fact that they were also physi-
logic because it is our subjective felt experience of perception
cally tortured: their bodies were starved and humiliated,
that makes us claim beauty for an object. Therefore Kant
riddled with parasites; they were not allowed to keep their
said that the objective or universally valid nature of judge-
bodies clean; they were subjected to gruesome medical ex-
ments on beauty was only an “as if”-objectivity, an “als ob”.
periments; they were subjected to forced labour; and finally they were terminated like vermin. If we recall the discussion
Dionysian Mysteries
of The Body in Pain, it is clear that the extermination camps
The memory of the holocaust was still fresh in the German-
epitomise the strategies available to man to destroy another
speaking world when a group of young Viennese artists
person’s world entirely. As Arendt points out, only because
around 1960 began a series of controversial performances.
we share the world with others, ‘because we have common
Their actions were partly meant as a violent reaction against
sense, that is only because not one man, but men in the
the all-too-comfortable and constrained conformism of the
plural inhabit the earth can we trust our immediate sensual
1950s, when bourgeois Europe tried very hard to bounce
experience’ (o.c. 476). Arendt’s reference to common sense
through the atomic age as if there wasn’t a care, let alone
329
330
a Cold War, in the world. All was bliss in the new era of the
ful. For example, earlier scholars often too eagerly accepted
shiny nuclear family. Everyone was doing his utmost to for-
mythological accounts of Dionysian ritual found in literary
get there had ever been such a thing as a Second World War.
sources as reliable guides to actual ritual practice. More re-
But for many young people growing up in that stifled air of
cent scholarship has corrected this view, but many of the old
enforced optimism the violence of the holocaust was felt
misunderstandings about Dionysos and his revels remain
to be seething under the thin veneer of preppy brightness.
popular and are often repeated in non-academic books.
The Viennese actionists wanted, among other things, to let
Similarly, working in the 1960s and 1970s, some of the earlier
this violence erupt so that it might be faced and dealt with.
scholarship has found its way into Nitsch’s thinking about
The most well-known artists from this circle were Günter
Dionysian ritual. And since Nitsch’s project is artistic rather
Brus, Rudolf Schwarzkogler, Otto Mühl, and Hermann Nitsch.
than anthropological the artist is entitled to appropriate any
Since Schwarzkogler tragically took his own life in 1969 and
interpretation or motif he likes, regardless of whether it is
Mühl degenerated into sexually obsessed debauchery that
still anthropologically sound. Similarly, a scientific “debunk-
ultimately landed him in jail for sexual assault of a minor, it
ing” of Nitsch’s concept of Dionysian ritual would be quite
was left to Brus and Nitsch to represent what was best and
pointless and would merely illustrate a critic’s less than suf-
most enduring about Viennese Actionism. It is Nitsch who
ficient grasp of the difference between art and science. The
has in fact been the most visible and controversial artist of
main purpose of the present section is therefore to sketch
the group. His actions were often enacted in a ritual way,
a portrait of Dionysos and his ritual that helps to elucidate
including the slaughter of animals and the rubbing of naked
Nitsch’s art. While some references to recent scholarship will
human bodies with blood and entrails. The apparently ob-
point to common misinterpretations, such an anthropologi-
scene nature of his work often brought him to the attention
cal critique is not the point or purpose of this discussion. In
of the police, who raided several of his performances. In 1971
this sense the present discussion is necessarily and to a con-
Nitsch bought Prinzendorf, a large estate that enabled him to
siderable extent complicit with Nitsch’s interpretative eclec-
perform his large-scale works on his own private property.
ticism, if only because it is his vision that we seek to under-
Prinzendorf henceforth became the home of what Nitsch
stand and not the scientifically correct historical record.
calls his Orgien Mysterien Theater, a clear reference to the
Dionysos’ origins are cloaked in mystery. For a long time,
mystery cults of ancient Greece, notably the cult of Dio-
scholars thought he must have been a non-Greek god whose
nysos. But before we look at Dionysian ritual and the way
cult originated in what W.K.C. Guthrie calls ‘the homeland
it operates in Nitsch’s work, we should make clear that no
of orgiastic religion, Asia Minor’ (Guthrie 1954: 150). He was
such discussion of Dionysos could ever be straightforward.
therefore a barbarian god who had to be naturalised into
Since the mid-nineteenth century scholarship on Dionysos
the Hellenic pantheon, a process that was supposed to have
has taken many forms, several of which were rather fanci-
been accomplished by the fifth century BCE, when Eurip-
331
332
ides’ Bacchai offers us the fullest literary source of informa-
brought to life again, Dionysos was the god of rebirth, which
tion available about the Dionysian cults. However, Linear B
made him eligible as a fertility god, linked to the cycle of the
tablets found in Mycenaean palaces suggest that the cult of
seasons that shows nature dying and coming to life again.
Dionysos is probably as old as that of the other gods (Burk-
In this sense earth both brings forth life (which grows from
ert 1985: 162; Bowden 2010: 106). The mythological facts
it) and swallows it (the dead return to the earth). ‘Greatest
about Dionysos’ birth are somewhat obscure and two ma-
of Dionysian feasts was the Anthesteria, held in the month
jor accounts are known. In both the Iliad and the Theogony
of Anthesterion or January-February; it united Dionysos and
Dionysos is presented as the child of Zeus and Semele, the
the dead and expressed the dual function of the earth. It
daughter of Kadmos, king of Thebes. This makes Dionysos
also celebrated the opening of the new wine, for on the first
the only Olympian god to be born from a mortal (Gantz 1993:
day the huge jars were unsealed and on the second the par-
112). ‘According to the story, not wholly explained, of his
ticipants gathered to try it, each with his own pitcher (from
birth, Semele when pregnant with him was blasted by the
which the day was known as Choes, ‘Pitchers’). On the third
lightning. [...] Zeus saved his son by snatching him from her
day they cooked a panspermia, a mixture of seeds and fruits
womb and thrusting him into his own thigh until the time
of the earth, in pots that gave the day its special name of
came for his birth’ (Guthrie 1954: 153). The second version
Chytroi’ (Kirk 1974: 230). Among the many other Dionysian
of the events surrounding Dionysos’ birth belongs to an Or-
festivals the most well-known are undoubtedly the ‘Oscho-
phic tradition and claims that Dionysos was the son of Zeus
phoria, the “Branch-carrying”: a procession set out from one
and his own daughter Persephone. This version entails a
of Dionysos’ sanctuaries in Athens and made its way to a
myth about the origin of mankind that is linked to ‘the kill-
shrine of Athena by the sea; it was led by two boys dressed
ing of Dionysos by the Titans, the old giants who were the
as girls and carrying vine-branches and grapes’ (o.c. 232).
enemies of the gods of Zeus’ generation. They gave toys to
Dionysos, and later his Roman counterpart Bacchus, was ex-
the infant god, and while his attention was thus distracted
pressly known as the god of wine and Caravaggio famously
set on him, killed him and feasted on his flesh. Zeus hurled
painted the god as a sickly jaundiced young man crowned
a thunderbolt to burn them up, and from the soot arose the
with vine-branches. In Homer and Hesiod the references
race of men. [...] The heart of Dionysos was saved by Athena.
to Dionysos as the god of wine are scarce (Gantz 1993: 114;
She brought it to Zeus, and from it he caused Dionysos to be
Guthrie 1954: 164). But it has been suggested that Dionysos
reborn’ (o.c. 319-320). Another version of this tradition claims
brought the gift of wine with him from his many wanderings
that it was Demeter who put the pieces of the boy back to-
in the East (Graves 1960: I, 27.b, p. 104).
gether (Gantz 1993: 113).
The two most characteristic and sensational aspects associ-
The story of Dionysos’ birth and childhood misadventures
ated with Dionysian cult are undoubtedly sparagmos and
explains much about his rituals. For, having died and been
omophagia, respectively ‘the tearing to pieces, and swallowing
333
334
raw, of an animal body’ (Dodds 1951: 276). Sparagmos means
captured in free-standing sculpture by the fourth century
that the worshippers tore sacrificial animals from limb to
artist Scopas.
limb, often scattering the pieces around. Several myths tes-
The practice of omophagia, the eating of the raw sacrificial
tify to the way Dionysos took terrific vengeance upon cities
flesh, was a logical consequence of enthusiasm, which is
or peoples who rejected his worship. Usually, ‘the god’s ven-
the experience of the god entering the worshipper’s body.
geance takes the form of visiting with madness the women
According to Professor Guthrie ‘the culminating point of the
of the land where he has been spurned. This usually leads to
rite was often the eating of a newly slain animal who was
their tearing a victim in pieces, either the king who has been
thought to embody the god. By imbibing the fresh life-blood,
the god’s opponent, or, when the women themselves have
the visible, physical form or symbol of deity, the worship-
been the offenders, one of their own children’ (Guthrie 1954:
per believed himself to acquire the spirit, strength, holiness
165-166). The chief participants in Dionysian ritual appear to
or whatever of the divine characteristics was most desired’
have been women because ‘the greatest gift of Dionysos was
(Guthrie 1954: 45). In this sense the practice expresses what
the sense of utter freedom, and in Greece it was the women,
professor Dodds calls ‘a very simple piece of savage logic.
with their normally confined and straitened lives, to whom
The homeopathic effects of a flesh diet are known all over
the temptation of release made the strongest appeal’ (o.c.
the world. If you want to be lion-hearted, you must eat lion;
148). This release was taken to excessive extremes, culminat-
if you want to be subtle, you must eat snake [...]. By parity of
ing in ekstasis, which literally means ‘standing outside one-
reasoning, if you want to be like god you must eat god [...].
self,’ and enthousiasmos or possession by the god. This pos-
And you must eat him quick and raw, before the blood has
session is expressed in uncontrolled raving (baccheia). In their
oozed from him: only so can you add his life to yours, for
ravings women would dance frantically in movements that
“the blood is the life”’ (Dodds 1951: 277). But this is a roman-
express what Camille Paglia has called ‘a rupturing extremi-
ticised vision of Dionysian ritual. Recent scholarship sug-
ty of torsion’ (Paglia 1991: 94), tossing their heads and expos-
gests that the eating of raw sacrifical meat was mainly the
ing their throats as if trying to extend their bodies to the full-
stuff of myth and that it occurred only very rarely in actual
est. The head would also be jerked forwards and backwards.
ritual, where the meat was usually boiled or roasted before
In his magisterial study of the nude in art, Kenneth Clark
its distribution among the participants (Burkert 1983: 139;
discusses the maenad or ‘the nude of ecstasy’ (Clark 1960:
Christopher and Parker 2004: 628). As Walter Burkert ex-
264) at considerable length, describing in detail how the ec-
plains, Greek sacrificial ritual was in fact ‘a straightforward
static body ‘twists and leaps, and flings itself backwards, as
and far from miraculous process: the slaughter and con-
if trying to escape from the inexorable, ever-present laws of
sumption of a domestic animal for a god’ (Burkert 1985: 55).
gravity’ (o.c. 264). The twisting of the maenadic body is what
If myth tells us that Dionysos took his vengeance by tearing
Clark calls ‘the Scopaic twist’ (o.c. 270) because it was first
people apart, the Dionysian ritual replaced these unfortu-
335
336
nate people with sacrificial animals, which in turn had to
governs everything that happens to us while we are unable
be cooked before they could be eaten in the sacrificial meal.
to control it in any way. To explain this, Nietzsche contrasted
Burkert further notes that ‘in the Dionysian realm, as else-
Dionysos with his opposite, Apollo, who was the god of light
where, animal-sacrifice guarantees that the ritual functions
and reason. Dionysos embodies the will-to-life and the cycle
sensibly’ and illustrates the point with ‘our one securely
of life and death. He refers to the primal realm of nature,
attested instance of human sacrifice’. This was the case of
where everything is moist and damp and where all life be-
Zoilus, the priest of the Dionysian cult in Orchomenos of
gins. Camille Paglia explains that ‘Dionysos rules what Plu-
whom Plutarch claims that he actually killed a young wom-
tarch calls the hygra physis, wet or liquid nature. [...] Diony-
an during a ritual of flight and pursuit. The community was
sian liquidity is the invisible sea of organic life’ (Paglia 1991:
so shocked by this fanatical breach of sacrificial decorum
91), it is ‘the blind grinding of subterranean force, the long
that Zoilus was put to death and the ritual was reformed
slow suck, the muck and ooze’ (o.c. 5-6) of primal matter. In
(Burkert 1983: 175). This shows that the violence enacted in
this sense Dionysos symbolises the primal force of the kos-
ritual was clearly distinguished from the violence narrated
mos or of Being. Apollo, in contrast, is the rational principle
in myth. Ritual is symbolic action and must therefore remain
of order. Because of its shapeless and incomprehensible na-
firmly fictional.
ture, Being (or the kosmos, or Fate) can never be expressed in
All these aspects of Dionysian ritual help us ‘to find out what
a rational form. What governs the kosmos is what constantly
effect [Dionysos] had on the Greek conception of man’s re-
eludes us. This means that the Dionysian can take no form.
lation to the divine powers’ (Guthrie 1954: 147). Dionysos’
Tragedy was an attempt to give it some form after all. It puts
role had everything to do with the way the uncontrollable
the tragic story of our dependence on a higher order on the
invades our well-ordered human kosmos and shatters its
stage in the form of a story. That is why Nietzsche says that
logos. Dionysian ritual expresses ‘a deep and abiding truth
Dionysos never appears naked on the stage: he is always
about human nature [...]. No man can submit without a
masked, clothed in some Apollonian guise. This means that
struggle to the experience of having his distinctively human
the unruliness of his primal power is clothed in the structure
faculty of reason, and all that connects him with the normal
of a story that makes his workings more comprehensible
world, overwhelmed and submerged by those animal ele-
to us. But while it illuminates the Dionysian, tragedy at the
ments which, normally dormant or at least in subjection,
same time shrouds it: it does not and cannot ever really re-
are released and made dominant by the irresistible surge
veal what it wants to reveal because the Dionysian is elusive
of Dionysian power’ (o.c. 172). According to Nietzsche in Die
on principle. Therefore tragedy symbolises the primary dy-
Geburt der Tragödie (1872) Greek tragedy played an important
namic of Being.
role in making present this truth: tragedy helped the Greeks
But ‘the impressive antithesis which [...] Nietzsche had
to accept the fact that man is dependent upon Fate, which
drawn between the “rational” religion of Apollo and the “ir-
337
rational” religion of Dionysos’ (Dodds 1951: 68-69) might be
normal everyday life, can free himself in the orgies from
too strong, for the opposition between the two deities is less
all that is oppressive and develop his true self. Raving be-
radical than is often suggested. In fact, both Dionysos and
comes divine revelation, a centre of meaning in the midst
Apollo had rituals concerning enthousiasmos and ecstasy. But
of a world that is increasingly profane and rational’ (Burkert
there was a different kind of ecstasy involved. The ecstasy
1985: 292). But this invasion by the god was only a temporary
in the rituals of Apollo is what professor Dodds has called
experience. ‘While it lasted there was nothing on earth to
‘prophetic madness’ ( o.c. 64) or a ‘shamanistic’ (o.c. 71) type
compare with it, but it left them as they were before [...]. The
of ecstasy where the god speaks through a human vessel
ekstasis was temporary, [...] and as it receded they felt that
to reveal himself. The ecstasy or enthousiasmos offered by
the god had left them and that they were human [...] once
Dionysian ritual was quite a different matter: ‘its social func-
more’ (Guthrie 1954: 180). To partake in Dionysian ritual was
tion was essentially cathartic, in the psychological sense: it
to be engulfed by brutal Being and to be brought back to the
purged the individual of those infectious irrational impulses
kosmos of societal life.
which, if dammed up, had given rise, as they have done in 338
other cultures, to outbreaks of dancing mania and similar
Cleansing Cleanliness
manifestations of collective hysteria; it relieved them by
The movement of immersion in the Dionysian and subse-
providing them with a ritual outlet. If that is so, Dionysos
quent return to the human realm is structurally at work
was in the Archaic Age as much a social necessity as Apollo;
in the performances of Hermann Nitsch. Nitsch’s perfor-
each ministered in his own way to the anxieties charac-
mances contain so many elements that it would require a
teristic of [Greek culture]. Apollo promised security [while]
book-length study to discuss them all in detail. To sketch a
Dionysos offered freedom [and] was essentially a god of joy’
general overview of his intentions we shall therefore take
(o.c. 76). But Dionysian ritual had a profoundly altering ef-
as starting-point the manifesto for the Orgien Mysterien The-
fect on its participants. If Apollo simply used his ecstatic
ater that Nitsch wrote in 1962. From that programmatic text
priestesses as a medium through which he could reveal his
we shall expand the discussion to take in later statements.
wisdom, the Dionysian revellers actually came to partake of
Nitsch starts by explaining his own role in the actions. ‘In
the god’s divinity. ‘The Dionysian worshipper, at the height
my artwork (a form of mysticism of being) I take the seem-
of his ecstasy, was one with his god. Divinity had entered
ingly negative, the unappealing, the perverse, the obscene,
into him, he was entheos, and the one name Bacchos covered
rut, and the sacrificial hysteria that results from these upon
both deity and devotee’ (Guthrie 1954: 174). Walter Burkert
me so that YOU can be spared the soiled, shameless descent
further explains that ‘this state of frenzy is blessedness [...].
into the extreme. I am the expression of the entire creation.
An atavistic spring of vital energy breaks through the crust
I have dissolved myself in it and identified myself with it.
of refined urban culture. Man, humbled and intimidated by
All pain and lust, mixed together into one single expressive
339
340
condition of rush, will penetrate me and therefore you’ (OMT
intensely in the rush of orgiastic ritual, where ‘we identify
8). In a gesture that has earned him the derision of many a
with the entire universe, with the entirety of all that exists’
sober-minded critic Nitsch clearly posits himself as a kind of
(OMT 115-116). The Dionysian orgia achieves this level of
artist-priest carrying the burden of sacrifice and absolution
consciousness because all our senses are activated in it. In
of mankind: ‘I want to deliver humanity from the bestial’
Nitsch’s ritual, there is touch, smell, taste, sight, and sound:
(OMT 10). But behind this claim there is a complex meta-
the ritual is experienced through the senses just like ‘life
physical view of being that closely resembles the ecstatic
is experienced through all five senses at once’ (OMT 118).
worldview that we find in Dionysian ritual, but also in pan-
Hence the Orgien Mysterien Theater is ‘a feast of all senses’
theism and Neoplatonism.
(ibid.) and through its sensory intensity ‘the true experience
For Nitsch Dionysos represents the realm of the repressed.
of our universe, the embodiment of the universe, comes
Society civilises us at the cost of restraining many of our
into being. We recognise the universe as our own body. [...]
biological and animalistic urges, primarily the desire to kill,
The fully grasped and lived through moment (drunkenness
but obviously also sexual lust. The Dionysian expresses the
of being) brings identity with the essence of creation, with
need for abreaction, for acting out what is repressed: ‘Das
its moving, its changing, its never-ending realisation, in the
Dionysische ist ein anderes Wort für Abreaktionsbedürfnis’ (OMT
infinity of eternity’ (OMT 119).
12). To be Dionysian is to live and experience life to the full-
To break the chains of civilised repression the Dionysian
est, including all the desires and urges that society seeks to
cult ‘wakes up anal sensuality. The prohibition against lust-
cancel out. In a 1978 manifesto Nitsch formulates a vision
fully touching the genitals, the prohibition against smearing
that is somewhat reminiscent of Neoplatonic emanation
excrement, connects the anal to the sexual realm’ (OMT 36).
from the One. He sees the entire material universe as one
Children are taught not to play with themselves, with their
all-encompassing and self-creating organism in search of
excrement or with any bodily secretion. They are taught to
self-awareness. It is an atheist pantheism, a materialistic
feel shame about their bodies’ most natural and pleasure-in-
religion of the earth. Everything in the universe is intercon-
ducing functions and to submit to strict rules of cleanliness.
nected: ‘creation (all that is and that comes about) strives
This robs them of some of the most elementary sensual
towards experience of itself through the living. The course
experiences available to man and makes it impossible for
of the worlds, the whole of everything, creates itself through
them (or for any socialised mature person) to fully under-
the living, through all living creatures, all organisms, to know
stand the existential import of the surrounding world, which
itself’ (OMT 115). We, as organisms, are part of that system,
is thoroughly organic. We are no longer part of the universe.
so that Nitsch can claim that ‘I believe that the universe is
We have cut ourselves off from it. And because this cutting
my true body’ (OMT 116). This cosmic expansiveness, this
off occurs at a very young age the damage is lasting. It also
belonging to the organism of the all, is experienced most
accounts for much violence, such as hatred against the body,
341
342
especially bodies that remind us of the organic nature of all
and partridges. It is sad when a bullet tears apart the heart
being: the female body (with its connections to the bloody
of a doe, a deer, or a boar. But it is beautiful to eat game and
mess of childbirth) and the homosexual body (with its sym-
drink red wine with it’ (OMT 120). The problem is not with
bolic connection to passive anal pleasure, which the domi-
eating meat but with the way that meat is obtained. The
nant heterosexual male must edit out of his sexual being).
meat we buy in the supermarket is prepared and packaged
Because these cultural restrictions must be breached Nitsch’s
in a way that allows us to forget the bloody slaughter that
ritual attaches great importance to the ritual soiling of the
preceded it. Our societies have placed a major taboo on kill-
body, which is covered in blood and intestines while fluids
ing, but Nitsch claims it is ‘a fake taboo, for killing goes on
such as wine, milk, honey, and egg-yolk are smeared on it.
on a daily basis. We just don’t want to get our hands dirty.
There is a strong sadomasochistic current at work in these
[...] We are the strongest, most insatiable and most relent-
acts. But sadomasochism simply expresses the reversed
less killing predator’ (OMT 130). It is therefore necessary to
violence of breaking the shackles of violent repression. To
acknowledge the bloody facts of murder and slaughter to
submit to the sadomasochistic soiling of oneself is to regain
fully achieve our humanity, not because cruelty and slaugh-
contact with one’s true physical and therefore essential self.
ter are good, but because one must pass through the darkest
In the loud and hysterical explosion of ritual man seeks to
knowledge of oneself to be able to truly civilise oneself. We
reconnect with what is at once most intimate and most for-
must face what and who we really are. Ritual is our opportu-
eign within him: the body physical, which is the universe of
nity to embrace this dark knowledge without causing actual
all nature, with all its urges, desires, and functions. The body
harm to our fellow beings. Obviously, this argument also
and its manifold desires exist, as all of nature exists, beyond
entails a profound indictment of capitalism, which is really
good and evil: it is simply there. And its existence must be
no mode of civilisation at all. Capitalism is merely barba-
fully and honestly acknowledged.
rism masquerading as civilisation, for it is the culture of the
This does not mean that Nitsch endorses violence. On the
benefit of the few at the cost of the destruction of the many.
contrary, he points out that no animal is slaughtered in his
Our supposedly civilised democracies prate much of equality
actions that would not otherwise have been slaughtered as
and human rights, but at the same time there is inequality
well: ‘No animal should be killed on my account’ (OMT 10).
and exploitation everywhere. Our societies choose money
All the animals that are disembowelled in the Orgien Mys-
over people on principle. But we flinch at the sight of blood
terien Theater have either died of old age or had to be killed
and feign to abhor violence. It is therefore necessary to live
of necessity (because of illness or injury). ‘Pain and torture
and experience our extremes intensely. In his most frenzied
of animals are fundamentally avoided in my actions’ (OMT
moments, which are reminiscent of Sade’s Sodome, Nitsch
32). In the 1978 manifesto Nitsch returns to this point and
even writes that actual human corpses, preferably corpses of
writes that ‘it is sad when shot rips apart hares, pheasants,
young boys, should be butchered, cut up, and fucked in the
343
344
ritual (OMT 38). Obviously, these passages are not meant as
ing unartistic can work in art, only those things which lead
incitements to actual crimes: they are merely provocative
to art can work through it’ (OMT 40). Hence Nitsch is very
expressions of the deep necessity of facing our most violent
sceptical about contemporary political art because it ‘confus-
impulses. ‘Through the theatre we can make our abreaction
es art with a politically-historical mode of sharing informa-
conscious and achieve catharsis. I show flesh and blood,
tion; the possibility to penetrate into the depth of the actual
things to which people react very strongly, they avoid them;
dimension of art, namely form, is not acted upon’ (ibid.). So
but those who look and experience intensely achieve a con-
Nitsch would probably agree with Langer that art is not and
scious abreaction and catharsis through aesthetics’ (OMT
should not be discursive, for that puts the goal of art outside
22).
the work of art itself. Nitsch also points out that ‘form is
Nitsch often stresses that the line between art and life is
not usually something external, not something superficially
obliterated in his work: everything in his actions is real. ‘The
aesthetic, but it is that essential thing that makes art art.
most important thing about my theatre – which I perform
It is false to speak of formalism very often: it is a complete
together with the spectator – is that all that happens is real.
misunderstanding of form. Formalism usually refers to an
In the old, conventional theatre, the actor “plays” his part.
art that uses only form and lacks all content. Of all that art
That is not reality. In contrast, in my theatre everything is
has to offer, form is the most profound. [...] The actual depth
real. The objects I use, such as animals, blood, sugar, are real.
of art lies in the extreme penetration into the ever unfath-
They are not symbols for something else, as was the case in
omable and inexhaustible possibilities of form. Art expresses
the old theatre’ (OMT 20-21). But all these real elements are
nothing but itself. Art is embedded in form’ (OMT 41). By
not there for their own sake: they are motifs integrated into
consequence, ‘the form-content problem does not exist for
a Gesammtkunstwerk which expresses Nitsch’s philosophy.
me, the most significant and only content of art is its form’
And if the individual motifs do not symbolically represent
(OMT 42). In fact, the whole form-content issue is simply a
anything else, the action in its entirety is very much a sym-
result of our Christian heritage, which spurns the material
bol or, as Nitsch puts it, a form. In fact, Nitsch is very insis-
(form), bifurcates body and mind, and urges us to find deeper
tent about the importance of form in all art, including his
spiritual meanings in the physical, which becomes illegiti-
own. ‘The most important goal of my work is form. [...] Art
mate if no such meanings can be found.
must be beautiful. And that means that it is formal. With-
The strong formal element guarantees that Nitsch’s actions,
out form there is no art. Form is the real message that art
no matter how much reality they incorporate, remain fiction-
can bring people. Art is form’ (OMT 23). In a lecture of 1970
al. The excess of his actions ‘is restrained in the theatre, it is
Nitsch has discussed his ideas about form extensively. He
achieved within the orders of play, rules, it is safeguarded,
claims that ‘the specific nature of art lies in purely formal
it becomes visible as an aesthetic phenomenon [...]. Pain is
elaboration. Form represents the deepest nature of art. Noth-
avoided. As pointed out before, all my actions are supported
345
346
by the principle of form, they all really take place, but their
is eliminated, the inclusion of the spectator is never in the
meaning lies in the form, in the retrieval of new aesthetic
least coercive.
values’ (OMT 39). Hence the sacrifice in the ritualistic action
If loneliness is indeed at the heart of the postmodern hu-
‘is performed bloodless, symbolic, abstractly spiritualised,
man condition, as Kondylis claims, and if Arendt is correct to
but it is not therefore less real’ (OMT 9). This tension be-
suggest that loneliness was cultivated in the most perverse
tween fiction and reality makes Nitsch’s actions an ideal
way in the extermination camps of nazism, then the work of
test-case for our definition of the primary illusion of perfor-
Nitsch tries to undo this violence and re-establish a connec-
mance. All the art forms and real elements that Nitsch uses
tion with the world. Nitsch’s rituals allow their participants
are incorporated into the Gesammtkunstwerk that is the ac-
to enter into contact with the kosmos or nature or Being. Be-
tion, the ritual as work. But it is a work that also includes the
ing is a kosmos the logos of which eludes us. For Nitsch the
audience. In fact, since Nitsch wants to obliterate the bound-
ritual is the place where Being can be experienced without
aries between life and art within the ritual, his work fits our
the interface of language or reason. We are immersed in it.
definition perfectly. By making the estate of Prinzendorf in
Instead of trying to explain Being, and hence explain it away
its entirety the scene of his theatre, it becomes an enclosure.
or circle around it without touching its essence, we can get
It is a magic circle. All who enter, enter the forcefield of the
into unmediated contact with Being through ritual. This al-
performance and become part of its transformative ritual.
lows man to feel grounded again in the world because he
To enter the estate is to become a participant. And because
is brought into direct contact with what is at once most
the idea that underlies the entire performance is the idea
intimate and most foreign in him: Being. It is obvious that
of fundamental connectedness within the universe, what
Nitsch’s work here echoes Martin Heidegger’s remarkable
happens to Nitsch or the participants in the performance,
claim that Western culture suffers from what he calls Seins-
also happens to the spectators who are in communion with
vergessenheit or forgetfulness of Being. This means that the
them. This is similar to Aristotle’s concept of katharsis, where
Western philosophical tradition since Plato has objectified
the audience finds release through empathy with what is
Being into some kind of Highest Being, whether a Platonic
enacted. But there is a difference because in Nitsch’s work
Idea of the Good or an almighty god. By objectifying Being
there is no distance between the spectators and the partici-
the sense of it as an unruly, invisible and impenetrable force
pants. Such a distance is part of the “old” theatre. But unlike
is somehow lost. Being is given clear Apollonian form, it is
the unwitting participants (the passers-by) in Burden’s Dead
a benign Father or a transcendent Idea, and it can be ad-
Man, all spectators at the Orgien Mysterien Theater are free to
dressed through prayer or penetrated through philosophical
come and go as they please and can decide for themselves to
reflection. Heidegger urges us to see Being again as it really
what extent (if at all) they want to get involved in the ritual.
is. And its true nature is what the Greeks called Fate. The
So although the distance between spectator and participant
German word for Fate is Schicksal, which has the same root
347
as Geschick, something which is sent us. And this, Heidegger
of pain (the sadism of Sade) with the lustful experience of
remarks, is exactly what Being actually is: it is not an object,
inflicted pain (the submission of baron Von Sacher-Masoch).
not a person or person-like instance, but it is “what hap-
The instrument of the ritual is pain. As we saw, pain destroys
pens” or “what befalls us”. Geschick is visited upon us in the
the world. But since the pain is restrained within the rules
same way the Greeks were visited by Fate. It comes from
of the sexual game, its world-destroying power is curtailed.
nowhere and nobody is responsible for it. It is again the vio-
This is a paradoxical process that requires explanation. If a
lent intrusion of the unruly kosmos into the neatly rational
person is tortured, the combination of physical distress and
human world, ‘an incursion from the fathomless depths
psychological terror encloses her in her body. Pain is inflicted
beyond the limits of sane and conscious human personal-
as a way of destroying the world. Although many practices
ity’ (Guthrie 1954: 173). Our brutal animality is part of our
known to torturers are also used in sadomasochism, their
Fate, our Geschick, which we must work through and come to
role and meaning there are fundamentally different. The
terms with if we are ever to achieve any kind of authentically
most important difference lies in the relationship between
full humanity.
the participants. In torture, there is an aggressor who violates a victim. In sadomasochism there is an equal relation
348
Irreligious Rituals
between sexual partners. There are firmly set rules about
Eroticism is the formalising of unruly sexuality. It is lust cap-
what is and what is not allowed. Hence, the submissive
tured in the ritualised form of the spectacle. And the most
partner does retain control at all times, even if she submits
ritualistic form of eroticism is sadomasochism. In its theatri-
to a ritual in which many of the events visited upon her are
cal enactment of brutal violence the sadomasochistic ritual
unexpected. The submissive person chooses to play the part,
comes very close to Dionysian ritual, both in structure and in
derives enjoyment from it, and normally has a way of ending
meaning. In essence, sadomasochism is a ritual of surrender:
the ritual at any time by giving a prescribed sign. This means
the passive partner submits to the dominant partner, who
that the sexual ritual of sadomasochism is never arbitrary in
gains control over another person’s body. The submissive
the way that torture is. This links sadomasochism to Diony-
partner surrenders himself. In games of bondage he or she
sian ritual with its many rules and prescriptions. It is a the-
is literally tied up and sometimes even gagged, preventing
atre of excess, and hence a measure of control and restraint
them from speaking or screaming. In certain extreme games
is exercised. Between the sexual partners there is not an
full sensory deprivation is applied, as when the submis-
aggressive relation but a relation of trust: both partners sur-
sive partner’s body is wrapped in cellophane or dressed in
render to each other.
a rubber body-suit. The most well-known version of the
This reciprocity is very important. It is a common mistake
sadomasochistic ritual, however, is the one from which it
to assume that it is merely the passive partner who sur-
takes its double name: a combination of the lustful infliction
renders. But by accepting the token of the submissive body,
349
350
the dominant partner gains not only power over that body,
nant partner. Once the passive partner is pulled back into
but also responsibility; not simply the responsibility of play-
the real world, the ritual ends. So the sexual ritual has the
ing by the rules as they are set, and hence not inflict actual
structure of a passage: just like Dionysos (or Christ) the pas-
violence, but also the responsibility of providing enjoyment
sive partner descends into the underworld but returns (rises
for the passive partner. To dominate is an exhausting task: if
from the dead) unscathed, or at least relatively so, and usual-
the passive partner does not experience ecstasy (but rather
ly not scathed beyond what measure he or she had declared
boredom or, worse still, non-pleasurable discomfort) the
desirable at the beginning of the ritual.
dominant partner has failed miserably. In this sense there
This structure of descent-release-return is not only a game
certainly is a dialectic of master and slave: by surrender-
of trust between partners, one of its possible effects is a
ing, the passive partner surrenders his ego; by accepting the
growing trust in the world. By embracing the Dionysian, one
body of the passive partner, the dominant partner invests
can learn not to fear it, or to fear it less. Hence, sadomasoch-
his ego. If the ritual fails, it is the dominant partner who is
ism, and especially masochism, is probably one of the surest
to blame. It is he or she who stands to lose face, no matter
cures for neurosis available. To face one’s fears and anxieties,
how much he or she humiliates the passive partner. The
to wallow in the excrement that society forbids us to seek
passive partner chooses and embraces humiliation, which is
pleasure in, is to master them and put them to rest. To be
a source of tremendous relief. It is also a gesture of tremen-
a masochist is to commune with both the cosmos and the
dous trust and courage. It is a leap into the void. The passive
kosmos: one becomes part of both universal materialist na-
partner descends into the Dionysian realm of the formless:
ture and unruly Fate that disinterestedly governs our ways.
by giving up identity he or she returns to the primal unity
The sense of surrender and its concomitant release can be
with the universe. By losing or giving up, temporarily, the
exceptionally forceful. There is an astonishing chapter in Pier
sense of self, one is reduced to one’s physical being, a part of
Paolo Pasolini’s last and unfinished novel Petrolio in which a
cosmic nature. One becomes organism. To be dominant is to
man drives to the outskirts of Rome, ventures out to a der-
cling to Apollonian form: one must act upon the other, and
elict stretch of urban wasteland, and lets himself be fucked
action requires determination and deliberation. The release
by a group of riff-raff. He (for the man is himself the narra-
experienced by the passive partner is to a large extent due
tor of the chapter) describes his masochistic submission in
to the ritualistic nature of the sexual game. In this respect
almost mystical terms. This is no coincidence: to be anally
it resembles performance art: it is known more or less from
penetrated is to be exceptionally vulnerable. One is literally
the start what the ritual will be like and how long it will take.
open; witness the remarkable shots in porn films of assholes
This means that the passive partner knows that he will be
that stay spread open even after the penis has been pulled
pulled back from the Dionysian abyss, which makes it easier
out. To have one’s ass opened to that extent, and maintain
for him or her to surrender in trust to the power of the domi-
this openness even when there is no intrusive foreign body
351
352
squeezing it open, is to invite everything and anything to
should probably simply speak of a masochistic ritual rather
enter. It is small wonder that most cultures have morally
than a sadomasochistic one. Anita Phillips explains that ‘the
condemned anal sex, especially between men; not because
two species are anything but complementary [...]. Sadism is
such intercourse is somehow unnatural, but because the
characterised by a sullen, resentful apathy punctuated by
symbolical link with total submission and shameful loss of
bursts of self-pitying rage, in Sade’s case directed at god and
self is obvious. In fact, it is the whole point of the practice.
his mother-in-law. My sense of Sade’s driving impulse is of
Interestingly, this again shows how the power-relations in
violence fantasised as compensation for the feeling of being
sadomasochism are inverted. It is usually the dominant
weighed down by an oppressive figure. [...] Sadism is a story
partner who is depicted as masculine, forceful, and virile. But
of great pathos and even failure, in that the violence never
in actual fact, it is the passive partner who engages in hero-
accomplishes its goal of clearing a free space for action, for
ics for it is he or she who performs the role that really takes
intervention into history. Highly autonomous, the masoch-
heroic guts. To be anally submissive is to be at once superbly
ist’s faults are vanity and posturing. While the sadist seeks
heroic and inexcusably slutty. It is no doubt this paradoxical
a victim, and is repelled by the masochist’s capacity for
feature of masochism and sexual submission that accounts
pleasure, which diminishes his own, the masochist wants to
for its enormous rush. It is a short-circuit that results in loss
find a playmate. The opposite number is someone who can
of self. And as Anita Phillips remarks in her lucid defence
be convinced or charmed into acting the role of torturer, not
of masochism, ‘there is nothing so unusual about wanting
a brutal heavyweight [...]. No sadist is any good for a mas-
to leave one’s identity behind. Any kind of real enjoyment
ochist, since each is disqualified from dancing to the other’s
enables a temporary forgetting of the self, whether it is gaz-
tune, with the result that both are wrong-footed. The perfect
ing at a Giotto fresco or betting on the dogs. There is nothing
choice may be another masochist’ (o.c. 12). The key to this
so helpful and invigorating as excessive enjoyment. [...] The
paradox probably lies in the fact that there is a sadist in ev-
reason that boredom is so miserable is because it means
ery masochist. Sadomasochism is an ambivalent fetish, not
being continually conscious of oneself. The same applies to
in the sense that it needs two different kinds of people to be
the jaded person who is unable to make use of the resources
realised (namely a sadist and a masochist), but in the sense
around them because a sense of surfeit allows no space in-
that what we call a masochist is probably a sadomasochist
side, no hunger to draw on external stimuli’ (Phillips 1998:
(and vice versa) while a sadist is quite something else. Part of
105). The masochist is mystically cleansed of the burden of
the enjoyment of the dominant partner in sadomasochism is
identity through immersion in the muck.
undoubtedly an experience of projection: he or she is inflict-
In a very real sense, sadomasochism is a misleading term be-
ing upon the submissive partner what they would probably
cause it suggests that in the sadomasochistic ritual a sadist
like to have inflicted upon themselves but are too chicken
and a masochist meet to their mutual contentment. But we
to submit to. Sadism, on the other hand, is a rage that rises,
353
as Phillips suggests, from frustration. It is a rage against the
function of the physical: there is nothing in heaven that was
world. Which is not to suggest that the masochist is at peace
not first experienced in the body. If we may paraphrase Aris-
with the world: he has simply found an entirely opposite
totle, it is unnecessary to create a superfluous order of supe-
way of dealing with his frustration. What the masochist
rior beings. We do not need god if we are willing and able to
needs, is someone who is willing to slow down time with
listen to nature; not in some corny New Age way, but in the
him or her, someone who will make it their own desire and
sense of beginning to think and feel about ourselves as an
enjoyment to see the submissive partner experience ex-
organism. ‘That man is an animal I certainly believe,’ writes
tended pleasure. To torture a masochist, one needs empathy,
Langer, ‘and also, that he has no supernatural essence, “soul”
not sadism.
or “entelechy” or “mind-stuff,” enclosed in his skin. He is an organism, his substance is chemical’ (PNK 40). Hence, god
354
Lost in the Stars: A Materialist Manifesto
is an unnecessary, or at best an aesthetic, hypothesis. We
In masochism, as in all Dionysian ecstasy, we temporarily
should not kneel down for gods of our own (or others’) mak-
give up the world to have it given back to us; or to have our-
ing. One should only ever kneel down to give a blow-job.
selves be reborn into it. As Phillips points out, ‘the achieve-
Immanuel Kant once remarked that there were two things
ment of the masochist is to attempt to grasp, with the imagi-
that filled him with awe: the infinite sky above him and the
nation, to suffer passively, with the body and will, the transi-
infinite moral law within him. In both instances we are con-
tion between life and death’ (o.c. 154). To hover between life
fronted with our own insignificance. There is nothing quite
and death is to hover on the threshold of kosmos, it is to gaze
so dizzying as to put one’s head back in the night and stare
into its abyss and not be annihilated by it. It is to sense its
at the star-lit sky, which seems to tilt and turn above us and
pull and then be pulled away from it again. It is playing with
which seems to suck us in if we look long enough. When the
the edge. In this sense it is a truly religious experience, far
night is especially clear, it may even seem as if the stars or
more so than any of the traditional monotheistic religions. It
the moon are moving towards us, or we towards them. We
is often claimed by religious people that atheists do not re-
are indeed lost in the stars, hidden away on a speck of dirt in
ally have any kind of profound spiritual life, as if to dismiss
the cosmos. There is no sense in the universe. It simply ex-
the transcendent is to be void of the spiritual. But there is
ists. It changes according to several physical, chemical, and
great spirit in the material world. In fact, it is probably far
biological principles, but to no purpose and with no intent.
more authentically profound to worship the earth and the
There is simply infinity gaping at us. What both Nitsch and
body than to worship any kind of fictional superior being. As
the masochist attempt to achieve is an intensified experi-
we saw in our discussion of Langer, man is by nature sym-
ence of that void, that emptiness, and the great havoc it
bolic. It is a yearning of the organism to express itself sym-
makes of our certainties, our sense of self and purpose. The
bolically. Religions are symbolic systems. Hence, they are a
point of ecstasy is to come into contact with that void and to
355
356
accept it. There is release in accepting one’s futility. And the
undoing what should be an unsettling transcendence. To
odd thing is that suddenly, when one accepts one’s futility,
have an almighty Father or other superior being is to shut
nothing is futile anymore, for one suddenly sees the things
the door on any real transcendence before you have even
that really matter in life, in the world. Our passage in this life
started. To have a god is a clever way of having your infin-
is brief at best. And there is no other life. So all we can do is
ity and eating it, too. What transcendence is possible in a
live our life in constant awareness of its finite nature. This
universe where one man has already died to save us all? To
attitude makes a mockery of our vanities, of the bustle of ev-
have religious convictions is to be cuddled to death. It is life
eryday business. It shows the obscenity of capitalism, career-
made easy, with a never-faltering moral compass to tell you
ism, and crude materialism while highlighting the blessings
what the universe is like and what your particular place in it
of small pleasures, beauty, art, human companionship, and
should be. It’s the Rough Guide to Creation, telling you what is
the appeal of the sensual (and sexual) world. It is a release
natural and what is not, what is orderly and what is not, and
to be able to accept insignificance on a cosmic scale (and is
hence which parts of creation you may oppress or destroy
there, could there be, any other scale?).
without sinning against the great immortal code of the cre-
This acceptance is true religion. And it is a truth that or-
ator. It separates the chosen or the pure from the rejects and
ganised religion rarely yields. To the extent that traditional
the impure. Metaphysically, it is an Apollonian mask slapped
religions identify Being with a god, and usually a benign
over Dionysian truth, but not to allow Dionysos to appear,
god at that, they simply stunt our sensitivity for the infinite,
but to hide him, to make him invisible. Religions tell us that
the meaningless, the annihilating void that stares back at
the mask is all the reality there is. For all their talk of deeper
us from Kant’s starlit heaven. The mortification of the flesh,
and ever deepening dimensions of meaning, religions are
the denial of the physical, the belief in the transcendent, the
shockingly one-dimensional, for there is no place in them for
rejection of the organism and its manifold functions: these
either the infinite or the material. This is as true of Islam and
are the bad faith of religion. There is no real spirituality in
Judaism as it is of Christianity. The true way to ecstasy is the
any belief system that has a benign god as guarantor that
way of all flesh. This is what sex, and particularly masoch-
all is or will be well. There is only fake transcendence if one
ism, does: it takes us to the threshold of death and brings us
transcends into the secure knowledge that there is a benign
into contact with the great void into which we will one day,
logos governing both the temporary and the eternal worlds.
inevitably, collapse.
As the highest instance, the god is literally the lid on the universe: he contains and makes pleasant all that is incom-
Demonic Time
prehensible, material, and unruly. Life is a mystery, religion
The sense of cosmic and existential unrest is nowhere more
proclaims, but happily there is a god at hand to explain away
tangible than in the films of Béla Tarr. Tilda Swinton, who
our perplexity with tales of creation and a cozy afterlife,
worked with Tarr on The Man from London (2009), has justifi-
357
358
ably described his cinema as a ‘medieval space programme’
including the little Estikes of this world. To make his dream
(Quandt 2009: 11). The description sounds iconoclastic but
come true, he invites the villagers to give him their money
evokes very well the coming together of the ancient and the
to start up the community. Then they must wait for him in
contemporary in Tarr’s work. Tarr’s films speak of our pres-
a ruined house outside the village, where he will come to
ent times, but they do it by using a symbolism and a visual
collect them. Most villagers are so wrecked with guilt over
language that seem to speak to us from some dark backward
Estike’s death that they willingly hand over their money and
in the abysm of time. ‘We have some ontological problems,’
leave the village behind to follow Irimias, who takes them to
the director has claimed with some understatement, ‘and
the nearest city and splits them up in several houses and ap-
now I think a whole pile of shit is coming from the cosmos’
partments, where they are to wait for further instructions. It
(Daly and Le Cain 2001). Tarr has filmed this cosmic excre-
is forbidden for them to seek contact with one another. Once
ment most impressively in his trilogy of films based on the
the group of villagers has been split up in this miniature
work of novelist László Krasznahorkai: Damnation (Kárhozat,
diaspora, Irimias alerts the police to their presence, accusing
1988), Sátántangó (1994) and Werckmeister Harmóniák (2000).
them of being an organisation of immoral anarchists, and
If anything, Tarr’s films deal in cosmic entropy, showing the
bolts with the money.
gradual disintegration of communities in the wake of some
An important key to understanding Sátántangó is the mys-
intrusive event. This is the basic structure of Sátántangó,
terious figure of Irimias, who shares his name with the
Tarr’s most important and most ambitious film with a run-
prophet of the Old Testament Jeremiah, who foretold the
ning time of over seven hours. The film is set in a small rural
destruction in 587 BC of Jerusalem and of the Temple. Hence,
community in Hungary where the farmers drink away their
he is the prophet of doom. In the film, it is never made en-
meagre income in the local pub. Until they hear of the im-
tirely clear who he is and what his secret might be. But it
minent return of one Irimias (Míhály Víg) and his companion
is clear that he is driven by greed. He also seems to know a
Petrina (István Horváth). For some reason, which is never
lot about the villagers, things that they would prefer to keep
made clear, the news of their return causes a lot of commo-
hidden, and that he wields a lot of power over them through
tion among the villagers. Apparently both men had disap-
this knowledge. In this, Irimias resembles Karrer (Míklos B.
peared more than a year before and were presumed dead.
Székely), the main figure in Damnation. Karrer is a nihilistic
The unrest in the village reaches its peak with the death of
loner who wastes his days away sitting around his appart-
the young girl Estike (Erika Bók), who commits suicide with
ment. His only diversion are his visits to the local bar, wittily
rat poison. Irimias arrives in time to act upon Estike’s death.
called the Titanik Bar, and his liaison with his mistress, who
He gathers the villagers around her body and tells them
is the singer in the bar. One day, the proprietor of the bar
his dream: to create a collective farm, a harmonious living
offers him the job of picking up a package in another town. It
environment where the world would be safe for everyone,
is clear that this is a shady and illegal business. Karrer ac-
359
360
cepts the job, but gets his mistress’ husband to do it for him,
wreaks havoc upon the community. The morning after, some
after which he goes to the police and denounces the propri-
calm has returned, but this calm lacks the innocence which
etor of the bar and the husband, so that they will be arrested.
seemed to be present before the cataclysmic events of the
Both Irimias and Karrer have some knowledge about others
night before. In theory, the sun structures the universe again,
that allows them to move them about like pawns on a chess
but in reality the damage of chaos cannot be entirely un-
board. Their actions bring about a dissolution of the estab-
done. It is like the story of the Fall: once we have eaten from
lished order in the community, whether it is the relation-
the tree of knowledge of good and bad, there is no way back.
ships between a very small group of people, as in Damnation,
We cannot pretend it never happened, we cannot pretend
or an entire community, as in Sátántangó.
we do not know, or, in the film, we cannot go on living as if
In Werckmeister Harmóniák this theme is taken up again. The
the outbreak of violence had never occurred. The community
quiet life in a small town is suddenly disrupted when a car-
has been ruptured and ravaged and life from now on will
nival moves into town, sporting as its main attraction a huge
have to be lived and rebuilt on the ruins of that violence.
stuffed whale and a mysterious “Prince” who speaks of the
Sátántangó has a figure similar to Janos in the Doctor (Peter
end of time and soon gathers around him a great number of
Berling). This burly man is a drunk who spends his time
followers. One night, these people march through town and
looking through his window, observing the villagers and
beat up everything and everyone they can find in a terrifying
recording their actions in drawings and notebooks (there is
explosion of violence. Just like the other two films, Werck-
a notebook for each villager). The voice of the Doctor is the
meister Harmóniák has a central figure who seems to know
voice of the narrator, so we cannot exclude the possibility
everything about everyone, but he is much more benevolent
that he is somehow orchestrating the events in the film, or
than in the other films. It is Janos Valuska (Lars Rudolph), the
even conjuring them up. His position as a possible demiurge
mailman who also functions as the town dunce. Janos’ privi-
or god-like figure is attested by the fact that a picture of the
leged status as one who knows about others is symbolised in
solar system hangs next to his window. It is possible that his
a map of the universe that hangs above his bed. At the be-
record-keeping activities are a way of imposing some kind of
ginning of the film there is a magnificent scene where Janos
order on the events in the village. It would seem he is writ-
choreographs some men in the pub into playing the earth,
ing and recording against chaos and against dissolution. But
the sun, and the moon who circle around each other until
on the night of Estike’s death, the Doctor runs out of alcohol
they achieve the constellation of a solar eclipse. When the
and heads out into the night to buy some more. Wandering
eclipse occurs, Janos explains, chaos breaks loose on earth.
through the darkness, he happens upon Estike, who has run
When the sun reappears, order is established again. This, in
away from home. He tries to follow her through the pouring
essence, is also the structure of events in the film, where the
rain, but he collapses and she gets away. At this point, events
appearance of an unusual event, the arrival of the carnival,
take a turn for the chaotic. The next morning, Estike is dead
361
362
and the Doctor is taken away to hospital, leaving the scene
of ritual. It is an event we must schedule into our lives. We
open for Irimias to start his demonic operations, undoing
must take time to withdraw from the everyday world, shut
the work the Doctor has done by sowing schism among the
the world out and engage these films. Obviously, we have to
villagers and breaking up their community. When the Doctor
do this every time we watch a film, read a book, or go see a
returns to the village at the end of the film, it lies deserted.
play, but we are rarely asked to do it with such commitment,
There is nothing left to record, nothing left to orchestrate.
and to such overwhelming effect, as in Tarr’s films (but I am
The kosmos, which was the Greek word for both the cos-
writing as one who has never been made to sit through an
mos and the order that kept it together, has disappeared. So
entire cycle of Wagner’s Ring). His films engulf you and draw
the Doctor nails shut his window, slowly creating the black
you into their own universe. In the end, time takes over. This
screen on which the film ends: there is no more world to
is very important, for usually watching a film is still a very
look at, no more world to record.
structured event. Most narrative films, and even quite a few
One of the key features of Tarr’s films is their length. The
experimental films, adhere to some kind of basic structure
long running time, usually filmed in real time and with only
that allows us to stay oriented in time. We have a gut sense
the barest minimum of cuts, is often associated in the film
of how far the film has developed, and we usually sense
with the act of walking or running. But the people who walk
when the final act has begun. Most films, but also most nov-
in Tarr’s films do not seem to be going anywhere. They walk
els and plays, have a curve of action that we can follow and
through fields or wander through the night or through rain,
that tells us how much film is still left (reading a book, turn-
but their actions often seem to lack any clear goal. When
ing page after page, the amount of remaining pages visibly
there is a goal, it is often negative, as when Janos runs away
diminishes, like the time remaining on a film diminishes).
from the village along a railway track at the end of Werck-
Tarr’s films do not allow us to do this. This is especially true
meister Harmóniák. Another negative or meaningless goal
of Sátántangó. If one is watching a film that runs for about
is the endless walking of the villagers in Sátántangó, deter-
seven hours, there is really no point in anticipating the mid-
minedly marching towards their own doom in a city they
dle, the end, or anything. Even the film’s individual chapters
do not know. We are also made to watch Irimias and Petrina
sometimes run longer than an average feature film. And yet
walking towards the village in the rain, which gives us
the film is not meant to be seen on several occasions, like a
plenty of time to contemplate their identity and intentions;
television mini-series: ideally, it must be submitted to in one
questions that mostly go unanswered. But there is a very
extended sitting. But to do so is to surrender to time. And
important formal point to these extended scenes. The mas-
in surrendering to time, one breaks away from everyday life
sive length of these films forces us to submit to them. You
and sojourns, for the duration of the film, in a parallel uni-
cannot casually watch a Tarr film, you have to make time
verse.
for it and commit to it. This gives the act of watching an air
363
364
Comes Undone
the same time. Similarly, Sátántangó is structured in twelve
If we take an even closer look at time in Tarr’s films, it would
chapters, but they are not of equal length and especially in
appear that time, or maybe we should now speak of Time,
the first half of the film they are not presented chronologi-
is the true protagonist of these films. And time in Tarr’s uni-
cally. The expanses of time that Tarr presents overlap and
verse, and especially in the universe of Sátántangó, is firmly
change perspectives. This way, time is shown not only out
out of joint. The centre cannot hold and kosmos or order
of joint but unfolded, deconstructed from the inside (Tarr’s
comes undone. One of the basic structuring devices for order
film walks through time and space in a way similar to Da-
in the world is time. But there is something exceedingly odd
vid Hockney’s Visit with Christopher and Don). In such an un-
about time as a unit for measuring anything. Phenomeno-
hinged universe the folds of time become visible as demonic
logically, time is an absurd thing. To measure space we have
openings: black holes in time through which decay seeps in.
metric systems which, although culturally relative and even
And before long the universe starts to rot.
variable (centimetres and metres are not feet and inches),
Sátántangó contains several elements that point towards
are linked to tangible standards in the material world. But
such a demonic unhinging of time. First, objective time is
where can one find the standard second? How can it be mea-
revealed to be unreliable. In the first chapter, that is set in
sured or circumscribed? If a clock goes tic-toc, where does
the home of an adulterous couple, a ticking clock is insis-
the second begin or end? Is the second the space of time
tently present on the soundtrack. The ticking is unnerving
between the tics? Are the tics included? And if the second tic
because it seems to be going slightly too fast. In the second
ends the second, does the second second begin after the end
chapter, titled “The resurrection of the dead,” Irimias and
of the tic? To which second does any given tic belong? These
Petrina arrive in the city where they will later take the vil-
questions of course hark back to Zeno, who showed that any
lagers. They go to the police office for some administrative
unit of time or space is in itself infinite. With regard to time
business. As they sit waiting in the hallway, Irimias notices
these problems are especially vexing because there is no way
that the two clocks in the hall both give a different time
for us to perceive and thus verify time. The only reasonable
and that neither gives the correct time. This could be an
material measures for temporal rhythms at our disposal are
example of the carelessness of civil servants in a decay-
the heartbeat and the cycle of day and night. By disrupting
ing social system (we might call it “civil servant fatigue” or,
our normal experience of time, Tarr’s films question not only
worse, the first onset of the banality of evil), but on another
standard time but any sense of order, for without time every-
level it could also suggest that this community has lost
thing falls apart. If the universe (the kosmos or order) is un-
track of time or has come to find time irrelevant. We could
hooked from time, all events begin to drift apart like islands.
also interpret these insurgent clocks as symptoms of the
This brings to mind again Kondylis’ concept of the postmod-
isolated world in which Sátántangó is set. Then the clocks
ern as an extensive space in which everything is available at
might suggest that time itself simply disregards this part of
365
366
the world and does not bother to make itself known there. In
traditional motif: the earth breaks open and pushes the dead
any case, this community seems to exist outside of ordinary
back to the surface. All these signs foretell that apocalypse is
time and therefore seems to no longer be part of the greater
upon us.
world. Later, when Irimias and Petrina are having a drink
But no discussion of evil in Sátántangó can be complete with-
in a café, there is a humming sound on the soundtrack. But
out addressing the innocent body that lies at the heart of
when Irimias draws attention to it, it becomes clear that this
this apocalypse: the corpse of Estike. This young girl is the
sound is not a mood-enhancing feature of the soundtrack.
central character of the central chapter of the movie, namely
It is part of the material universe of the film. It is difficult to
the fifth chapter that is titled “Comes Unstitched” and in
point out the source of this humming, but we might inter-
which the young girl seems to become possessed by the dev-
pret it as the opening of time, in a metaphysical sense. If
il. Estike is the diminutive form of the Hungarian word for
shit is indeed coming from the cosmos, then the sphincter
evening. So Estike might be taken to symbolise the twilight
of the cosmos must be opening. The humming that breathes
of this world: she is the evening on which the apocalypse
through Sátántangó could be interpreted as the draught blow-
begins towards which the world is already tilting. When we
ing through this opening of time. Something wicked this
first meet Estike, she is shut out of the house by her mother.
way comes and this cosmic humming heralds its imminent
She seeks solace in the granary, where she tortures her pet
arrival. In Werckmeister Harmóniák its arrival is announced by
cat. She looks the animal straight in the eyes and tells it she
equally insubstantial means. When the car carrying the huge
can do with it whatever she wants because she is the stron-
stuffed whale drives into town, crawling through the dark
gest of the two. This recalls a scene in Damnation where Kar-
(and evil often comes under the cloak of night), its arrival is
rer is addressed by an old lady guarding the wardrobe at the
announced by the ominous humming of its engine. The first
Titanik Bar. At one point she refers to a passage in the Old
thing we see, is not the car itself but something immaterial:
Testament where God foretells how Israel will rise against
the bright headlights that sneak up on the houses that line
him but that he will squash its resistance, ‘and then they
the street. Next the shadow cast by the car creeps across the
will know that I am the Lord’. This avenging and angry god
houses. Only in the last instance does the car itself appear.
seems to have taken possession of Estike: banished from her
So the source of evil in this film almost literally appears out
own home she continues the chain of repression by venting
of a tear in the darkness of night, materialising out of sound
her anger on a weaker creature. The endlessly protracted
and light. A final motif that heralds the arrival of evil, partic-
scene in which the girl tortures and finally poisons the cat is
ularly in Sátántangó, is the stench of the earth. In the fourth
brutal cinema, not in the least because the entire sequence,
chapter of the film several of the villagers are sitting in the
which runs for over three quarters of an hour, consist of a
pub at night when a woman notices the stench and crawls
minimal number of unblinking shots so that there can be
under the table to find out where it is coming from. This is a
no doubt about the fact that the cat is actually suffering
367
368
through this excruciating calvary. Tarr is exceedingly per-
in Tarr’s films, and especially in Sátántangó, which seems to
verse here, getting a young girl to enact in real time the cruel
come full circle only to start the same story again. But in its
and merciless torture of a helpless animal, beating it around
detached cruelty, showing us the workings of evil in excru-
and poisoning it (or, we might hope, simply sedating it for
ciating real time, unhurried and confident that everything
fictional effect). After this demonic act of violence, Estike
needs must take its fatal course, the film is also stoic in
takes the cat’s dead body under her arm and begins her long
tone. The ancient Stoa saw history as a constant repetition
wandering through the village; a journey that will last an
of the same process. In Stoic cosmology a cosmic fire brings
entire day and night. First, she is sent away by her brother,
about order in the universe. Once this order is created, things
dismissed again. Next, she is outside the pub at night, look-
move with logical regularity to their predestined conclusion.
ing in through the steamy windows and contemplating the
Then everything is destroyed again in a cosmic fire out of
tired revels inside. Finally, she tries to accost the Doctor, but
which the same process starts again. The same fatalism is
in vain. He, too, dismisses her. We see the pain of rejection
at work in Tarr’s films. It also typifies his characters, who are
crawl over her face like the shadow of death. And then she
depressed and dejected, always on their way to nowhere,
runs. The Doctor tries in vain to keep up with her. And the
endlessly walking without a goal. There is no hope in their
next morning, drenched and cold to the bone, she is still
lives, only absurdity and resignation. This makes sense: if ev-
walking. Finally, she reaches an abandoned ruin of a house,
erything that happens has been orchestrated by some malin
lies down on the ground, and swallows the rest of the rat
génie then hope is a pointless sentiment. And if everything
poison she used on the cat.
constantly repeats itself, time becomes irrelevant. Lost in
After Estike has committed suicide the narrator’s voice re-
the stars, man has nothing to look forward to except his own
counts her final thoughts. The last thing Estike experiences
pointlessness. What makes Karrer stare out of his window
is a sense of calm and acceptance, a profound confidence in
and betray his rival, what makes the villagers in Werckmeister
the ultimate connectedness of everything in the universe.
Harmóniák turn to violence, and what makes Estike take her
Nothing happens in vain, the voice tells us, and there is a
own life is the one certainty we all have in life: the eternal
reason for everything. The great architect has planned every-
return of doom.
thing and everyone has his or her role to play in this plan, including Estike. But as the film makes clear, this great choreographer in the sky is an architect of evil. People are like flies to this wanton god, who kills them for his sport. And at the end, when the tale is told and destruction wrought upon the world, he shuts the window on this theatre of Fate and starts his story all over again. There is a fatalistic circularity
369
Chapter Five
a return to Langer. At the end of Feeling and Form Langer introduces a brief note on cinema in which she claims that the primary illusion of the film is what she calls ‘the dream
370
FRAIL
mode’ because the film ‘creates a virtual present, an order of
GAZING
Taking our cue from Elaine Scarry, we will take the cinema as
direct apparition. That is the mode of dream’ (FF 412). It is a fascinating suggestion that she does not very much elaborate. dream mode and explore it from within, conjuring up images from imagination and memory. Lie with them awhile.
We started this book with the spectre of the male gaze. We
Pathetic Fallacies
have argued with Elaine Scarry that this supposedly hurtful
If one wanted to summarise Langer’s philosophy of art, one
gaze is not at all malicious by definition and that there is no
could say, as she does in the first volume of Mind, that ‘art
evil in looking at beauty. In this long concluding chapter we
is the objectification of feeling, and the subjectification of
will look at beauty and several of the many meanings it can
nature’ (MI 87). Art objectifies feeling because it is a presenta-
have for us. In looking at beauty we will replace the male
tional symbolism that presents us with a prime symbol of the
gaze with what I would like to call the “frail gaze”: a way of
felt experience of life. But in doing so, art gradually subjecti-
looking that revels in beauty and is moved by its frailty. It
fies nature because ‘in developing our intuition, teaching eye
is a gaze that is capable of being moved by beauty because
and ear to perceive expressive form, it makes form expressive
it recognises itself, its own projection, in objects of beauty.
for us wherever we confront it, in actuality as well as in art.
Scarry suggests that the experience of beauty can teach us
Natural forms become articulate and seem like projections
to find beauty where we previously thought no beauty could
of the “inner forms” of feeling’ (ibid.). Anything can become
be found. Such an expansive way of looking could ideally
a material or an element in art because anything and every-
culminate in a gaze that finds beauty everywhere and in
thing can be seen as expressive of human feeling and mean-
everything. In its search for beauty this chapter is a kind of
ing. All meaning and all beauty are projections of the human
indulgence, an invitation to dwell on beauty longer than is
mind onto the surrounding world. But if art is the projection
strictly necessary. It is a rhizome, a patchwork of intercon-
of feeling onto the world, it soon allows us to see expression
nected discussions of works of art. It is a brief for beauty and
in objects that are not man-made. The entire world then
an invitation to its indulgence. It is a walk through a garden
becomes expressive and meaningful. Most images ‘fit more
of delights, and as such it comes with an invitation for the
than one actual experience. We [...] impose them on new per-
reader to stop at will to take in the sights. Finally, it is also
ceptions, constantly, without intent or effort [...]. Consequent-
371
372
ly we tend to see the form of one thing in another, which is
inanimate things as animate, or at least imbued with feeling,
the most essential factor in making the maelstrom of events
is not immature or childish. In other words, a distanced, cool,
and things pressing upon our sense organs a single world’
disaffected approach of the material world surrounding us is
(MI 60). This is how our symbolic intuition works, effortlessly
truly an inhuman approach. In the human world, meanings
perceiving Gestalten in the constant flow of sensory input that
are everywhere. Some such meanings may be extremely fan-
reaches our organism. As Langer points out, ‘the abstraction
ciful, but no part of the human world is ever without mean-
of gestalt from an actually given object by seeing it as an
ing and to look upon it as devoid of meaning or feeling is to
image of some entirely different thing [...] is a very ancient
look upon it as if one were not human oneself. This, as we
source of representational art’ (MI 169). She illustrates this
suggested with Marx and Scarry, is what makes liberal capi-
with a quote from Leonardo da Vinci, describing how we can
talism a fundamentally inhuman world order: it reduces the
see many objects in ‘the texture and crack of old walls’ (ibid.).
world to quantifiable economic entities. There is nothing hu-
This does not mean, however, that Langer would like us to
man about efficiency, because to be efficient one must deny
embrace an animistic view of life. She never allows us to
all the meanings that we find in the world and to deny those
forget, nor should she, that these operations of our symbolic
meanings is to deny our very humanity.
intuition are acts of projection: the cracked texture of a wall
So, in a sense, we should become like children. Not, to be
is never actually a face or a bird or a plant. Nor is a cloud
sure, in the sense that our behavioural patterns should now
ever a whale or a face, even if it seems to resemble one. But
become childish, but in the sense that we should become
the constant seeing of familiar forms in new patterns of
childlike in our perceptual engagement with the world. In
perception is the way our symbolic intuition makes sense of
other words, we should not deny ourselves or others the
our perceptual input and enables us to construct a coherent
pleasure of seeing the entire world as imbued with beauty
world out of the many sensory stimuli that reach us. Asso-
and meaning. And, as we saw in our discussion of Scarry, the
ciating familiar meanings with new impressions is simply
entire world is not limited to nature and art but also includes
the way we get about in the world. But it also opens the door
the beauty of airplanes and cars, buildings and freeways,
to many aesthetic and artistic possibilities. In fact, the pro-
windmills and industrial ruins – in short, anything that al-
cess of perceiving Gestalten in the constant flow of sensory
lows us to experience beauty in the sense of expressiveness.
input should remind us of the quasi-aliveness of inanimate
There is beauty in all things human. If we fail to see the im-
objects that Elaine Scarry made us aware of. Objects become
port of beauty, it is because we choose to ignore it. There are
quasi-alive when we project life into or onto them. It was
indeed people who value the economic potential of a stretch
Scarry’s claim that this projection broadens the scope of our
of land over the wild flowers growing there. They might pre-
care in going about in the world. This has several important
fer to bulldoze and exploit the land. We, on the other hand,
implications. It now appears that the childlike habit of seeing
may feel free to doubt whether these economic busybodies
373
374
are human at all (don’t these people know that life is just a
salad took on an air of crisis’ (Hollinghurst 2005: 332). Apart
bowl of cherries and that you can’t take your dow when you
from the way this observation manages to balance irony and
go?). Obviously, we need industry and its benefits. But to ac-
tragedy by noticing the specifics of the interrupted dinner,
knowledge this need is a far cry from sacrificing anything and
Hollinghurst (or the narrator) projects the feelings the ab-
everything on the altar of economic expansion. Sometimes
sent woman is experiencing, namely a sense of crisis at the
a shrub should come first, especially if it is a particularly
news of a dear friend’s death, onto her food. This would be
beautiful shrub. Factories can be built almost anywhere. A
unacceptable to Ruskin because side plates of salad simply
beautiful stretch of land, a green pasture, or a picturesque
do not experience crises. Ruskin himself offers the example
moor cannot usually be transported for exhibition in another
of a line in a poem that speaks of “the cruel, crawling foam”
locale. So let us make the industry fit the landscape and not
on the waves of the sea; an observation Ruskin dryly rebuts
the other way around.
by pointing out that ‘foam is not cruel, neither does it crawl’
The importance of projected meanings in the realm of hu-
(Ruskin 2000: 369).
man experience was somewhat lost on John Ruskin (1819-
However, Ruskin does not disapprove of the use of compari-
1900). It is odd that a critic and expert draughtsman with
sons. He gives the example of Dante, who describes spirits
such a splendidly lucid eye for the beauty of nature should
falling “as dead leaves flutter from a bough”. In this compari-
have disapproved so thoroughly of the projection of human
son Dante never loses ‘his own clear perception that these
meanings onto that beauty. But this process is in fact what
are souls, and those are leaves; he makes no confusion of one
he famously dismissed, in volume III (1856) of Modern Paint-
with the other’ (o.c. 369-370). For Ruskin, the superior artist
ers, as the “pathetic fallacy”. The pathetic fallacy occurs when
will always ‘keep his eyes fixed firmly on the pure fact’ (o.c.
‘violent feelings [...] produce in us a falseness in all our im-
372). But since many artists are not very partial to record-
pressions of external things’ (Ruskin 2000: 369). This means
ing pure facts, Ruskin famously decimated the pantheon of
that the pathetic fallacy is a “fallacy of sight” that consists in
great artists, both in the visual arts and in literature. Besides
perceiving the world differently than it really is by project-
Coleridge, Ruskin berates both Keats and Pope for indulging
ing our feelings or ideas upon it. Let me give an example
in the pathetic fallacy, marking them as ‘poets of the second
from a passage in Alan Hollinghurst’s exquisitely beautiful
order’ (ibid.). Reading this, one cannot help but wonder how
novel The Line of Beauty (2004), which is about style and how
Ruskin would have judged Shakespeare’s disingenuous de-
it both hides and betrays feelings. The main characters are
cision to let churchyards yawn at Hamlet in the night. But
gathered for dinner when the phone rings and the lady of
Ruskin’s disapproval of the pathetic fallacy does not simply
the house leaves the room to hear of the death of a very dear
stem from a boorish insensitivity to metaphor or from a
friend. During her extended absence the narrator observes
simplistic kind of realism; it is also, and more interestingly,
that ‘her half-eaten grilled trout and untouched side plate of
related to truthfulness in expression. It is his feeling that
375
376
many instances of the pathetic fallacy are introduced to ex-
time maintains a critical distance towards them. Like the
press strong feelings but end up sounding trite, formulaic,
ironist we must maintain our awareness of the fact that what
and contrived in their symbolism. Ruskin feels that poetry
meanings we perceive are projected by us. This is one of the
that indulges in the pathetic fallacy is often hypocritical
things that makes fiction work: we know that the events seen
about the feelings it purports to express. Such poetry does so
in a film, acted out on a stage, or described in a novel are
much hard work looking for interesting images to use that
not actual events, but that does not stop us from becoming
it loses sight of the actual emotion or feeling that needs to
involved with them, crying about them, laughing with them,
be expressed, which ultimately leads to poetic posturing. In
or being upset by them. In other words, if the world is the
this sense the pathetic fallacy ‘is a sign of the incapacity of
projection of our meanings, then the world will certainly be
[the poet’s] human sight or thought to bear what has been
pathetic to our experience (which is not exactly the same as
revealed to it’ (o.c. 373).
our perception of it). And as Simon Shama has shown in his
But we need not accept Ruskin’s severe criticism of the
remarkable book on Landscape and Memory (1995), even the
pathetic fallacy. In fact, it is probably not a fallacy at all. Re-
natural world has ceased to be merely natural but now bears
membering arguments from Marx and Scarry we might sug-
traces of human meanings, even at the heart of supposedly
gest that Ruskin has a wrong take on the pathetic fallacy: he
primeval forests. There is really nothing on this planet un-
identifies the phenomenon but fails to see its true import. In
touched by human hand. So there is nothing void of mean-
reality, people do not, as a rule, misperceive reality in such a
ing. And hence the entire world may appear to us as pathetic.
way that they think all kinds of feelings are actually present
Of course, projected meanings are not limited to practical
in objects. We are very much aware of the fact that we project
interventions. A deforested area clearly bears the stamp of
such feelings and meanings onto these objects. But once they
human meaning, as does a freeway, a skyscraper, or an air-
have been projected, it is very difficult to withdraw them and
plane. But meanings also include symbols and the metaphors
pretend they are not there. In this sense, artists who commit
of myth and religion. They even include a child’s habit of
the pathetic fallacy are really being responsive to the way
seeing the inanimate world as animate, as when they con-
the human world is structured. All meanings are projections,
verse with dolls (or imaginary friends) as if they were actual
and without such projection there simply is no human world
people. If the human world is thus alive with meanings, we
to speak of. If the whole of the human world is the world of
come very near an animistic concept of the world. And that,
human meanings, and if all such meanings are projected by
I believe, is the beauty of our “Marxist-phenomenological”
us upon the world, then it would be quite inhuman to see
approach of meaning: our discussion of Marx, Scarry, and,
(or want to see) the world without such meanings in it. In
of course, Langer allows us to envisage a re-enchantment of
this sense, we really must become a little like Richard Rorty’s
the world without seeking recourse to the esoteric, airy-fairy
ironist, who is attached to his convictions but at the same
nonsense that this often entails. In fact, the re-enchantment
377
378
that lies before us is really thoroughly realistic. It is grounded
explain this we must deal with Ruskin in relation to the work
in cold hard facts about the world. It relies on our organic
of the Pre-Raphaelites. Ruskin is often portrayed as their
link to the organisms around us. It relies on our biological
great advocate and we must briefly investigate how this came
nature and on our ability to generate meanings, which are
about. In his history of the Pre-Raphaelite movement Timo-
then projected onto the world. It relies, in fact, on our ability
thy Hilton claims that with Ruskin, ‘natural history was to
for imagination, which is not something esoteric but a matter
become natural art history’ because Ruskin had a firm belief
of neurology. The re-enchantment we have been developing
in ‘the ability of man to reproduce and interpret the world
does not mean we submit to New Age fashions; nor does it
through pictorial art’ (Hilton 1970: 11). As is well known,
entail any kind of belief in gods, spirits, or other supernatural
Ruskin valued representational fidelity in art more than
beings; it is simply to accept that meaning and (of course)
anything else. He could easily be claimed as a forerunner of
beauty are wherever we may find them. We can embrace
photorealism in painting. But we should be cautious, because
meaning and beauty in the world and accept them as part
Ruskin’s adherence to realistic representation was linked
of reality because reality, and especially reality’s value and
both to his religious beliefs and to his very specific concept of
meaning, are our own creations. To dismiss projection is to
Truth. Ruskin’s religious fervour can be glimpsed in several
dismiss human nature. The meanings and feelings we find in
passages in Modern Painters, for example when he writes that
the external world are not put there by some superior force;
‘true criticism of art never can consist in the mere applica-
it is we who put them there and they are ours to enjoy as
tion of rules; it can be just only when it is founded on quick
reflections of ourselves. And as reflections, they offer insight
sympathy with the innumerable instincts and changeful ef-
(an idea, I imagine, that would not have been foreign to No-
forts of human nature, chastened and guided by unchanging
valis). There is no magic here, no mysticism, and no esoteric
love of all things that God has created to be beautiful, and
belief. This is simply what being human is about.
pronounced to be good’ (Ruskin 2000: 310). Ruskin quite simply believed that all of creation was beautiful and deserved
Having the World
to be scrutinised with aesthetic generosity because it was the
So let us have the world. Let us see its manifold beauty and
creation of a benevolent God. Empirical science, for Ruskin,
revel in it. In the following sections of this chapter we shall
was simply the way to read the book of creation most faith-
embrace this world of plenty through the work of several
fully. ‘Rocks, stones, and water, winds and clouds, leaves and
outstanding artists who will provide us with new insights
grasses and flowers,’ Hilton writes, ‘all these, the various ma-
in our own nature as beings of meaning. But first we must
terials of the natural world, came under an intensely empiri-
redress an injustice, for the previous section might very well
cal scrutiny. [...] He recorded, analysed, and classified, and did
have given the reader the impression that John Ruskin was
so, ultimately, to glorify’ (Hilton 1970: 13).
immune to beauty. In reality, he was quite the opposite. To
Against such a religious background it is obvious that faithful
379
380
pictorial representation was never simply about disinterested
great artist to faithfully represent both. This means that the
science. Ruskin was an expert draughtsman of great sensi-
visual artist must be able to faithfully express spiritual truths
tivity, but he ‘is not interested in making pictures; he hardly
with the means of material truth that painting offers him.
ever framed and hung his own work. He never alters what he
This means that the artist must be able to see and represent
sees in front of him and he hardly ever draws from memory.
the deeper meaning of the natural elements that he is rep-
He is concerned only with the precise recording of natural
resenting. In his discussion of Truth, Ruskin makes several
appearances. And yet he is not dispassionate, for everything
claims that put him in an interesting proximity to Susanne K.
he draws seems now to proclaim that he has indeed exam-
Langer. For example, Ruskin writes that ‘Truth may be stated
ined the natural world with the eyes of love’ (o.c. 17). For
by any signs or symbols which have a definite signification
Ruskin, faithfully recording natural appearances is only the
in the minds of those to whom they are addressed, although
beginning of a great artist’s work. Young artists should only
such signs be themselves no image nor likeness of anything.
draw from nature, but as they mature, they should use their
Whatever can excite in the mind the conception of certain
ability to reproduce nature faithfully to paint images that
facts, can give ideas of truth, though it be in no degree the
express what Ruskin called great ideas. As Ruskin explains
imitation or resemblance of those facts’ (ibid.). This, by and
at the beginning of Modern Painters, painting, but by exten-
large, is a theory of metaphor and could be put alongside
sion all art, ‘is nothing but a noble and expressive language’
Langer’s claim that anything can become expressive of an
(Ruskin 2000: 49). To draw faithfully from nature is to master
idea of feeling if it is expressively included in the fabric of a
that language; but it is not the language that matters in the
work of art.
end, but rather the ideas that are expressed through its use.
Ruskin’s involvement with the Pre-Raphaelites came about
‘It is not by the mode of representing and saying, but by what
somewhat by chance when Coventry Patmore prevailed upon
is represented and said, that the respective greatness either
the critic to write something in defence of the much-reviled
of the painter or the writer is to be finally determined’ (ibid.).
Brotherhood. In response, Ruskin wrote a letter to The Times
To explain this, it is important to understand the two differ-
which is usually taken to be a turning point in the Brother-
ent meanings that Ruskin attached to the word Truth. ‘Truth,’
hood’s fortunes. Initially, however, Ruskin was not overly
he proclaims, ‘signifies the faithful statement, either to the
enthusiastic about the Brotherhood, writing that he had ‘only
mind or senses, of any fact of nature’ (o.c. 56). But Truth is not
a very imperfect sympathy with them’ (Hilton 1970: 66). But
the same as imitation; imitation is but a small part of it. ‘Imi-
he did very much approve of their naturalism and attention
tation can only be of something material, but truth has refer-
to representational detail. This would lead, eventually, to a
ence to statements both of the qualities of material things,
very close involvement with the movement and especially
and of emotions, impressions, and thoughts. There is a moral
with John Everett Millais, who would rob Ruskin of a wife.
as well as a material truth’ (ibid.) and it is the business of the
Like Ruskin, the Pre-Raphaelites felt that art after Raphael
381
382
had degenerated into mannerisms and they wanted to return
see if suddenly gifted with sight’ (o.c. 135). The innocent eye is a
to the purity of early Renaissance painting. When Pre-Rapha-
way of looking that is free from preconceptions and therefore
elite art was first exhibited in 1849 and 1850, critics were very
receptive to the manifold wonders of the world. This may
dismissive. Two elements in the Pre-Raphaelite aesthetic
sound rather excessively Romantic, but the experience of
were found especially unappealing. First, the critics rejected
the innocent eye is still available to us. In fact, Elaine Scarry
the Pre-Raphaelite habit of painting the entire canvas in great
introduces something quite like it when she discusses what
detail. Second, they objected to the fact that everything in
she calls errors in beauty. An error in beauty occurs when
the paintings was bathed in equal light, so that there was no
we claim that something is beautiful when it is not, or claim
visual focus. There was no point of interest that was liter-
that something is not beautiful when it actually is. We be-
ally highlighted by being surrounded with a glow or by being
come aware of the error when we are suddenly struck by the
painted in more detail than the murkier surroundings. In
insight that our judgement was wrong: the beautiful thing
fact, the Pre-Raphaelites painted like a camera would make
is suddenly revealed to be ugly, or what was considered not
a picture: even the smallest and most insignificant detail will
beautiful at all is suddenly revealed to be beautiful after all.
still come out sharp because the camera has a disinterested
Scarry offers an example from her own life: ‘I had ruled out
mechanical eye. It simply and democratically registers every-
palm trees as objects of beauty and then one day discovered
thing and anything that is reflected through its lense in equal
I had made a mistake’ (BBJ 12). The mistake dawned on her
measure of clarity and sharpness. The fully detailed picture
when she was suddenly confronted with the swaying leaves
and the evenness of light were the signature traits of Pre-
of a palm tree next to the balcony of her hotel room. The
Raphaelite painting. And they were exactly what critics ob-
revelation of the beauty of an object previously deemed not
jected to. But the obvious answer to this objection, which was
beautiful is disconcerting and overwhelming because ‘a beau-
given by Ruskin in their defence, ‘was that their system of
tiful object is suddenly present, not because a new object
lighting was that of the sun. The sun illuminates everything,
has entered the sensory horizon bringing its beauty with it
and they painted what they saw’ (o.c. 57).
[...] but because an object, already within the horizon, has its
But in order to paint what one sees, one must look and know
beauty, like late luggage, suddenly placed in your hands’ (BBJ
how to look. In a public lecture at the opening of the Cam-
16). What is especially interesting is that the revelation of the
bridge School of Art, where he would teach drawing classes
error in beauty is almost always linked to a particular experi-
for the working classes, Ruskin explained that the artist
ence. ‘When I used to say the sentence (softly and to myself)
must be taught Sight. Attempting to explain what he meant,
“I hate palms” or “Palms are not beautiful; possibly they are
Ruskin said that ‘the whole technical power of painting de-
not even trees,” it was a composite palm that I had somehow
pends on the recovery of what may be called the innocence of
succeeded in making without even ever having seen, close
the eye... a sort of childish perception... as a blind man would
up, many particular instances. Conversely, when I now say,
383
384
“Palms are beautiful,” or “I love palms,” it is really individual
feeling onto the world. This obviously brings us back to the
palms that I have in mind” (BBJ 19).
main theme of the present book: all meaning, all expressive-
What Scarry illustrates here, is that ‘beauty always takes
ness, and hence all beauty, are created by man. ‘Indeed,’ Read
place in the particular’ (BBJ 18), a point also stressed by Kant.
continues, ‘the primacy of feeling is the bracket in which we
Composite ideas, and by extension idealised concepts of a
can include the whole romantic movement’ (ibid.).
class of things, can mislead us into formulating erroneous
Let us retrace our steps before we open up this discussion to
aesthetic (but obviously also ethical or moral) judgements
introduce a host of beautiful works of art. It all starts with
about these objects. Beauty is particular and it is always an
careful attention to the world, which leads us to a feeling of
individual object or experience that alerts one to the beauty
beauty. This sense of beauty may prompt us to copy the world
of an object or a class of objects. So if any conclusion can be
in a work of art, but it may also (and simultaneously) prompt
drawn from Scarry’s palms, then it surely is that we must
us to project values and feelings onto the object. In fact, find-
be alive to the world and always exercise a generosity of
ing beauty and projecting meaning are really two sides of a
perception while moving through it. As a rule, everything is
constantly revolving coin. This is what Ruskin would call the
beautiful until proved ugly. Scarry writes that falsely reject-
pathetic fallacy. But as was pointed out before, we are usually
ing objects as not beautiful is an error ‘on the side of a failed
aware of the fact that such meanings and feelings are merely
generosity’ (BBJ 14) and that this error is much graver than
projected. They will surely prompt us, as Scarry claimed, to
claiming beauty for something that turns out to not be beau-
care for the world, but we will not as a rule forget that we
tiful after all; in the second case, one had been overly gener-
are the creators of the world’s beauty. I believe that this is an
ous, which one can never really seriously be. This attitude
important insight for contemporary art, for we have a great
was also expressed by Constable, who once said that ‘there is
number of artists working today who make works that show
nothing ugly; I never saw an ugly thing in my life: for let the
how commonplace objects can reveal deeper meanings. This
form of an object be what it may, light, shade, and perspec-
I believe to be the real transfiguration of the commonplace
tive will always make it beautiful’. But Herbert Read, who
at work in contemporary art: it is not the attachment of criti-
uses this quote in The Philosophy of Modern Art (1952), warns
cal meanings to objects in the way that Danto describes but
us that we should not take this claim at face value because
rather the ability to see beauty in the commonplace because
Constable ‘is making an ethical judgement. It is not light,
the commonplace is infused with meanings and feelings
shade, and perspective which in themselves transform or-
that matter to us. Commonplace objects are today being seen
dinary or even ugly objects into works of art; they are rather
again as what they really are: carriers of meaning. It is one of
transformed by the artist’s feeling’ (Read 1952: 79). So beauty
Marx’s great achievements as a philosopher that he was very
(for I believe it would be better to substitute beauty for art in
keenly aware of this capacity of objects to embody the hu-
Read’s statement) is the effect of a projection of the artist’s
man world. And it is a capacity that is being exploited to the
385
full in the works of a number of important contemporary art-
ing is the mother of all the visual arts: it always comes first.
ists. Several of these will take the limelight in the following
Along with dancing, singing, and writing it is the art form
sections, notably Apichatpong Weerasethakul, Derek Jarman,
that requires the least instruments and the least financial
and Wolfgang Tillmans; but our discussion of their work will
investment: almost anyone can do it almost anywhere. The
in turn prompt us to look at other, equally wonderful bodies
hand, as Marx and Scarry would remind us, is our primary
of work. These discussions are meant to further illuminate
tool to explore, alter, and copy the world. If children with a
our philosophical claims, although I hope the reader will also
talent for the visual arts start making creative works, drawing
enjoy them as a kind of indulgence (we are, after all, dealing
is often the first thing they do. But even in the developed arts,
with beauty, not long division).
the drawing often comes first. There is little sculpture without a preliminary sketch, there is no building built without
386
Doubling
a previous drawing being made, and few figurative paintings
If the eye sees something that is beautiful, the hand wants
are ever painted without a preliminary pencil sketch. Even
to draw it. What better place to start this extended stroll
artists who seek release from form and work in an abstract
through a gallery of beautiful things? But beauty, as we recall,
manner must first master form before they can deconstruct
is expressiveness. And expressive is that which has a form
it. It will not do to simply apply paint randomly to a surface.
evocative of life entirely felt. Beauty is living form. But beauty
To undermine form in a relevant way, one must know it in-
is not only found in art, it is also alive in the everyday world
timately, and many of the great abstract painters or ravish-
and in nature. And for us, human beings, the greatest seat of
ers of classical form were expert draughtsmen themselves,
beauty has always been the human body itself. What form
whether they were Picasso or Andy Warhol.
could be more expressive of life than the vital human body
There is great artistic honesty in the drawing. It provides no
in all its splendour? Whether it is the beautiful youth who
refuge for the mediocre artist. We live in a society that likes
guides Plato to the realm of Ideas or the youth who steps
to think that everything can be taught and that everything
forth as William Blake’s vision of Albion, whether it is Sally
is socially constructed, but it is not. No amount of schooling
Mann’s sensual eye cast upon her children or Courbet’s rivet-
will turn someone with no or only middling talent for draw-
ing portrait of the origin of the world, art never ceases to sing
ing into the next Michelangelo. When pencil and paper are all
the body electric, representing it again and again in its many
there is, the artist cannot hide. No amount of precious theo-
vital manifestations. It is the body beautiful that we most
rising can erase the blemish of a bad drawing. No amount of
revel in. And the medium that is most ready to hand to ex-
theory can convince us that what looks bad on paper is in
press this beauty in art is the human hand. To have the hand
fact a great work of art. Similarly, the fact that no critical or
draw the beautiful body is an amazingly intimate and exhila-
theoretical meanings can be found in a stunningly successful
rating experience. But this should not surprise us since draw-
drawing will never dissuade us from valuing that drawing as
387
388
a wonderful work of art. With drawing you can either do it,
can do what a painting or drawing does. Since a painting or a
or you cannot (in fact, David Hockney has argued that paint-
drawing is always the result of a search, it incorporates many
ing in watercolours requires even greater skill, because no
different moments of looking at the model. Many artists have
mark can be erased; Weschler 2008: 197). Nothing can undo
started to use photographs as source material for their paint-
the immediate effect that good draughtsmanship has on the
ings. And, conversely, photographers have started organising
viewer. But to draw is also an extremely intimate experience.
their portraits like paintings, either modelling their subjects
When the draughtsman puts pencil to paper to draw a beau-
in a specific way or putting them in carefully organised set-
tiful body from life, his hand is following the lines of the body
tings, or simply altering the image afterwards by manipulat-
to repeat them on paper. Drawing is a form of touching: it is
ing the image or, in the case of digital photography, by using
to caress from afar. The eye must sound the depths of every
computer technology to alter the original image or bring
blemish of the body, it must stroke every curve, feel the run
elements from several images together in a new composite
of every line, unfold every fold, and gauge the weight of ev-
image. Either way, whether one paints, draws, or photographs
ery mass. To draw a body is to get to know it intimately. The
a subject, the result will only ever be successful if the art-
draughtman’s primary virtue is attentiveness. He must be
ist succeeds in capturing what Francis Bacon has called a
attentive to the body, both in the sense that he must pay the
person’s emanation or energy. And there are ways in which
closest possible attention to its every detail and in the reli-
drawings or paintings can do this that are not readily avail-
gious sense of Andacht, which approaches the object observed
able to the photographer, and vice versa.
with respectful reservation. To draw is to engage in a profane form of worship.
Body Doubles
As photography became more and more widespread in the
But the doubling of subjects can become especially interest-
nineteenth century, it was widely felt that this new technol-
ing if it does not stop at mere doubling but multiplies the
ogy endangered the art of painting. Photographs could ac-
doubles. This is what the American artist Anthony Goicolea
complish in mere seconds what it took painters much longer
has been doing in his photographs. Goicolea creates bizarre
to do. If painters had spent centuries painting likenesses of
and surrealistic images that are peopled with identical look-
people, their services suddenly seemed to become obsolete
ing boys and girls that seem to have been cloned from one
in view of the photograph’s ability to really capture the mo-
source specimen. This source specimen is the artist himself.
ment. As we know, the advent of photography was one of
In his work, Goicolea is constantly doubling his own image,
the factors that motivated Modernism in its turn away from
but in manipulated and altered ways. In Porn (2000) a bunch
representational art. But in the long run, photography has
of randy teenage Goicolea lookalikes are gorging themselves
not been the undoing of painting or drawing. No photograph,
on junk food while gaping at a porn video. In Premature (2002)
no matter how realistically representational of its subject,
they are having a collective wank as spilt milk drips from
389
390
their hands and onto the floor as if it were sperm. Parochial
these images also evoke a context that lies further back in
(2000) takes us into the dorm of an exclusive Catholic school
time. In Greek mythology there is talk of a very early period
where the boys are defiling the host, the cross, and a bottle
that is called the Golden Age (Kirk 1974: 132-136). Sources
of holy water. In Stigmata (2000) Goicolea has organised three
are unclear about how we should imagine this period, but
of his clones in a mock version of Titian’s Ascension with a
it was clearly a paradisaical period when the land bore fruit
boy clad in candy-coloured sportswear ecstatically casting
without the need for tilling. It was an age of purity, which is
his eyes to heaven while stigmata bleed from his hands.
expressed through ‘parthogenesis, just as Christian salvation
Sanitary towels and tampons lie about in abundance as if
later imagines beginnings in immaculate conception and
they are meant to stop the bleeding. To the side of the image,
virgin birth: flowers blossom sine semine, without seed, with-
a Goicolea clone is taking a shower in a position that seems
out semen, without sexual congress, emissions, and organs’
reminiscent of either the immaculate conception or, more
(Warner 2002: 62). Goicolea has also evoked such a garden
likely, Zeus entering Danaë in a shower of golden rain. Most
of delight in a series of photographs. Cherry Island (2002) is a
of Goicolea’s images are critiques of the American capital-
pleasure garden filled with birds of paradise; until, looking a
ist system, but they are highly ironic and seem to have been
second time, one notices that these gorgeous creatures are
orchestrated by the producers of gay porn films, revelling in
birds of less lofty plumage: peacocks, ducks, pigeons, and
assorted Adidasboys and Scally Lads. Offering up his own
even rabbits people this landscape which, it now also tran-
body as an endlessly repeated altar for our horny libations
spires, is ironically furnished with white plastic garden furni-
Goicolea practices Creation Through Masturbation, which is
ture. Similarly, the idyllic Nesting (2002) shows us the cabin of
a deliciously new way of playing with one’s self. He wanks
a postmodern family Robinson, living among colourful flow-
in the house of mirrors and we are all invited to look on and
ers that have been draped with toilet paper. By peopling his
share in the rubbings.
pictures with clones of himself, Goicolea obviously invokes
Goicolea’s photographs are obviously reminiscent of Fernand
parthogenesis, but in many of his pictures he takes this pro-
Khnopff’s Symbolist paintings in which the ghost-like figure
cess one step further and also reproduces himself as a series
of his sister Marguerite appears simultaneously as several
of girls. In Pregnant (2001) sexual dimorphism is complete:
figures within one image. Similar clones can be seen in the
sporting white socks and a sleaveless undershirt to accentu-
work of Edward Burne-Jones, either in the knights tied to The
ate his smoothly shaved prick, Goicolea looks like the ulti-
Wheel of Fortune (1883) or in the endless row of musical ladies
mate ephebophile’s pin-up; except for his very pregnant belly.
descending The Golden Stairs (1880). Camille Paglia has called
Goicolea’s pictures are luscious, sensual, ironic, narcissistic,
this kind of self-replenishing imagery “allegorical repletion”
and shamelessly sexy. His is truly a world that is constantly
or ‘the filling up of fictive space with a single identity appear-
self-replenishing and self-regenerating. In the video Nail Biter
ing simultaneously in different forms’ (Paglia 1991: 447). But
(2002) he sits up in his bed, anxiously biting his nails which
391
392
seem to grow back instantly until a revolting stream of saliva,
ning L’homme blessé (1983). Next, he showed us the plague-rid-
sticky with masses of bitten nails, drips from his chin onto
den flesh of La reine Margot (1994) and proceeded to Intimacy
the bedclothes. Linked to such fantasies of the self-regen-
(2000), a film about sex without love, and Son Frère (2002),
erating body are the revolutions in gender-bending body-
which displays the frail body invaded by a mysterious dis-
alteration that new developments in medicine have made
ease. The latter film contains a concussively unsettling scene
possible. Orlan’s auto-mutilation through surgery is no longer
in which the protagonist’s naked body is entirely shaved in
the limit of physical metamorphosis in art. Modern surgery
preparation for surgery. The procedure is shown matter-of-
allows the genders to blend together and come apart again.
factly in real time and is almost unbearable to watch. Other
For instance, the porn performer Buck Angel is a hunky, bald-
filmmakers have followed down this path of explicit carnal
headed, and tattooed truck driver who used to be a woman.
imagery, but not always with comparable artistic success.
But he has kept his vagina. Questions of whether his work as
Cathérine Breillat usually casts a cold analytical eye on the
a performer should be labelled gay, straight, or bisexual seem
naked body, most violently in the disturbing À ma soeur
rather beside the point, especially since Buck will bed it all.
(2001). Ulrich Seidl is relentlessly humanist in his disclosures
Sexuality has become polymorphous again. In fact, auto-mu-
of the flesh, particularly in the harsh light he shines on the
tation without a genetic trigger, which is basically what such
inflated fleshy ego of degenerated bourgeois in Hundstage
gender-bending surgery accomplishes, is not even neces-
(2001) and in the unflinching way he confronts us with the
sarily linked to questions of sexual identity anymore. Singer
marginalised body in Tierische Liebe (1995), a stylised docu-
and performance artist Genesis P-Orridge has submitted to
mentary about people and the intimacies they share with
surgery which is meant to make him look like his wife, Jaye
their pets, and Import/Export (2007), his harrowing account
Breyer, whom he married in 1995. P-Orridge is not a transsex-
of the human body as trafficable commodity in contempo-
ual. His desire to change his body to incorporate elements of
rary Europe. Other notable films dealing with the body in its
the opposite sex is triggered by an ideological desire to erase
frail beauty are Sébastien Lifshitz’s melancholy and moving
the boundaries of gender, bring the sexes together within one
Presque rien (2000), the same director’s sensitive exploration
body and hence do away with the politics of sexual oppres-
of transgender bodies in Wild Side (2004), or Jean-Marc Barr’s
sion and objectification that still taint our culture.
bizarre but intensely erotic Too Much Flesh (2000), which is a film about the fuss about foreskin (it is also a film about
Pictures Imperfect
Barr’s own body, which, given Barr’s body, is entirely justifi-
Let us dwell somewhat longer on the human body. In con-
able narcissism).
temporary cinema it has become a primary site of visual
What is striking about all of these films, compared to Goico-
interest. The work of Patrice Chéreau is a wonderful example.
lea’s playfulness, is the fact that the display of the human
The director first made us feel masochistic flesh in the stun-
body is rarely simply about sensuality. The body is shown as
393
394
frail, in pain, diseased, restrained, or hysterical. It is rarely
our own body. This makes us uneasy. The unease is born from
simply erotic. One might well wonder why these filmmakers
the sudden awareness that internal processes might elude
feel they have not adequately expressed their characters’ un-
our control at any time. It takes shockingly little to make the
ease and suffering unless they have shown it inscribed in the
body break, not just literally in the sense of physically break-
characters’ flesh. Why does the body’s surface become the
ing its limbs or back, but also figuratively in the sense that
mirror of the soul and its ailments? Why must the body’s fail-
our intestines and bodily fluids can escape our control at any
ing be shown in such unsettlingly explicit detail? The answer
time and confront us with our debilitating and humiliating
to this question was at least partly given in our earlier dis-
dependency upon the imperfect organic machinery of that
cussion of voyeurism. What is read upon the body contains
soiled interior. What scares us the most is the possibility that
the stuff of truth. The abject body, the body overcome by it-
the inside might come out; that pain or illness might literally
self, is a body surrendered. To show the body in explicit detail
tear us inside out, ripping our body apart with the horrors of
is a mark of authenticity, even in a work of fiction. By con-
vomiting, diarrhoea, and uncontrollable bloodshed through
fronting us with the naked truth about our physical body and
any and every orifice. The body is a vessel, neat and tidy like
its failings these films confront us with our shared humanity.
a Warhol painting of a Campbell’s soup can. But as Wayne
In this respect the bodies they display are comparable to the
Koestenbaum pointed out, inside the can there is the chaos
Andachtsbild in religious art: they are not in the first place
of half-digested foodstuffs. Wanting to keep the lid firmly
objects for the erotic gaze (although they can become that)
shut, we are shocked and upset by films that open up the
but objects for contemplation. This is most clear when the
body physical to our gaze.
body is taken to extremes of suffering because this often also
But the flesh can also be the parchment on which the po-
requires the actor playing the part to submit his own body
etry of our solitude and psychological distress is written.
to punishing alterations. We have already mentioned Chris-
Chéreau’s Intimacy and the series of novellas by Hanif Kurei-
tian Bale’s shocking transformation in The Machinist (2001). A
shi on which it is based offer a fine example of this. Kureishi’s
similar unsettling confrontation with the body takes place in
novella Intimacy (1998) is a relentlessly tender account of the
Steve McQueen’s film Hunger (2008), which is ostensibly about
night in which fortysomething Jay decides to leave his wife
a hunger strike by a group of IRA activists in a British prison
and child. The themes of the novella are further developed in
but which is really an attempt to show us the way the suffer-
a series of associated short stories, as if Kureishi were explor-
ing body comes undone. By taking us into close proximity to
ing the same theme from different angles. All the characters
the frail body of its protagonist (Michael Fassbaender), Hunger
in these stories lack a sense of fulfilment. According to the
traps the viewer in a pavlovian commitment to its subject.
story Nightlight (1997) they are ‘on the move from wife to wife,
Watching the painful torture and undoing of the body on the
husband to husband, lover to lover. A city of love vampires,
screen makes us acutely aware of similar processes inside
turning from person to person, hunting the one who will
395
396
make the difference’ (o.c. 101). The nameless male protago-
reason the sex scenes are unusual is that we rehearsed them
nist of this story seeks solace in weekly Wednesday meetings
in the same way as dialogue scenes.’ For him, ‘the point was
with an anonymous woman in his basement flat. They do
not to show something in particular, but also not to hide
not talk, they have sex, she leaves. ‘He dismisses the idea of
anything. [...] The actors didn’t improvise in these scenes:
speaking, because he can’t take any more disappointment.
each gesture was discussed and they knew exactly where
Nothing must disturb their perfect evenings’ (ibid.). Anony-
the camera was – a matter of respect – so they could hide
mous lust is safe: ‘desiring other women kept me from the
parts of their bodies if they wanted to’ (Falcon 2001: 24). So
exposure and susceptibility of loving just the one. There are
the revelation of the body and its intimate secrets is staged
perils in deep knowledge’ (o.c. 12-13). But carnal knowledge,
in the film. Even though the actors are naked, it is not their
displaying and caressing the intimacies of the flesh, inadver-
nakedness that we see but their characters’ nakedness. This
tently becomes deep knowledge, especially when the ritual
might sound like a facile denial of the actor’s nudity, but it is
is repeated and the body becomes familiar. ‘After a certain
nevertheless an important distinction to make. Just like the
age sex can never be casual. I couldn’t ask for so little. To lay
body in dance, the naked body in film is engaged in creating
your hand on another’s body, or to put your mouth against
living form. It is part of a greater whole, which is the living
another’s – what a commitment that is! To choose someone
symbol of the film. The paradoxical fact that it is not really
is to uncover a whole life. And it is to invite them to uncover
the actors we are watching is in fact often suggested by our
you!’ (o.c. 13)
response to a film. It is very difficult to watch Intimacy as a
This commitment is tied to the fact that the naked body is a
porn film. Although the sex in the film is real and explicit, it
story that involuntarily reveals itself. You cannot have carnal
never addresses us on an exclusively or even primarily sexual
knowledge of another body without being intimate with it.
level. Although explicit, the film’s sex scenes do not turn us
This is the shattering lesson learned by Kureishi’s characters.
on. This is because the naked bodies are vehicles of expres-
But to translate this insight to the screen for the film Intimacy
sion. To use an old distinction: the actors are nude to express
the involuntary revelation of the body had to be undone. Pre-
nakedness. What we see is the characters’ nakedness, not the
paring the film, Kureishi and Chéreau ‘talked about bodies,
actors’. The actors are nude rather than naked because their
about death and decay; about Lucian Freud and Bacon, and
bodies are covered by the form of expression, the fact that
the hyper-realism of some recent photography. [...] We talked
the nakedness they are expressing is not their own.
about what bodies do and what they tell us’ (o.c. xiii). And
Issues of the body as expressive in its nudity are very im-
it very soon became clear that mere exposure of the actors’
portant in contemporary photography. This is especially the
bodies would not do as a means of expressing the characters’
case in the work of the photographers that make up the so-
distress. To attain expressiveness in the film the explicit sex
called “Boston School”. The central figure in this group, who
scenes had to be choreographed. Chéreau explains that ‘the
were also personal friends, is Nan Goldin. The group further
397
398
includes David Armstrong, Mark Morrisroe, Jack Pierson, and
a small blot, a little cut’ (Bathes 1980: 49). It unsettles the
Philip-Lorca diCorcia. Especially the work of Goldin, Morris-
studium because it is unintended, unexpected, and yet sud-
roe, and Pierson seems to be focused on a generous respon-
denly all-important, to the point of becoming, for the viewer,
siveness to people and to the world. But to understand the
the very reason why he or she feels drawn to the photograph.
formal ways in which they create works of emotional inten-
Obviously, this means that the punctum, unlike the studium, is
sity and beauty we must look at Roland Barthes’ beautiful
often intensely personal. It is something that seems to come
book on photography, La chambre claire (1980), where Barthes
out of the picture itself, and yet it is very much something
makes a famous distinction between studium and punctum in
that only becomes visible in the picture through the gaze of a
photography. The studium, as the word itself implies, is about
specific person.
the photographer’s intentions in making a photograph. It is
In many cases the punctum is the real reason why we like a
what he or she wants to show us. The enjoyment derived
photograph. It could be argued that many of the classicis-
from appreciating a photograph’s studium is intellectual or
ing nudes of, say, Herbert List, George Platt-Lines, or Robert
academic: it is about “getting” the message and reading all
Mapplethorpe are very successful in an academic sense but
the signs correctly. As Margaret Iversen explains, ‘a photo-
not very exciting in a sensual way. It would be interesting to
graph with only a studium stays put within the confines of
ask oneself, while perusing their work, whether we like the
the picture – its coherence is entirely internal. In contrast, the
pictures we especially like because they are better than the
punctum breaks up that coherence bursting through the frame
others stylistically (because of their studium) or because we
and plane’ (Iversen 1994: 456). The punctum shatters the well-
are personally more attracted to the body or the face of the
organised surface (or discourse) of the picture. It disturbs the
men who are portrayed. The same question seems relevant to
photograph’s coherence because it is an element in the pho-
all erotic art: do we like an image because it is a good image
tograph that was not meant to be there, but it is there never-
or because we find the bodies in it attractive? And hot on the
theless and suddenly draws all our attention to it. The punc-
heels of this question should come another question, namely
tum can be many things. In a photograph that is a portrait of
whether liking an image because the bodies in it are attrac-
a sports team our attention can be drawn by a figure in the
tive is not at least part of the point of erotic art. In any case,
background; and suddenly the picture becomes all about that
it is clear that punctum will often play a large part in deciding
person and not about the team. It can be a detail in clothing,
whether we like an image; and it is certainly instrumental in
a fascinating element in a body, something taking place in
deciding whether we will become obsessed with a certain im-
the background; in fact, it can be anything that grasps our at-
age. The most powerful images in our experience are usually
tention but that was not meant to be part of the photograph’s
not experienced as powerful on the strength of their studium
studium or subject when the photographer made the picture.
alone. This means that it can be to the benefit of a photog-
In this sense, says Barthes, punctum is ‘a prick, a puncture,
rapher to have a punctum-effect in photography. This would
399
400
mean, in a very general way, that a photographer might at-
137). Goldin’s attitude was profoundly influenced by the New
tempt to consciously introduce elements in his or her work
York underground scene of the 1960s, and especially Warhol’s
that have a considerable chance of being experienced as a
Factory with its glamorous transvestites, and the work of
kind of punctum. In this way, and somewhat perversely, punc-
Larry Clark. ‘I was documenting my life,’ Goldin explains. ‘The
tum would become part of the studium, something one at-
only person who was documenting his own experience was
tempts to achieve. To be sure, this is not a simple thing to do
Larry Clark. His work gave me some sense of a precedent’
and is often a good recipe for certain failure: by wanting the
(ibid.). The basis of Goldin’s work is therefore the snapshot,
punctum too much, the photograph might very well end up
‘the form of photography that is most defined by love’ (o.c.
looking contrived.
450) because it captures an intimate moment in an image. For
But there is a way around this problem. The solution might
Goldin, ‘it’s not a detachment to take a picture. It’s a way of
be to engage in a kind of photography that is essentially
touching somebody – it’s a caress. I’m looking with a warm
about the kinds of themes and motifs that are intimately as-
eye, not a cold eye’ (o.c. 452).
sociated with punctum. This would mean a very personal and
Making a photograph of the human body, then, need not be
intimate kind of photography that would be related to the di-
about “objectification” at all. In fact, Goldin claims that ‘it’s
ary format in literature. The “Boston School” to a large extent
about trying to feel what another person is feeling. There’s a
fits such an approach of photography, although they were not
glass wall between people, and I want to break it’ (o.c. 448).
the first photographers to attempt it. It could be argued that
But to attain such intimacy in a photographic image it is of-
the invention of “street photography” in the 1960s (which we
ten not sufficient to simply record the intimate. Creating the
discussed in Chapter Two) set the tone for images that were
punctum, not as a willed detail in an image but as the overall
not academically perfect and that actively sought out themes
feel of a body of photographic work, often involves consider-
and motifs that related to the casual, the incidental, the per-
able skill and craft. This becomes especially clear in the work
sonal, and the individual. One of the first artists to actively
of Mark Morrisroe (1959-1989). Where Goldin’s photographs
turn the diary-like photography of his life and the life of his
often have the feel of the documentary approach, including
friends into photographic art was Larry Clark, notably in his
the fact that she often works in series and has produced an
book Tulsa (1971). A similar approach, but much less focused
immense amount of images for semi-narrative books like
on the seamy side of life, is to be found in the underrated
The Devil’s Playground (2003), Morrisroe’s works is much more
work of Will McBride. As Nan Goldin explains, ‘when I started
obviously technically manipulated. Jack Pierson once claimed
photographing seriously in ’71, ’72, ’73, art photography was
that ‘Mark’s work is like Caspar David Friedrich in a donut
basically rocks and trees and perfect printing and, right from
shop’ (Heinrich 1998: 109), a claim that goes some way to
the beginning, David [Armstrong] and I were the dust-and-
describing the texture of Morrisroe’s work. Morrisroe’s photo-
scratch school. We only cared about content’ (Goldin 1996:
graphs often look grainy and sensual. They seem to have the
401
402
texture of oil painting. To achieve this effect, the artist would
simply express or record intimate occasions. In order for it to
use two negatives, one in colour and one in black and white,
be art, it must be processed into an object given for our aes-
put one on top of the other and then print the image. He
thetic consideration; something more than a page torn from
would further add all kinds of blemishes and errors, such as
a diary. Jack Pierson, for example, also achieves a very intense
scratches and fingerprints, to enhance a sense of found pho-
overall punctum in his work, but in contrast to Goldin and
tography, as if these grainy, slightly discoloured images had
Morrisroe he achieves it through a form of hightened reality.
only recently been retrieved from someone’s attic: relics from
He emphasises the momentary and the melancholy through
other lives and other voices in other rooms. To match this ef-
under- or over-exposure and especially through painting over
fect, the content of Morrisroe’s images is often melancholy. In
his printed images in sometimes very vivid colours. Just like
Self-Portrait with Broken Finger, Christmas 1984 (1984) Morrisroe
the other artists of the “Boston School” his aim is to create a
turned his camera on his own body, and not for the last time,
personal record of people and places. ‘What I primarily want
crouching naked in front of a mirror, his right hand bandaged
is an emotional reaction,’ he explains. But he adds that ‘it
and his lean naked body cloaked in the half-light. Fascination
was easier to evoke feelings if things were not perfect. The
(1983) is one of his most striking self-portraits, lying in bed,
pictures are simply more real then’ (Heinrich 1998: 141). Peter
looking vaguely like Rimbaud, but with his arm outstretched
Weiermair has written that in Pierson’s work ‘photography
above him and a small bird perched on top of it. Much of his
becomes a medium for escape from the world, for stylisation
work is devoted to chronicling his own physical decline as he
and also for lies’. He also claims that photography for Pierson
battled aids, a theme that is also a major thread in Goldin’s
is ‘a means of transforming real circumstances into a state of
work.
glamour’ (in Pierson 1997: 6). But such a glamorised version
It is clear that artists such as Clark, Goldin, and Morrisroe
of a melancholy reality need not be a place of lies. It can just
practice a highly stylised form of photographic autobiogra-
as easily be read as a vision infused with dream reality. It is
phy. Although their work is intensely personal, it is so in two
the hyperreality of dreams, where events take on a slightly
ways. First, and most obviously, in the choice of subject mat-
exaggerated feel which makes them even more evocative of
ter. But second, and less obviously, in several kinds of formal
reality. To heighten an image’s intensity through glamour can
procedures that clearly mark these photographs as works
also result in a heightened emotional impact, in Pierson’s
of art. These formal procedures are also intensely personal
case a sense of melancholy sensuality, a world of lovers in
in the sense that they are highly individual. Lovers of their
motel rooms, abandoned fairgrounds, and kitchen sinks scat-
work can spot a Goldin picture or a Morrisroe from afar: these
tered with the colour patterns of plastic flowers and bottles
photographers have a signature style that is all their own.
of detergent.
This again underscores the intimate link between feeling and form that Langer never tired of stressing. It is not sufficient to
403
404
Scattergorising the World
look, rules formed by others. Instead one can create a perso-
The most generous photographic outlook on the world can
na and identity of one’s own beyond all commercial interests’
be found in the work of Wolfgang Tillmans, whose engage-
(Birnbaum 2006: 28). This attitude has remained central to
ment with the world is adequately summarised in the title
Tillmans’ work and should remind us of Kondylis’ notion of
of his 2003 exhibition at the Tate in London: if one thing mat-
the spatial expanse of equality that is foundational for post-
ters, everything matters. In a conscious swerve away from what
modern culture. The belief that one’s identity is something
he calls the “language of importance” (Birnbaum 2006: 18)
that one can largely piece together without guidance from
Tillmans’ art is radically anti-hierarchical. Contrary to what
any kind of authority is intrinsically linked to the idea that
is a widespread assumption Tillmans did not start his career
any kind of choice or combination, except those harmful to
as a photographer for fashion magazines. In fact, Russell
others, is legitimate. The patchwork concept of postmodern
Ferguson points out that ‘Tillmans has never had anything
identity necessarily implies the principle of equality in diver-
resembling a conventional career as a fashion photographer.
sity.
He has never shot for any advertising campaign, and he
Tillmans has introduced this principle into his work, which
does not allow his work to be used for advertising. His sub-
centres on a wide array of topics. There are portraits of
jects are rarely wearing high-profile logos or brands, except
friends and lovers, there is landscape photography, urban
perhaps the ubiquitous and inescapable Levis and Adidas.
landscapes, still lives, and even abstract work. Tillmans
[...] His recurrent themes – quiet observation of nature and
treats every subject with the same kind of love and atten-
everyday things; hanging out with friends; sex; political activ-
tion, whether it is Damon Albarn taking a shower or a piece
ism; dancing – are all free. None of them involves buying or
of fruit on the window sill. His choice of subjects and style
selling’ (Ferguson 2006: 76). But Tillmans did use magazine
of photography has proved immensely influential, not only
spreads, and especially the works he published in i-D in the
among other artists but among the larger populace. ‘Life
early 1990s, as a way of finding new, less elitist ways of com-
imitates art,’ Daniel Birnbaum has noted, ‘and thanks to the
municating with the world; a world that would be consider-
“Tillmans effect” many of us recognise our own Tillmans pic-
ably larger than the artworld in-crowd. In fact, Tillmans came
tures or situations right in front of us, out there in the world’
to prominence as the most important photographer of the
(o.c. 18). In this sense Tillmans’ work clearly illustrates how
Love Generation of the 1990s, the culture of house music and
art can alter the way we look at the world. His way of look-
Berlin Love Parades that seemed to herald a new era that
ing often fundamentally alters the way his audience looks at
would be less materialistic and less capitalist than the 1980s
the world through what Paul Flynn has called ‘his signature
of Reaganomics and Thatcherist oppression. When Tillmans
ability to find the extraordinary in the ordinary through his
was publishing in i-D the magazine ‘made clear that nobody
camera’ (Flynn 2010: 96). But it should be clear that Tillmans
has to subscribe to official rules of how to behave and how to
does not simply stumble upon the extraordinary by chance,
405
406
as if he were somehow prone to uncovering it. He seeks it
photographs, too. Paradoxically, they seem all the more im-
out. Mark Wigley has quoted Tillmans as saying ‘that “photog-
mediate’ (ibid.). But Tillmans’ style does not stop at lighting.
raphy always lies about what it is in front of the camera but
His sense of space is stunning and extremely precise. Mark
never lies about what is behind.” It captures the experience,
Wigley has pointed out that Tillmans’ kind of ‘architectural
the thinking, behind the image. Photography is a psychologi-
space is not simply found in the world. The majority of Till-
cal rather than a technological medium. It is a way of pro-
mans’ images are in some way staged. [...] In each case, all
jecting thinking into the world and sharing that experience’
evidence of rearrangement is removed so that the staged
(Wigley 2006: 150-154). This implies that Tillmans is anything
scenes are experienced as found, and the found scenes are
but a snapshot photographer. He is an artist who takes great
experienced as precisely staged. [...] No clue is offered as to
care in creating his images; but he creates them in a way that
the choreographing of each scene, preserving the sense of a
makes them look casual.
rich found world. So each image appears halfway between
The fact that Tillmans’ images are very deliberately authored
the world and the photographer’ (Wigley 2006: 150). As a con-
is especially obvious in one of the genres for which he initial-
sequence, fact and fiction merge, as do feeling and form, in
ly became recognised: portraiture. What sets Tillmans’ photo-
the way Tillmans guides the world into appearance.
graphic portraits apart from others is the way they are light-
One of the double layers in Tillmans’ work is the way his
ed. As Tillmans himself explains, ‘I got rid of everything that’s
loving looks at the world imply an unobtrusive but very radi-
artistic in portraiture [...]. I found a way of indirect lighting
cal political statement that is exactly about his belief that
that looks like the absence of artificial light. That’s often
everything in the world is deserving of equal consideration.
been misunderstood as a lack of formality, and dismissed as
As Tillmans himself puts it, ‘the eyes are a great subversive
the dreaded “snapshot aesthetic”’ (Ferguson 2006: 81). What
tool because they technically don’t underlie any control, they
looks least formal in Tillmans is in fact the most deliberately
are free when used freely’ (Birnbaum 2006: 16). Tillmans sug-
formalised aspect of his work. But his lighting technique is
gests that our ability to see for ourselves and to use our gaze
so firmly welded to the content of his images that it is barely
consciously is a strong subversive tool because it allows us
noticed by the viewer. As Russell Ferguson has said, ‘it is all
to deconstruct and undermine the stories that are told about
but invisible, but it is very important. He generally keeps it
the world and that are presented us as truth, as inescapable
flat, most often by bouncing a hand flashgun intuitively into
realities, or as economic, political, or cultural necessities.
the room, preferably off a white wall somewhere. This tech-
By looking at the world with a generous eye that spreads its
nique largely eliminates shadows, thus giving the picture a
attention equally among all things we can develop a sense
clarity and a directness that is understated but unmistakable.
of reality that is at odds with the requirements and needs of
We tend to edit out shadows from our consciousness of what
global capitalism. Like Baudelaire’s painter of modern life,
we see in daily life. Tillmans keeps them mostly out of his
Tillmans’ roving eye seeks out the eternal in the everyday,
407
408
not in the sense of reading the world as metaphysical scrip-
Klein has called “disaster capitalism,” which sees natural and
ture, but by finding value, and lasting and profound value, in
social tragedies and disasters as opportunities for lucrative
everything, even in that which the dominant culture wants
moneymaking (Klein 2008: 6). Along with this new and ag-
to discard. This sense of equality also lies at the heart of
gressive capitalist culture a new world order has come about
Tillmans’ exhibition practices. When showing his works, he
that was given fuel by the attacks on the World Trade Center
often hangs them with binder clips or tape. He also hangs
on September 11, 2001. Since then the world is often repre-
original works next to magazine spreads. Although it is com-
sented as bifurcated along the lines of Them and Us. But the
mon for artists to present their works in new combinations
fault-lines that divide us do not simply run along continents
at every exhibition it is far less common for every presenta-
or cultures, they are within every community, where differ-
tion of the work to consciously display this openness to new
ences in race, religion, class, and gender cause communities
combinations. By using binder clips or tape Tillmans always
to disintegrate from within. Tillmans has said that ‘I believe
shows that whatever the presentation is, it could always have
that the greatest problem of our time are people who claim to
been different. Every combination of images is temporary and
possess absolute truths’ (Jäger 2008: 35). The truth study center
everything is constantly being rearranged, both in the exhibi-
started as a reflection on the nature of truth. But instead of
tion and in the world that is represented in it.
hanging his images on walls, Tillmans now presented them
The fundamental importance of these ever-changing com-
on cheap-looking, vitrine-like tables, where he would often
binations in Tillmans’ exhibitions should again remind us
combine them with newspaper clippings and advertisements.
of Kondylis’ analysis of the postmodern. We build our world,
By presenting the images on tables the relative nature of the
and project our meanings onto the world, by continually
combinations is even more in evidence, producing serendipi-
combining new elements, undoing existing combinations
tous associations of all kinds of imagery and texts. As Russell
and initiating new ones. This approach has become especially
Ferguson has observed, the images in truth study center are
clear in Tillmans’ exhibition project truth study center, which
categorised in a non-systematic way through ‘undeclared
was also made into a book. If the world is the result of our
categories, non-categories. The flow from one to another is
combinations of meanings and objects, the entire concept
continuous’ (Ferguson 2006: 66). As a result, Truth is held in
of truth becomes problematic. But where our continual con-
abeyance. But this does not entail a facile kind of relativism.
frontation with the relative value of truths should make us
Rather, Tillmans would hold that truth is always in the par-
more tolerant of diversity, the opposite is happening in the
ticular, created by and for human beings in the here and now
world. The change in culture that Tillmans’ generation of the
of lived experience.
early 1990s expected has not come about. On the contrary, the new millennium has brought a new upsurge of capitalist greed, notably in the relentless destruction of what Naomi
409
410
Optics of Desire
there is something in the image that renders it inexhaustible.
Tillman’s generosity in looking at the world is particularly in
It takes possession of us and of our gaze. It makes the image
evidence in the way he looks at people. His portraits, but also
irresistible.
his male nudes, are a continuation of the punctum-centred
In Tillmans’ erotic imagery, this punctum is linked to pieces of
photography we found in the work of Nan Goldin. Whether
clothing. This requires us to further elaborate our discussion
he photographs bodies or the clothes that have been shed by
of fetishism and voyeurism. For a fetishist, pieces of cloth-
those bodies, whether he photographs individual bodies or
ing, and especially items of clothing that are associated with
groups of dancing bodies in ecstasy, Tillmans’ work always
intimate parts of the body or with bodily secretions such as
has the feel of immediate experience. They hover on the
sweat, become carriers of meaning. They are infused with
verge of becoming tangible. Helen Molesworth claims that
the wearer’s essence, drenched in what is hidden inside the
she cannot find any punctum in Tillmans’ work, no moments
body and carried outside in minute particles. This concept of
of desire or longing (Tillmans 1996: x). This is true only in the
fetishism is brilliantly illustrated in Tillmans’ Genome (2002),
sense that his images, and especially his early portraits, are
a duotone photograph of a hallway that is littered with dis-
so consciously staged as to leave nothing to coincidence. But
carded black socks. The socks look like short strands of the
what is created through this highly stylised approach is an
human DNA-string, which is the map of our bodies’ inner
image that is all-over-punctum: what is created, is the illusion
structure. But at the same time the socks are obvious objects
of something spontaneous. I would say that many of Till-
of fetishistic attention: worn for sports, they are imbued
mans’ pictures express nothing but desire and longing. Except
with sweat, they carry skin flakes and randy smells. By call-
that this longing and this desire are not to be found in the
ing them genomes Tillmans makes us see in them the shape
details that usually carry the punctum-effect. Longing and de-
of genomes, which in turn recalls the profound biological
sire are the very fabric of the images. ‘Confronted by a wall of
foundation of fetishism, which is about possessing the body’s
his photographs,’ David Deitcher observes in Tillmans’ mono-
interior. By stuffing the sock in his mouth, a masochist might
graph Burg (1998), ‘I am possessed by a powerful desire to
very well suck up (or might very well imagine he were suck-
know things. [...] I look for the links between them. [...] I look
ing up) a person’s most intimate biological body chart along
for the significant detail, as if it might provide me with ac-
with the sweat. But despite this strong fetishistic charge the
cess to domestic places and private rituals.’ Daniel Birnbaum
image retains a sense of fun, recalling that fetishism is also a
has commented that many of Tillmans’ photographs, and
kind of game, and a form of edge-play. It is a roundabout way
not simply the erotic images, ‘seem inexhaustible. [...] I can
of dealing with the body. But it is crucial to Tillmans’ sense
return to some of his pictures over and over again and every
of eroticism for, as David Deitcher observes in Burg, ‘when
time experience the same sense of something fundamentally
Tillmans wants to project sexual longing, he focuses on the
inscrutable’ (Birnbaum 2006: 16). This is the effect of punctum:
fetish instead of the man’.
411
412
Tillmans has an entire wardrobe of fetishist imagery, most
us feel the erotic tension, the thrill of the forbidden and of
famously, and also most beautifully, his Faltenwurf-series,
maybe getting caught, that must have guided Tillmans’ hand
which shows pieces of clothing draped or casually thrown
as he took the photograph.
(staged or found) on pieces of furniture or on a staircase.
‘I had this desire for many years to capture what I see in front
Another series shows glistening close-up shots of Adidas
of my eyes during rush hour,’ Tillmans once explained in an
shorts in glorious red or blue. One of his most iconic erotic
interview. ‘This public intimacy, this closeness is only pos-
images is Sportflecken (1996), a white T-shirt that is stained
sible or workable because we accept that it’s taboo’ (Eshun
yellow with an abundance of sweat. ‘To look at Sportflecken,’
2000: 105). We know that people packed on trains and buses
Deitcher correctly notes, ‘is to imagine the body of the person
are in fact engaged in a possibly explosive sexual exchange.
who once filled that T-shirt.’ Although the body is gone and
They invade each other’s private space with their smells,
the T-shirt discarded, it can almost make us feel the pres-
their clothes, their bags and cases, and with their bodies. To
ence of warm flesh, heated by the exertions of sports (When
keep public life manageable we often deny the erotic charge
Robert Mapplethorpe used pieces of clothing in his fetishistic
of such situations. The voyeur takes advantage of this small
early sculptures, Patti Smith would sometimes ask him: ‘Can
rupture between what we know and what we acknowledge
I wear this? Or is it art?’; Morrisroe 1995: 75). But as his erotic
we know and peers in through the edges. Public intimacy
imagery developed, Tillmans sometimes skipped the fetish
is at the heart of a series of photographs Tillmans made of
and went straight for the man, albeit still in a furtive man-
people, or rather fragments of people, on the London subway,
ner. When they look at men with a desiring eye, Tillmans’
simply naming the photographs after the line on which the
photographs often operate along the lines of the voyeur’s
picture was made. Again, it is not at all clear to what extent
gaze. Jeremy (1993), for instance, shows us the bare torso of a
these pictures were staged and lighted or simply made with-
young man, the tough looking buckle of his belt, and the can
out their subjects’ knowledge. One of Tillmans’ most power-
of beer he is holding in his hand. This image brings us into
ful erotic images is Bakerloo Line (2000), a black and white
close proximity to a man who looks like the type who would
photograph that looks into the short sleeve of a man’s T-shirt
not welcome this kind of homosexual attention in real life.
as he steadies himself on the subway. The photograph’s and
Similar furtive glances can be found in the book Soldiers: the
our gaze are directed straight at the young man’s armpit.
nineties (1999), a collage of found photographs of soldiers and
Armpits have a very high erotic charge in gay fetishism. This
some of Tillmans’ own photographs. Among his own works,
should not surprise us since it is one of the places where the
Tillmans included two shots of a soldier seen from the rear as
human body is apt to sweat and smell the most. By peeping
he leans against a door in a train (Soldat I and Soldat II, 1996).
into the young man’s armpit Bakerloo Line allows us to share
It is unclear whether the soldier knew his picture was be-
the furtive erotic charge of secretly looking at other people’s
ing taken, but the photograph suggests he didn’t and makes
bodies in public. The title of the photograph, as indeed the
413
414
titles of all the photographs in the series, stresses the ano-
and no doubt a coincidence subsequently exploited by Till-
nymity and fleeting nature of such visual encounters, noting
mans, that the patterns that these experiments brought into
the geographical location where it occurred rather than the
being should have both cosmic and fleshly connections. By
person’s name (which is presumably unknown anyway).
taking on the texture and structure of the human body seen
But this was not Tillmans’ first photograph of an armpit. He
up close, and especially the texture of muscle tissue, these
had earlier portrayed one in the aptly titled armpit (1992; Fer-
abstract images seem to take us into the moist inner space of
guson and Molon 2006: 85). This was a close-up of an armpit
the human body, moving among and feeling the soft tissues
sticky with sweat, retrieved from the club scene. But I feel it
and pulsating masses that generate the movements that in
has an uncanny resemblance to one of Tillmans’ abstract im-
turn cause sweat to be excreted. Journeying inside the body,
ages, Freischwimmer 40 (2004). The latter picture is part of a se-
these abstract images fall back into cosmic surrender.
ries of abstract images that Tillmans started to create in 1998.
This ties together many strands of Tillmans’ work. As the
These are pictures created without a camera, simply by dis-
artist himself once said, ‘paradise is maybe when you dis-
persing or scattering photosensitive materials on paper and
solve your ego – a loss of self, being in a bundle of other bod-
exposing them to light. The series have luscious names like
ies’ (Birnbaum 2006: 28). But it were such bundles of bodies
Freischwimmer, Blushes, or Peaches and the texture of the pat-
that filled the clubs where Tillmans started his career. In fact,
terns created by the crystals on the paper has a curvacious
the photograph Knotenmutter (1994) shows a knot of two bod-
sensuality that often resembles body parts or the texture of
ies intertwined, making it difficult to tell at first sight which
muscles. Daniel Birnbaum has called these works ‘ecstatic
arms and legs belong to which of the two bodies. It is as if
pages of cosmic flesh’ (Birnbaum 2006: 24) and ‘a pure writ-
these boys were melting together to form one new entity.
ing of light’ (Birnbaum 2008b: 7), which recalls the language
Taking this erotic loss of self even further, we might connect
of alchemy. But Birnbaum also links these images to August
back to Hermann Nitsch and his Dionysian revels. Camille
Strindberg’s so-called “celestographs”: photographs created
Paglia has suggested that the ecstatic dancing at discos and
by exposing photographic plates directly to the starry sky (o.c.
clubs could be interpreted as a resurgence of pagan ritual in
8). So the cosmos and the body seem to merge in these imag-
a post-Christian world (Paglia 1993: 23). Like the maenads
es, creating expanses of matter that echo the textures of the
dancing in honour of Dionysos, connecting with the void, the
body physical. It could even be argued that they represent yet
revellers at contemporary clubs become one with the bodies
another step in Tillmans’ voyeuristic endeavour to lay bare
around them and together make up the cosmos of the physi-
the hidden depths of the body. After all, Mark Wigley urges
cal. There may be melancholy quiet in Tillmans’ work, and
us not to forget that ‘for all its sensuous beauty, the image is
tender politics of polymorphous erotics, but in connecting
a laboratory test, a forensic exposure of the raw materials of
back to the world the tremendous force of something cosmic
the art’ (Wigley 2006: 156). It is a most fortuitous coincidence,
is always at play.
415
416
Imagining Petals
O’Keeffe takes the imagining of flowers out of our mind and
One of Tillmans’ greatest images is Grey jeans over stair post
into the real world. To understand how she does that, we
(1991), which shows a pair of grey jeans draped over a stair
must look at Elaine Scarry’s investigation of imagination in
post. To the right of the jeans we see the soft red tones of
Dreaming by the Book (2001).
the carpet on the stairs, to the left there is simply a bright
Scarry starts from the observation that we actually seem to
white light, probably daylight. The banister, in the middle
experience imagination going on in our forehead. ‘When we
of the image, is covered by a white T-shirt. The stair post
think of images somewhere on the inside of the body, we
bulges phallus-like through the bottom of the jeans. The
habitually think of them as residing inside the head’ (DB 46).
image recalls Robert Mapplethorpe’s sexualised images of
The forehead is ‘the habitual space for interior imagining’
Calla Lilies, which are in turn indebted to Georgia O’Keeffe’s
(DB 47). But she adds that it is equally easy ‘to carry out one’s
lusciously sexual images of flowers. O’Keeffe’s flower imag-
imagining in other parts of the body: for example, one may
ery has long been controversial, not in the least because the
picture Pegasus in one’s forehead, but one can also imagine
artist herself was often unhappy about the sexual meanings
him in one’s forearm or in one’s forefinger’ (DB 46). But Scarry
that were read into them. But these meanings are obviously
adds a note in which she records Robert Nozick’s reaction to
there. In fact, since flowers actually are the sexual organs of
this mental experiment. In fact, Nozick ‘questioned whether
plants, the visual link between them and human genitals is
the image in the forearm is really in the forearm or in a pic-
a very natural one. By choosing flowers as a subject, O’Keeffe
ture of the forearm held in the forehead’ (DB 256). I believe
was challenging traditional ideas about what was a suitable
Nozick’s observation is quite correct: if I try to imagine a
subject for women artists. Instead of painting her flowers in
minute Pegasus in my finger, this is remarkably easy, but I
nice little watercolours, O’Keeffe painted them in oils and
am not imagining Pegasus in my finger in the sense that my
on a grand scale that was usually the preserve of sublime
finger becomes the space of imagining; rather, I am imagin-
landscapes or cityscapes. She simply dismissed the idea
ing in my forehead a picture of my finger in which a minus-
that flowers were not an appropriate subject for serious art.
cule Pegasus can be found. So the forehead does seem to be
‘I’m one of the few artists, maybe the only one today, who is
the primary space for imagining. And one of the remarkable
willing to talk about my work as pretty,’ she wrote in 1924. ‘I
things Scarry notices, is the ease with which we can imagine
don’t mind it being pretty. I think it’s a shame to discard this
flowers inside that space. If we imagine a human figure, a
word; maybe if we work on it hard enough we can make it
horse, a landscape, or even a human face, it is very difficult
fashionable again’ (Drohojowska-Philp 2004: 246). But apart
to see all the details in our mind’s eye. But a flower emerges
from that, the giant size of her flowers also forces the audi-
in full detail with very little effort. The ease with which we
ence to really look at them. Flowers are easy to overlook.
imagine flowers is due to what Scarry calls ‘the ratio of ex-
But they are easy to imagine. By painting them extra-large,
tension to intensity’ (DB 53). If an imagined object has a size
417
418
that is comparable to the size of our interior space of imagi-
our space of imagining, emerging in vibrant directness. But
nation, the image is perceived in greater detail. To imagine a
an opposite approach is also possible, as is shown in the work
horse or a landscape, the image must be reduced in size to
of the Swiss-Dutch artist Regula Maria Müller. She creates
fit it into our mental projection room. In reduction, details,
small sculptures of flowers and other organisms out of beads,
and hence a degree of intensity, get lost. But flowers are just
threads, and pieces of blown glass. She reproduces in reality
the right size to fit the inside of our head. That is why, when
the kind of intense detail that Scarry associates with flowers
they emerge, they immediately emerge in full detail. Another
imagined in the mind. By using beads and glass, shimmer-
reason why we so easily imagine flowers is what Scarry calls
ing materials that are fragile to the touch, Müller enhances
(with a word borrowed from Aristotle) their rarity: the fact
the preciousness we naturally associate with flowers. There
that their petals are thin and veil-like, so that one can see the
is a tremendous vivacity in her work, making it seem almost
light shining through them. Things imagined, Scarry writes,
more alive than actual reality. This way, Müller seems to in-
are rarely solid. Images in the mind have a ghost-like quality:
vert the normal creative process. As we saw, the artist usually
they appear to be weightless and hover before the mind’s eye.
takes a motif or a material from the world and transforms
When the object imagined shares this gossamer-like quality
it into something imaginary, something fictional. Müller, on
in real life, it is very easy to imagine it. That is why it is very
the other hand, seems to have taken something imaginary,
easy to imagine a fog, a veil, or a ghost, which are all sheer
namely the vivacity of imagined flowers, and made it real.
substances, but it is difficult to image a car, a face, or a build-
In her work, she creates the illusion of aliveness that is usu-
ing. ‘Phenomena in the actual physical world that have [the]
ally associated with objects imagined. If we remember David
attributes of transparency and filminess (such as thin cur-
Hockney’s observation that our eyes can only focus on one
tains, fog, and mist) can be more easily imitated in the mind
point at a time, it is clear that we can never really take in the
than can thick or substantive phenomena. The gossamer
splendour of beautiful things in one view. Since mental im-
quality of many flowers [...], the thinness and transparency of
ages do not rely on the optics of the eye, they can appear to
the petals [...] gives them a kinship with the filmy substance-
us in greater vivacity and with greater directness than objects
lessness of mental images’ (DB 59-60). Therefore flowers are
in the real world. By reproducing such mental images on a
easy to summon before the mind’s eye.
small scale, and with materials that reproduce an experience
It is now clear what we mean when we say that O’Keeffe took
of vivacity through effects of shimmering colours and light,
imagined flowers out of our heads and into the world. By
Müller creates the illusion of objects, and flowers at that, that
painting flowers on a size much larger than the human head,
have been lifted straight out of the mind’s eye and put out
she forces us to look at them with an intensity that is even
there in the world for our physical perception and delecta-
greater than the intensity of imaginary flowers. The paintings
tion. In their elaborate yet refined beauty, Müller’s objects
flood our field of vision in the same way imagined flowers fill
seem hyperreal and preternaturally beautiful.
419
420
The same opulence can be found in the work of Welsh artist
What the Dreamachine incites you to see is yours... your
Cerith Wyn Evans, who also addresses imagination and vi-
own. The brilliant interior visions you so suddenly see whirl-
sion in his work, whether it is in the rarity of super-imposed
ing around inside your head are produced by your own brain
slide projections (The sky is thin as paper here..., 2004) or in
activity’ (Dwyer 1999: 70).
his use of neon lights in his many installations. A series of
Evans’ installatians are radiant works of light and transpar-
chandeliers created between 2003 and 2007 are attempts to
ency. Their gorgeous beauty derives from the fact that they
bring into consciousness processes of meaning that usually
can turn a commonplace environment into something that
remain beneath the radar of felt experience. The chandeliers,
looks as if it is dreamed. He bestows upon the material world
which often were opulent works of design or hand-blown
the rarity of imagined worlds. For instance, Arr/Dep (Imaginary
glass, burned in pulsating light patterns. These patterns were
Landscape for the Birds) (2006) was a project created for the
anything but random: they were transmitting texts in Morse
Lufthansa Aviation Center at Frankfort airport. It is a chande-
code, ‘transformed into pulsing light’ (Birnbaum 2008a: 23).
lier that was assembled from lines representing the air routes
Literary texts, poems, philosophical tracts, or any other kind
that connect cities all over the world (one cannot help but see
of text were translated into Morse code and programmed into
this work in conjunction with Wolfgang Tillmans’ series of
the pulsating pattern of the chandelier. Daniel Birnbaum has
photos of the Concorde, 1997, following its tracks through the
compared the messages of the chandeliers to channelling
sky). Daniel Birnbaum describes the work as ‘a kind of three-
because ‘voices – translated into light signals – reach us from
dimensional drawing [that] hovers weightlessly and mysteri-
the past, from the future or from a place that is impossible
ously in its crystal container, and in the evening and the early
to define in temporal terms’ (ibid.). The works are ‘about in-
morning hours you get the sense that the entire building is
voking other subjects, other zones of experience that remain
turned into one massive lamp’ (o.c. 27). But despite its beauty,
radically inaccessible to the viewer’ (o.c. 25). But the idea of
the work is also political, for in its representation of global
channelling messages through light was not entirely original
aerial trade routes it is in a very real sense ‘the most alluring
to Evans, who was inspired by Brion Gysin’s famous Dreama-
and stylish portrayal of something that probably cannot be
chine, an instrument that was designed to generate mental
portrayed, Global capital’ (ibid.). If we agree with Birnbaum’s
visions. The Dreamachine is a metal cylinder with a series of
interpretation then Arr/Dep takes the project of the earlier
geometric patterns stamped out. Inside there is a light that
chandeliers a step further. Instead of broadcasting existing
shines through the openings. Once the Dreamachine starts
texts through chandeliers, Arr/Dep succeeds in visualising a
spinning one must look at it with the eyes closed. The stro-
concept that only exists as an idea in our collective imagina-
boscopic effect of the light flashes will then generate visions
tion. As such, it underlines the fantasmatic nature of global
in the mind. As Gysin himself explained, ‘you are the artist
capital. It is a fiction, a dream dreamt by the rich and power-
when you approach a Dreamachine with your eyes closed.
ful on the backs of the poor and the oppressed. That is the
421
sting in the tail of its beauty, for what it represents is the
a metaphor for the loss of memory, then it could be argued
dialectic of Enlightenment, where, according to Adorno and
that Apichatpong’s cinema is an act of resistance against
Horkheimer, ‘the whole enlightened earth is radiant with
this loss. It is an attempt to pull back into consciousness the
triumphant calamity’ (ibid.). In a sense, then, Arr/Dep is a
memory of things nearly lost. ‘We are in the age of extinc-
beautiful wreck, a global tragedy only imagined. As a work of
tion,’ Weerasethakul writes. ‘The cultures, the languages, the
precious beauty, it at once dazzles us, presents us with imagi-
forests, the animals, the treasures hidden in the vast tunnels
nation made flesh, and shows us the cynicism of global capi-
in the mountains. We are then forced to move to the Age of
tal, which generates a rhetoric of progress and civilisation at
Enlightenment when Nothing is meaningful. But the spirits
the cost of tremendous human exploitation. It is a perfect fit
remain, the spirits of the artefacts’ (Quandt 2009: 239-240).
of meaning and form.
Memory is the organising principle in Apichatpong’s cinema, where it is related to the strategy of the exquisite corpse. Le
422
Living Memory
corps exquis was an artistic method used by Marcel Duchamp
To see the plentiful world as beautiful is to see the objects in
to introduce chance and random coincidence into the artistic
it as carriers of meaning. But in our world of global capital-
process. In the exquisite body ‘drawings or texts are passed
ism, objects are constantly being slaughtered on the altar of
from person to person to elaborate upon, with the original
profit. This entails the risk that the meanings might perish
materials hidden so that each addition does not adhere in
along with the objects, leaving the scope of human experi-
any “logical” or predetermined way, resulting in a collective,
ence greatly impoverished. What remains is the rule of rea-
randomly assembled piece’ (Quandt 2009: 31). Apichatpong
son, the law of efficiency and profit that bleeds all meaning
used this practice in his first feature film, Mysterious Object
from life and leaves us with the Nothing of the capitalist
at Noon (2000), where a series of characters take turns to tell
void. In this void, which is really the egalitarian expanse of
their own version of the same story, each adding their own
the postmodern field (a collection of equal things stretching
twists or details. Some of these stories are dramatised in the
beyond the horizon), nothing is really of value since distinc-
film, so that Mysterious Object evolves into a rhizome of shift-
tions no longer apply. In his film Syndromes and a Century
ing narrative strands that blurs the line between fact and
(2006) Apichatpong Weerasethakul offered an unforgettably
fiction. But the exquisite corpse technique expands beyond
ominous visual metaphor for this process: in a sterile subter-
individual films. Many of Apichatpong’s films contain clues
ranean space the black hole of a large funnel slowly sucks
and references pointing back and forth between them. For in-
in the mist that hovers in the room, as if it were sucking the
stance, in the opening scene of Tropical Malady (2004) a group
place empty. This drain is what is happening to human expe-
of soldiers find a dead body, which is implied to be (and has
rience in capitalist culture: our inner lives are being bled or
been identified by the director as) the body of a young man
sucked dry by the logic of corporate vampirism. If this pipe is
who was presumably shot dead in Blissfully Yours (2002), Api-
423
424
chatpong’s previous film. One of the two main characters in
ity that it is true”’ (o.c. 104). By combining his own memories
Tropical Malady is the soldier Keng, who was also mentioned
and the memories of others, or his own vision of a film and
in Blissfully Yours. The other main character of Tropical Malady,
the input of his collaborators, Apichatpong blurs the line
Tong, seems to reappear in Uncle Boonmee Who Can Recall His
between reality and fiction, between real past and imagined
Past Lives (2010), but is there played by Sakda Kaewbuadee,
past. This undermines the reliability of the accounts present-
the actor who played Keng in Tropical Malady and who has
ed but also brings them closer to actually lived life, where we
since become the director’s muse.
are constantly having to deal with the tricks memory plays
However, the practice of the exquisite corpse is most struc-
on us. In the final reckoning, it is even possible for memory to
turally present in Apichatpong’s way of making films. He
forget, to eliminate people and events from the realm of real-
is a director who allows his collaborators much freedom to
ity by suppressing them or consciously omitting them from
introduce their own contributions into the film. Comment-
a narrative. This is a topic that has occupied Apichatpong in
ing on the process of editing his films, Apichatpong says that
the Primitive project, which finally resulted in his film Uncle
both he himself and his editor cut their version of the film.
Boonmee Who Can Recall His Past Lives.
‘Then we compare. Or we separate scenes. Or I break down
The Primitive project originates with a monk who gave Api-
the script and add my notes on editing for him’ (o.c. 186).
chatpong a copy of his book A Man Who Can Recall His Past
This open approach also extends to both the professional and
Lives, which tells of a man called Boonmee who had memo-
non-professional actors, who often decide what will happen
ries of previous existences. This fascinated Apichatpong
to the characters, a practice that is most explicit in Mysterious
because he felt that this Boonmee carried around his own
Object, which is constructed according to this very principle.
cinema: he did not need film to project his (reconstructed)
For Apichatpong himself this method is closely related to the
memories because everything was in his mind. In an inter-
importance of memory in his work. ‘I think this is one of the
view Apichatpong also explains that a monk (possibly the
reasons I make films,’ he explains. ‘My personal memories
same monk who gave him the book) told him ‘that medita-
are always interwoven with those from various other sources,
tion was like filmmaking. He said that when one meditates,
reading, listening and travelling (my own travels and those
one doesn’t need film. As if film was an excess. In a way he’s
of others). It was hard then to remember the real past clearly,
right. Our brain is the best camera and a projector. If only we
so I made films without knowing how true they really were.
can find a way to operate it properly’ (o.c. 184). The idea that
This was an important detail; it was like waking the dead
there is a link between imagination, meditation, and cinema
and giving them a new soul, making them walk once more. It
is a fundamental key to Apichatpong’s cinema. This link is
is the same when writing, sometimes it is just our imagina-
also mentioned by Elaine Scarry in Dreaming by the Book, when
tion, arising from our desire to remember, as Gabriel García
she claims that imagination operates like a projection in our
Márquez wrote: “The memory is clear but there is no possibil-
forehead. But to comprehend the full import of the mind as
425
426
an interior cinematic space for Apichatpong’s work we must
of the most memorable results of the project was the short
say something more about the Primitive project. Apichatpong
subject Ghosts of Nabua (2009), which shows a group of young
decided he would try and track down this Boonmee who
men playing soccer with a burning ball in the light of a single
could recall his past lives, or at least people who had known
neon lamp in the village of Nabua.
him. This had an added attraction for the director because
But the Primitive project also yielded the feature film Uncle
Boonmee had lived in the Northeast of Thailand, which was
Boonmee Who Can Recall His Past Lives. In this film Boonmee
also where Apichatpong grew up (in the city of Khon Kaen).
is dying of an unspecified affliction of the kidneys. He is
But this region has a very violent history, much of which has
cared for by his sister-in-law and by his nephew Tong. As
been repressed. In the 1960s the army used extreme violence
death approaches, spirits and animals from the forest gather
against communist peasants who revolted against the gov-
around the house. On the eve of his death, the spirit of his
ernment. Many men were slaughtered or disappeared in the
deceased wife and his long-lost son come to visit. During the
wilderness. This violent history, dragging on for years on end,
film Boonmee also recalls several of his past lives. In one of
is a deep trauma in the region, but it has been repressed.
his previous existences he was a princess with a scarred face
People do not spontaneously speak about it. The past is pres-
who visits a magical well where she makes love to a fish to
ent, but it is not mentioned. Apichatpong’s search for Boon-
regain her earlier beauty. But at the end Boonmee also has
mee eventually took him to Nabua, which had served as a
a dream about a future world in which the government has
centre to organise the government’s repressive actions and
the power to make any undesired subject disappear from
was in a state of siege from the 1960s through the 1980s. In-
the world; a totalitarian nightmare that not only refers back
terviewing locals about the past, stories began to emerge and
to the disappearance of countless men in the 1960s, but also
Apichatpong felt he should start a project working with the
points towards the political and military reality of Thailand in
teenagers of today who are the descendants of the forgotten
2010. Thus, Boonmee’s memories of his previous lives serve
men who disappeared or were slaughtered in the violence of
to link past to future in the present, which is haunted by the
earlier decades. So remembrance, memory, and reincarna-
ghosts of lives past. In fact, Boonmee himself is haunted by
tion (the return of dead spirits in a different guise) are at the
the past, for it is revealed, almost in passing, that he killed a
heart of the Primitive project, which seeks to make present
lot of communists back in the 1960s. Through Boonmee the
the past, reincarnated in a different form. The project yielded
film creates a continuum in time, where the ghosts of people
several short films, including A Letter to Uncle Boonmee (2009)
move through us (through Boonmee), undoing the forgetful-
which centres on the narrative of a man who claimed to be
ness forced upon them. But these political themes are not the
Boonmee’s son. Apichatpong also made a video short for a lo-
main focus of the film, which is really about the descent into
cal band and had the teenagers assemble a spaceship which
a man’s self-consciousness. The film takes us into an interior
served both as film set and as a hangout for the youths. One
world in which the lines between man and animal, between
427
428
dream and reality, and eventually also the lines between par-
to be looking at a representation of what happens when we
allel worlds are blurred. The film surrenders linear time to an
remember. Taking our cue from Scarry’s image of memory as
associative stream of consciousness that presents us with an
a mental cinema, we could argue that watching a film is like
organic vision of man and his world.
watching the operations of our own imagination being objec-
The scene of Boonmee’s death provides a mighty metaphor
tified. But since the projected film in the dark theatre fills the
for this vision. Led by the spirit of his deceased wife and ac-
visual field of perception, this objectification is immediately
companied by this sister-in-law and Tong, Boonmee ventures
blasted onto the screen of our interior cinema, which is over-
into the wilderness and is taken into a magical cave where
whelmed by it. This is a more roundabout way of saying what
the ceiling is lined with little specks of light that look like an
is more commonly expressed when people say that they
expanse of stars. It is a stunningly moving sequence. Inside
feel “inside” a film. Cinema is an intimate medium because
the cave the dying Boonmee is spied upon by spirits and
it emulates the deep structure of our most intimate faculty:
ghosts, dark shadows that have glaring red eyes. These are
imagination, which projects images onto our forehead. In this
the spirits of the past who have come to welcome Boonmee
sense Langer was correct to suggest that the primary illusion
into their midst. Boonmee remembers the cave: it is the
of cinema is the virtual dream or ‘the dream mode’ (FF 412).
womb of the earth, the place where he was born without
But she also points out that the camera is not the dreamer: it
consciousness of the differences between man and animal,
is ‘the mind’s eye and nothing more’ (FF 413). But saying that
male or female. Several lines of interpretation open up at
the camera is the mind’s eye is saying that cinema is an ex-
this point. It seems plausible to see the cave as a place where
ternalised representation of the felt experience of imagining.
some king of collective unconscious is located (it seems
Apichatpong has compared the experience of watching a
unlikely that such a cave of birth and remembrance would
film in a darkened theatre to a return to the womb: ‘we seem
exist for the sole benefit of Boonmee’s memories). But for
instinctively to want to enter dark halls; we are excited by
us it is interesting to link this sequence to Scarry’s image of
the prospect of hearing stories that emanate from that light
the internal cinema. In making a film that takes us into the
in the darkness. It is like returning to our mother’s womb’
enclosed space where a man’s memories (his internal cin-
(Quandt 2009: 114). In his films, this return to the womb,
ema) become real, Apichatpong seems to attempt to repeat
which is linked to remembrance, is symbolised by the de-
in a cinematic image the deep structure of imagination and
scent into forests and caves. Apichatpong has said that be-
remembrance. The descent of the characters into the cave is
ing in a forest ‘forces us to reflect on ourselves’ (o.c. 50) and
filmed in such a way that it takes the viewer, if he is willing
can be a transformative experience. Apichatpong’s film that
to submit to the experience, into the internal cave of his own
expresses the transformative power of the forest most force-
imagining and remembering. Or, put the other way around:
fully is Tropical Malady, a miraculous work of art and a truly
looking at Uncle Boonmee Who Can Recall His Past Lives we seem
original cinematic experience. Its story is deceptively simple.
429
430
It tells of two young men, the provincial lad Tong (Sakda
halves, but it seems clear that the second half of the film
Kaewbuadee) and the soldier Keng (Banlop Lomnoi) who fall
is an internal reprise of the first half: it shows the internal
in love. The film observes their budding relationship with
struggle of the boys, who must come to terms with the vio-
remarkably demure spontaneity. But then, halfway through
lent emotions that love unleashes in them. It shows their
the film, something odd happens. The two boys are driving
inner quest of finding each other. The fact that the same ac-
through the night on a motorbike and have stopped to relieve
tors return in the second part underlines such a reading. It is
them selves. When Tong is done pissing, Keng takes his hand
the wild beast of love and lust that is metaphorically being
and starts smelling, sniffing, and licking it; and Tong returns
tamed in the second half of the film. This is also indicated by
the gesture by licking Keng’s hand in what James Quandt has
a quote from the Japanese author Atsushi Nakajima who says
called an ‘ingestive sexuality’ (o.c. 72-74). But suddenly Tong
that we must learn to master our animal desires because ‘all
turns away and walks into the dark forest. He disappears. The
of us are by nature wild beasts’ (o.c. 65-66). Benedict Ander-
next morning, Keng sits in Tong’s room, mourning his friend’s
son has pointed out that the second half of the film can also
disappearance. At the same time, rumours start circulat-
be given an Orphic interpretation as the story of a man (the
ing around the village: there is a ‘strange beast’ roaming the
soldier) who must journey into the underworld (the wilder-
area, killing cattle. This strange beast translates as the literal
ness of the forest) to bring back his beloved (the boy who has
meaning of the film’s original title Sud pralad. Benedict Ander-
been transmogrified into a were-tiger that must be tamed)
son has noted that the title was also, for a brief period in the
(o.c. 76). On either reading the forest is a place of inner explo-
early 1980s, gay slang for the penis or for a male homosexual
ration and discovery, similar to the way Uncle Boonmee pres-
(o.c. 158). Keng decides to set out into the forest to find Tong,
ents the cave where Boonmee dies as a place where Boonmee
after which the screen goes black and an entirely new film
returns to his origins. As such it also recalls the principle of
seems to begin. The second half of the film follows an anony-
the Dionysian, a primeval realm where the categories of cul-
mous soldier, again played by Banlop Lomnoi, who is hunting
ture do not apply. For example, Boonmee clearly recalls that
a were-tiger, a shape-shifter who can turn from human into
he did not know the difference between male and female or
tiger and back again. His hunt takes him deep into the forest
between man and animal when was born in the cave. Hence,
until he finally meets his opponent eye to eye. In a stunning
the cave represents a realm before such differences applied,
sequence the tiger (who, when in human shape, is again
if not a Golden Age such as Greek mythology tells of, then at
played by Sakda Kaewbuadee) looks down at the soldier from
least a primary biological miasma of brimming life, polymor-
a tree and the soldier offers him his body and soul. It is clear
phous and polysexual. Apichatpong’s characters certainly
that hunter and hunted are really one soul, leaving open the
seem to exist in such a realm. This is made especially clear in
question who is hunting whom.
the many transmutations that they undergo and in the blur-
Much has been made of the symbolism of the film’s two
ring of the lines between species. Boonmee has had earlier
431
lives as a woman and as a buffalo (among others). When he
his son and himself and who is changed by the experience:
was a woman, namely the princess with the scarred face, she
once the son is found, the man leaves him with the tribe,
had intercourse with a fish. Inter-species sex was also sup-
which is his new home, and destroys the dam that would
posed to make an appearance in Tropical Malady, where, it
destroy that home. He sacrifices the supposed progress of
should not be forgotten, a man and a tiger share a soul and
Western society and his own life’s work as an engineer to the
hence are meant for each other. In an interview with James
higher good of preservationism. But there is also a stylistic
Quandt Apichatpong has explained that ‘we shot the soldier
influence, for Apichatpong has expressed his amazement at
licking, eating Tong in the end (for one of the three endings).
the many shades of green Boorman’s film brings out in the
And we shot the soldier making love with a tiger’ (o.c. 130).
forest (Quandt 2009: 44, 189). As Boorman himself explains in
Man, woman, and animal, male and female, human and
an interview included on the 2008 dvd release of the film, the
spirit: all live together in a continuum extending infinitely
film has been heralded for its very realistic depiction of what
through time and space.
the rain forest actually looks like. But ironically, this effect was achieved with artificial means because the dense forest
432
Inner Space
is so dark that it must be artificially lighted to translate its
Apichatpong has pointed out that an important influence on
visual impact to film. Boorman explains that the rain forest
his work was John Boorman’s film The Emerald Forest (1985).
usually looks murky on film because cinematographers make
This ambitious but flawed film, which is hampered by some
the mistake of treating it like an exterior when it is really an
stilted acting and an overreaching finale, is based on true
interior that must be lighted the way you would light a room.
events and tells of a young boy who is taken from his parents
This same artificial take on the forest returns in Tropical Mal-
while they are working on a dam on the Amazon river. The
ady, where the stunning light effects of the nocturnal forest
father spends ten years of his life looking for his son, who
were actually created with matte effects in a German studio.
has grown up as a member of the tribe called the “Invisible
The Emerald Forest is a continuation of core elements from
People”. Father and son meet again when the dam is near
Boorman’s earlier work. After all, Boorman directed what is
completion and the expansion of the white man’s world into
possibly the locus classicus of films about men who descend
the rain forest is about to destroy the territory of the Invis-
into the wilderness to find themselves: Deliverance (1972),
ible People. Much research into Amerindian tribes went into
based on a novel by James Dickey. Deliverance tells of four
the film and director Boorman even spent three weeks living
city-dwellers who want to spend a weekend in a canoe on
with such a tribe. It is easy to see the link to Apichatpong’s
a river in the Deep South of the United States. The river will
work. The Emerald Forest is about resistance to the extinction
soon dry up because it (like the river in The Emerald Forest) is
of a tribe, of a culture, and of the rain forest. It shows the
being dammed. The expedition is meant to renew contact
quest of a man who must descend into the forest to find both
with something essential these men feel they have lost.
433
434
Glibly, one could say they want to find their inner selves or
men do not live in nature, they embody it, brutally indifferent
reconnect with nature. Fashionable as such sentiments may
and ingeniously brutal.
be, they do point towards a fundamental problem in Western
The forest as a primeval scene of self-exploration was taken
culture, which is so focused on rationality, control, and order
up again in Excalibur (1981), Boorman’s mighty take on the
that we have become neurotic beings that are alienated from
legend of King Arthur and Merlin. This, too, is a film about ex-
the natural rhythms of life. Throughout his career, Boorman
tinction, for as Merlin points out in the film and Boorman has
has dealt with this problem, which he perceives as a very
explained in interviews, ‘the Arthurian legend is about the
real danger: ‘I really feel the most dangerous thing – and it’s
passing of the old gods and the coming of the Age of Man, of
a cliché – is to be totally cut off from the source of things:
rationality, of laws – of man controlling his affairs. The price
to have no sense of where our food comes from, how the
he pays for this is the loss of harmony with nature, which
machines we operate work... It’s a process of profound alien-
includes magic. [...] The only way to regain it is by some form
ation and leads to neurosis: that’s what the modern city is all
of transcendence, which the quest for the Grail represents
about’ (Yakir 1981: 50). The four men’s expedition turns into
– to transcend the material world and find a spiritual solu-
a nightmare when they happen upon a group of mountain-
tion’ (Yakir 1981: 50). The Age of Reason means that man is
dwellers: a bunch of inbred farmers who seem to have lost
no longer part of nature, as he was in the Middle Ages, but
contact with civilisation. These mountain-men start hunting
its opponent. ‘The most significant thing about the Middle
down the intruders, who are now facing two enemies: nature
Ages,’ Boorman explains, ‘is that it was an untamed world
and its inhabitants. If looked at metaphorically, one could say
and man had a minor role in relation to the animal kingdom.
that the mountain-men are the henchmen that nature sends
It was the mystery of the forest’ (ibid.). Merlin (Nicol William-
out to rape these arrogant intruders as punishment for the
son) is still from this old world and it is his task to introduce
rape they have perpetrated on her by building a dam. Nature
the young Arthur into the world of magic. Merlin compares
takes revenge, and the rape is literal, for one of the four men
the forest to a Dragon, ‘a creature that came out of the slime
is humiliatingly raped by the savages in an unsettling scene.
and had to do with the memory of emerging from the reptile’
If civilised man violently penetrates nature (damming rivers,
(ibid.). As part of his spiritual journey to become king of the
cutting rain forests, soiling oceans) then nature will penetrate
Britons, young Arthur (Nigel Terry) must sojourn in the forest
him right back. And just like the benign Invisible People in
and hold his own among the many creatures that come out
The Emerald Forest, who seem to blend in with the green of the
in the night and fill it with strange sounds. Again, the forest
forest, the mountain-men of Deliverance seem to sprout from
in Excalibur is similar to that in The Emerald Forest and Tropical
the primal soil of the Deep South. ‘I shot the mountain men,’
Malady: filled with eerie light that shows in great detail the
Boorman explains, ‘as though they were emerging from trees
many strange bugs and beasts that crawl around. Its hues
like malevolent spirits of the forest’ (Kemp 2001: 23). These
are preternaturally green or violently red and orange, lighted
435
436
like a visionary landscape of Pre-Raphaelite invention. The
fled with youthful exuberance and great dedication, tramping
mist that hangs between the trees is the Dragon’s breath. The
around the country without a safety net. Then McCandless
knowledge of the forest’s innards has been forgotten by man
found that, come the spring, a river he had crossed when it
and now only lives in the minds of witches and sorceresses
was frozen had turned into a giant wall of water, barring his
like Morgana (a formidable Helen Mirren), who seduces Mer-
way back to the human world. Trapped in the abandoned bus
lin and traps him in a stone.
he has found, he dies after eating poisonous berries. Ironi-
In Excalibur nature is kosmos, all-encompassing. In Deliver-
cally, McCandless’ camp was a mere few miles away from a
ance and The Emerald Forest it has been instrumentalised,
luxurious holiday resort.
functionalised, commodified. It is an adventure to indulge in
The forest has always been a place for introspection and
during the weekend, renting a canoe and getting in sync with
transformation, as Apichatpong also pointed out. And in
your inner self. It is a picturesque event, something that is
many primitive tribes it is customary to send young men out
supposed to look primeval but not be it: tracks, guided tours,
into the forest as part of their ritual transition to manhood.
refreshments, and the necessary emergency exits are pro-
Several contemporary films have taken up this theme. Ariel
vided for the happy campers seeking to commune with Gaia.
Rotter’s film El otro (2007) tells the story of Juan (Julio Chavez),
But nature, as Björk sings, is ancient and she always gets the
a middle-aged man whose younger girlfriend informs him
upper hand. Man may pass through and do some damage,
that she is pregnant. A business trip to another town turns
but the world-encompassing organism that is our planet will
into a journey of self-exploration as Juan ponders what di-
always prevail and will finally undo all that man has done. As
rection his life should now take. This journey is framed like
Boorman points out in his comments on The Emerald Forest,
a dream or a metaphorical “trip”: during the bus ride Juan is
the rain forest itself is not much bothered by its deforesta-
lulled to sleep. When he wakes upon arrival, he discovers that
tion. It is we, the humans, who will suffer the ecological con-
the man sitting next to him, a doctor, has died. Wanting to
sequences. The forest itself might need thousands of years
extend his stay in the foreign city for a day, Juan takes rooms
to grow back, but that is really a very brief period of time in
in two hotels. In the first one he checks in under his own
the life of the planet. Similarly, in Deliverance nature reminds
name, in the other under the name of the deceased doctor.
arrogant Western man of her might. Even on a charted river
Finally, a friend wants to take Juan for a night out in a club,
only a few miles away from the civilised world these four
but feeling in no mood to party, Juan flees the scene and finds
adult men succeed in getting lost. In this respect their plight
himself running along a highway in the middle of the night,
is almost pathetic and reminds one of the tragic case of
with the lights of passing trucks looming ominously in the
Christopher McCandless, which was filmed by Sean Penn in
dark. The next morning he wakes up in the forest, picks fresh
Into The Wild (2007). McCandless also wanted to flee the fake
fruit for breakfast and spies on a group of young girls swim-
civilisation of large cities, but unlike the men in Deliverance he
ming in a river. Chastened, Juan takes the bus back home, is
437
438
lulled to sleep again and takes up the thread of ordinary life.
apply themselves to their craft because in prison nobody is
Whether the events in the other city were real or not remains
going anywhere. There is no rush, just a steady and unhur-
unclear. But the otherworldly nature of events is stressed
ried communion with each other and with the objects at
by the fact that the other city, the city of Juan’s inner trans-
hand. Vargas’s last night in jail is a stunning evocation of his
formation, seems bare and desolate, without inhabitants or
physical being. Lying in bed, he tries to read the paper, but
traffic, almost like a ghost town. The other of the title is really
cannot concentrate. Finally, he simply lies down, unbuttons
three others in the film: it is the other man, the doctor whose
his shirt and starts caressing his abdomen. It is as if we can
identity Juan steals; it is Juan himself, who is going through a
actually feel the masturbation Vargas is thinking about but
process of inner change; and it is the unborn child that con-
not performing. This scene is of great importance to the film,
fronted Juan with himself in the first place.
for the rest of Los Muertos basically evolves around Vargas’s
Lisandro Alonso’s film Los Muertos (2004) also highlights the
physical relationship to and presence in the forest. So it must
relation of man to primeval nature. The film’s narrative is
be made tangibly clear to us that he has a body.
sparse and may lend itself to several, indeed, to a host of in-
The use of extended takes, which make real time palpable,
terpretations. Los Muertos follows a middle-aged man, Vargas
is a very efficient way to create such a sense of physicality.
(Argentino Vargas), who is released from prison where he has
But since Alonso’s films always focus on male protagonists,
served a long sentence for the murder of his brothers. The
there is a lingering sense of homo-eroticism here that is not
film actually opens with an extended, three-minute point of
easily dismissed. Possibly it is a consequence of the fact that
view shot of the camera wandering through the green jungle
Alonso’s characters are loners, solitary figures who necessar-
and happening upon (presumably) the murdered bodies of
ily commune primarily with themselves. In La Libertad (2001),
the boys. This is all we learn about (what we assume to be)
his first feature, Alonso focused on a day in the life of a young
Vargas’s crime (although an earlier treatment of the film
Argentinean woodcutter, showing him both as he washes
provided the added information that Vargas killed his broth-
his chiselled body and as he takes a shit. In Los Muertos, Var-
ers because they were starving, which would turn him from
gas’s body is alone in its dialogue with the forest. He glides
a possible homicidal maniac into a complex moral being;
up a stream in a small boat in a hypnotising journey through
Quandt 2008: 334). At first, it is not clear that Vargas is actu-
the green belly of nature. The journey has a purpose: to find
ally in prison, for the prison seems to function like a village,
Vargas’s daughter and grandchildren. Alonso constantly em-
a miniature community where only the occasional presence
phasises the presence of the forest. Vargas, who seems to
of guards and bars serves as a reminder of what kind of place
feel entirely at home in the forest, is an expert at procuring
this is. In these early scenes we get a very close feel of the
food from it. When he sees a goat on the edge of the river, he
physical aspect of Vargas’s existence. Most inmates learn a
stops the boat, catches it and slaughters and guts it with his
craft and we see them at work. They can take their time to
machete. In a stunning sequence, Vargas ravages a beehive
439
to extract big slabs of honeycomb, which he eats with a rel-
take note of the very different use to which these directors
ish that makes the mouth water. When Vargas finally reaches
are putting a style of filming that is superficially similar. There
his destination, it appears that his daughter lives in a shabby
is a harshness in Alonso’s universe, expressed, among other
tent-like construction on an island in the stream. She is out
things, in the extended sequences of animal slaughter and in
and all Vargas finds is his twelve year old grandson who is
the rugged inexpressiveness of his male protagonists, that is
looking after his little sister. The boy enters the tent while
entirely missing from Apichatpong’s work. To be sure, there
Vargas remains seated outside. Finally, he gets up, puts his
is darkness in Apichatpong, too, but it is his love of the world,
machete on the table and follows the boy inside. The camera
or his love of worlds, that fuels his cinema. Both filmmakers
slowly pans to an abandoned toy on the ground. In the back-
unsettle and leave their images unresolved, and both have
ground we hear the ominous sound of joints that are being
created works of genius. But in Alonso, nature is ‘immense,
torn. Is a chicken being slaughtered or the little boy? Has the
entropic, indifferent’ (Quandt 2008: 332) whereas in Apichat-
film come full circle to the scene of slaughter with which it
pong it is equally immense, certainly entropic, but never indif-
opened? The shot of the abandoned toy is held for an uncom-
ferent. It is (inside) us.
fortably long time. Then, without any explanation or warning, 440
the film abruptly stops.
Magmatic Poetics
What ties all these films together is much more than the
Filming from the inside is not a new idea. It is what Pier Paolo
use of a forest as the site for reflection and transformation.
Pasolini, in a famous essay published in the October 1965 is-
They share a use of landscape as a means for illuminating
sue of Cahiers du Cinéma, has called “the cinema of poetry”. In
psychology; something that Ruskin would surely condemn as
poetic cinema the filmmaker uses the cinematic equivalent of
a pathetic fallacy. There is an immense power in this kind of
free indirect speech in literature (‘soggetiva libera indirecta’; Ber-
minimalist cinema, whether it is done by Alonso or by Api-
tolucci and Comolli 1965: 24; Pasolini 1965: 59). In the poetic
chatpong. But there is also a difference. As James Quandt has
cinema, Pasolini explains, ‘the director entirely penetrates the
written, ‘Alonso wants to besot with the ordinary’ (o.c. 333): he
soul of his character, whose psychology and language he thus
hypnotises his audience with intense observations of the ev-
adopts’ (Pasolini 1965: 59). There is no mediation between the
eryday that are made eerie by the obsessive way in which they
character’s interior and what is communicated, no authorial
are lingered on. Quandt also wrote about Apichatpong that
intervention. This means that the cinema of poetry is a stylis-
he has ‘a predilection for employing the camera to “just look
tic device: it is a kind of visual interior monologue. In practice
at beauty”’ (Quandt 2009: 28) and for revelling in what Elaine
it means that narrative makes way for mood. The filmmaker
Scarry (in another context) has called ‘the intense somatic
writes poetry in images instead of telling a story. A key way of
pleasure, the sentient immediacy of the experience of beauty’
doing this is to make the style of the film palpable. The viewer
(BBJ 122). Despite the similarities in description, we should
is constantly reminded that he is watching a film because
441
442
‘one feels the camera very strongly, there are a lot of zooms,
the film has the characteristic features of a Catholic work. But
intentional faux raccords’ (Bertolucci and Comolli 1965: 25) that
internally nothing I’ve ever done has been more fitted to me
express the character’s subjective perception of events. Paso-
myself than The Gospel [because of] my tendency always to
lini called this cinema of poetry a ‘stilistic magma’ (ibid.) that
see something sacred and mythic and epic in everything, even
he achieved by filming a lot of documentary footage and by
the most humdrum, simple and banal objects and events. So
working with non-professional actors. From this rough mate-
in this sense The Gospel was just right for me, even though I
rial he constructed the final film. Pasolini explained that ‘the
don’t believe in the divinity of Christ, because my vision of the
films of the cinema of poetry are not made according to the
world is religious’ (Stack 1969: 77). This tendency to see some-
ordinary rules and conventions of the script, they do not obey
thing sacred in everything is of course linked to an animistic
the usual narrative rhythms. On the contrary, disproportion is
concept of the world, which should not surprise us since Pa-
the rule: details are enormously exaggerated, points that are
solini was a practising Marxist rather than a practising Catho-
traditionally deemed important are dealt with rapidly. Also,
lic. In fact, Pasolini told Oswald Stack that ‘I am not interested
there is no narrative peak, no catharsis, no narrative closure.
in deconsecrating: this is a fashion I hate, it is petit bourgeois.
Through the technique of free indirect speech the film is en-
I want to re-consecrate things as much as possible, I want to
tirely reconstructed from within’ (o.c. 76). It is remarkable that
re-mythicise them’ (o.c. 83). But to re-mythicise things implies
Pasolini’s description of free indirect speech comes extremely
exactly the kind of projection of quasi-aliveness and the pro-
close to Warhol’s filmic practice. In fact, the principles of the
jection of value that we have been discussing. ‘Shooting films
cinema of poetry were central to many of the filmmakers in-
is a little bit like a drug for me,’ Pasolini once claimed. ‘it’s like
volved in the New American Cinema.
being drunk on reality. [...] When I make a film I am in reality
Pasolini used the cinema of poetry in Edipo Re (1967), in Medea
and I make reality’ (Snyder 1980: 29). To both be in reality and
(1970), and in the Trilogy of Life. But his greatest achieve-
make it: aliveness to the quasi-aliveness of the world never
ment in this style of filming is Il Vangelo secondo Matteo (1964),
sounded so solipsistic and yet so expansive.
which in a sense generated the style. ‘The Gospel confronted
There is much of this cinema of poetry in Apichatpong’s work.
me with the following problem,’ Pasolini told Bernardo Berto-
In Blissfully Yours he ‘misconstrues topography’ by combining
lucci and Jean-Louis Comolli, ‘I could not tell it like a classical
mismatched shots that undermine continuity. For example,
narrative because I am not religious, I am an atheist. [...] So
an image of a woman on a moving boat is followed by an im-
I had to tell a story in which I did not believe. So I could not
age of a boy on an elephant filmed from a moving vehicle, a
be the one telling it. That is how, without really wanting it, I
combination that is ‘geographically impossible’ (Quandt 2009:
wound up changing my entire cinematographical style’ (o.c.
37). More importantly, however, Apichatpong also uses the
25). Despite his own atheism Pasolini claimed that the film
free indirect speech of Pasolini’s cinema of poetry in his strat-
was probably his most personal work. ‘It’s only externally that
egy of filming from the inside out. This becomes especially
443
444
clear in the treatment of time. Pasolini claimed that the idea
Perchance to Dream
of temporary progress was an illusion. In Volker Koch’s film
One of the greatest filmmakers of memory is Terence Da-
S.P.Q.R. (1972) Pasolini explained that ‘time is not a sequence,
vies. His entire body of work, which is small but immensely
as is shown not only by the philosophy of mysticism, but also
powerful, is a glorious metaphor for the moving fabric of
by science. Therefore there is neither progress nor regress.
remembrance. His films most clearly illustrate the process
Time does not exist; and since time does not exist, there is
of the inner cinema described by Scarry in Dreaming by the
no history either; there is an eternal absolute present’ (Koch
Book and taken up by Apichatpong as a cinematic metaphor
1982: 209). I believe we should read this observation in the
for memory. In his film Of Time and the City (2008), which is a
light of Kondylis’ concept of the postmodern, for which space
portrait of Liverpool, the city where he was born and grew up
is the master metaphor. As we saw earlier, the postmodern
in, Davies speaks of a feeling he calls “unrequited regret”. The
is an expansive field in which everything is present, like a
notion is paradoxical, but it is a very accurate definition of
counter from which we can pick and choose our identities,
what is more generally called melancholy. In melancholy we
personalities, and worlds. In the cinema, this postmodern
feel sadness about a past that cannot be undone or relived
condition is expressed in the techniques of flash-forward and
and that has withdrawn into time, existing beyond our reach,
flashback, which allow the filmmaker to juxtapose several
as a memory. Memories are experiences and events that we
temporal strands. Similarly, several narrative strands, or sev-
know to be real but the reality of which can no longer be ex-
eral narrative strands situated in different timeframes, can be
perienced. It is one of the strangest aspects of time that it is
combined and interlaced within the continual visual stream
entirely punctual: only the now is ever real for our conscious-
of a single film. Pasolini used this technique in his Trilogy of
ness. The future is sure to be and the past has unquestion-
Life, which consists of Il Decamerone (1971), I Racconti di Canter-
ably been, but we cannot know or even comprehend where the
bury (1972) and Il Fiore delle mille e una notte (1975), his film ver-
past is now. Where are past events? Where are past places? It
sion of The Arabian Nights. Especially in the latter film Pasolini
seems absurd to suppose that the past has been stored away
jumps from story to story and from story-within-a-story back
somewhere. In fact, the places where the past took place are
to story or to another story-within-a-story without bother-
still here, but in the mode of the present. The places have
ing to keep us informed of the jumps he is making. Similarly,
not gone, it is simply the past that eludes us. So where do
Apichatpong drifts in and out of Boonmee’s past lives in Uncle
past events go? Does anything ever have any kind of reality
Boonmee Who Can Recall His Past Lives and it is up to the viewer
beyond the brief split second in which it occurs and is really,
to determine when and where the stories shift; a task we ac-
tangibly here? These are questions that have long gone unan-
complish with considerable ease because postmodern cinema
swered and that the present book, alas, is not going to answer
has trained us to do this.
either. But what we can do, and what Terence Davies’ work greatly helps us to do, is to try and explain the deep structure
445
446
of memory as it is also discussed by Elaine Scarry. This struc-
narrative strategies used. If the first two instalments of the
ture of memory seems to be more than superficially linked to
trilogy showed events as they occurred, the feature film pres-
the condition of unrequited regret, so we would do well to see
ents the autobiographical elements as memories. That we
how Davies translates this regret to film.
are watching memories is made clear with several stylistic
Davies was raised a Catholic and suffered the guilt associated
devices. First, the film is structured like a dream: characters
with it more strongly than most, especially because he had
come and go and events are linked together in an associa-
to come to terms with his homosexuality. That he became a
tive way that moves back and forth in time. Weaving through
filmmaker is almost a coincidence. The first twelve years of
the years and picking up scenes to highlight before they melt
his adult life were spent working as a bookkeeper. Internally,
away again to give way to other memories, the film generates
Davies was torn apart by frustration. He tried to deal with his
a tapestry of life remembered. Music is the glue that holds
misery by writing it down in a screenplay. The script turned
everything together. In most of the scenes the characters
out to be impossible to sell, until the British Film Institute
are singing. This is an important aspect of the film because
took it up and gave Davies a minuscule budget to film it, de-
it canalises private emotions through popular tunes of the
spite the fact that he had no experience in directing and had
1940s and 1950s, opening them up to the experiences of the
not even seen a camera up close. The resulting autobiograph-
viewer. We all have personal memories associated with spe-
ical short Children (1976), filmed in forbiddingly stark black
cific songs. Davies is counting upon our willingness to inject
and white, tells the story of how Robert Tucker grows up in
our own memories into the memories portrayed in the film.
a poor workers’ area of Liverpool. He has to suffer a boorish
The music kindles our own feelings of melancholy because
father at home and sadistic bullies at school and is repeat-
it takes us back to times long gone, especially if we happen
edly beaten up. After the success of this first short, Davies
to be familiar with the music and the era to which it belongs.
took lessons at a film school and next produced Madonna and
Thus, the music helps us to bring the film’s memories closer
Child (1980), a second short subject in which Robert Tucker
to our own, enhancing our emotional investment in the
has entered adult life, living with his aged mother who pre-
events of the film.
tends not to know about his nightly forays into the homo-
Another important shift in comparison with the trilogy is the
sexual underground. The final instalment of what would be
fact that Distant Voices, Still Lives discards the often despon-
assembled into The Terence Davies Trilogy was Death and Trans-
dent realism of the earlier films. In the last two segments of
figuration (1983), where Tucker is seen on his deathbed, lonely
the trilogy there was already a shift towards symbolism and
and deserted, visited by memories of his past. The sense of
impressionism, especially in Robert Tucker’s visions on his
total desolation and loneliness that imbues these three films
deathbed, but also in the way his sexual encounters were
returns in Davies’ first feature, the heart-rendingly beautiful
depicted in Madonna and Child. But Distant Voices, Still Lives is
Distant Voices, Still Lives (1988). But a shift takes place in the
entirely and unabashedly anti-naturalistic. In fact, it takes
447
448
its title quite literally because in most scenes the characters
present in any of the earlier films: the cinema as an escape
are positioned frontally in relation to the camera and they
from the depressing humdrum of everyday life. We should
are lighted as if they belonged in a painting by Vermeer. In
remember that in 1956 cinemas were still impressive palaces,
this way the film is literally structured as a series of still lives
sumptuous and luxurious theatres; not the multiplex screen-
that are filled with the absent voices of memories and songs,
ing boxes of recent times. In The Long Day Closes films play the
voices that seem to echo from afar to linger ever so briefly
part that was played by music in Distant Voices, Still Lives: they
and then make way for another scene, another story. A third
are carriers of collective memory. Just like songs, films can
structural shift in relation to the earlier shorts is that Distant
trigger memories of the olden days, they can project us back
Voices, Still Lives is no longer concerned simply with the mem-
through time to events and feelings long gone. In this sense
ories of one person. The memories that are interwoven in the
they really do function as memory banks. As we saw earlier,
film belong to several members of the same family. The web
Elaine Scarry writes that dreams and daydreams are experi-
that is woven by the film is a fabric of collective memory. This
enced as projections on the inside of our forehead. Taking up
forces the viewer to take up the role of narrator, or rather the
this analogy, it could be argued that the magic of the cinema
role of authorial rememberer. Because there is not one per-
lies in the fact that the beam emanating from the projector
son to whom the memories can be linked, there is an empty
and captured on the screen appears to us as an externalisa-
place at the heart of the film which the viewer must fill. In
tion of the interior processes of dreaming, daydreaming, and
doing that, he or she engages in the labour of remembrance
remembering. Or, as Deborah Harry sings in a Blondie song:
that the film accomplishes. Distant Voices, Still Lives is a mo-
the beam becomes my dream, with electric faces rising from
saic of memories that is structured in a floating mood.
the glow. This way, the cinema as a metaphor for memory
This changes again in Davies’ next film, The Long Day Closes
brings together all the important elements in Davies’ work:
(1992), which is once again structured around one central
just like a dream a film is a sequence of images that move
character, the eleven year old Bud who is facing the chal-
outside the normal laws of time and space; they are linked
lenge and horrors of secondary school, where he is bound
emotionally and are rife with cores of expressive imagery.
to become the butt of bullies. The film, which is set in 1956,
Music, film, dream, and memory exist in a phenomenological
harks back to the memories of Children, but in a milder tone.
continuum. All Davies’ films contribute to this metaphorical
The story has a warm glow and the family is tangibly pres-
vision and use of the cinema, but it is in Distant Voices, Still
ent, whereas the earlier film simply showed Robert Tucker in
Lives that he hones it to perfection, creating an associative
abject isolation. The only person who is conspicuously absent
fabric of luminous dream reality.
is the abusive father; and it seems that nobody really misses his presence. Taking yet another step beyond all the previous films, The Long Day Closes introduces an element that was not
449
450
Soft Sightings
that in fog the physical universe approaches the condition
The phenomenology of dream and remembrance can help
of the imagination’ (DB 22-23). This is a possible reason why
us understand one of the most reviled techniques in the
filmmakers and photographers resort to soft focus in pre-
cinema: the use of soft focus to suggest dreams, flashbacks,
senting us with erotic imagery. In fact, the effect they achieve
or, most commonly, to suggest an erotic atmosphere. Nubile
is double. On the one hand, there is the by now familiar effect
young girls in soft focus have been a stock in trade of erotic
of presenting us with an outward objectification of the in-
imagery for a very long time (interestingly, homosexual erotic
ward process of daydreaming. But by wrapping their imagery
imagery seems to rely much less on soft focus, but it does
in soft focus they also take the edge of the obscene away, pre-
have other conventions for cloying erotic photography). The
venting the shock of the pornographic by softening it into the
logic behind soft focus might very well have something to do
instant recognition of the image as resembling images in our
with the phenomenology of the daydream as it was described
imagination. What is shown with greater reality than it has
by Elaine Scarry. What links dreams, daydreams, and imagi-
in the inner eye of imagination is wrapped in the soft focus of
nation to soft focus photography is the element of vagueness,
the imagination to prevent it from being all-too-real.
the inability to get an image clearly into focus. This is no co-
By wrapping erotic imagery in soft focus, the edge is taken
incidence. Scarry has noted that mental images are anything
off the images. This is often done to make the images more
but solid. She points out that it is very difficult even to imag-
palatable for a mainstream audience that would shrink from
ine the face of a beloved person in clear detail. Whenever
outright pornography. This probably explains why the moral
we want to bring specific features of a face into focus they
outcry over erotic films often seems disproportionate to the
seem to elude us. Scarry comes to this point through some
rather unexciting films themselves. The mainstream erotic
experiments that she invites the reader to share with her,
cinema is paradoxically among the most conservative genres
notably trying to imagine one’s mother’s face in the clearest
in film because it wants to entertain its mainstream audience
possible detail. According to Scarry, this is more difficult than
without alienating it. So the story is usually highly moralistic
one would imagine. Whenever we seem to grasp the image, it
(with love prevailing and licentiousness often leading to un-
eludes us again. This kind of fuzziness, clouding our mental
happiness) and the presentation is neat and tidy. But there
view or wrapping our imaginings and daydreams in cotton
are also maverick directors who have infused their erotic
wool clouds of mist, also appears in reality. ‘Some physical
films with a sexual energy that explodes these restrictive
objects have features that more closely approximate the phe-
genre conventions. One of the most interesting is the prolific
nomenology of imaginary objects than do others. We often
Spanish director Jesús ‘Jess’ Franco. Tim Lucas, a critic of
speak of actual mist, actual gauze, filmy curtains, fog, and
fringe cinema, has once stated that it is impossible to watch
blurry rain as dreamlike.’ Especially a mist has the property
one Franco film without watching them all (Du Mesnildot
of making the world appear as in a dream. So ‘we might say
2004: 102). He meant that Franco’s oeuvre is of a piece and
451
452
that there are unifying themes, motifs, and stylistic char-
views that, incidentally, lend themselves to interesting views
acteristics that clearly mark a Franco film as a Franco film.
of the lower parts of women’s legs. Franco claims that Chet
Admirers of the filmmaker can usually tell after one scene of
Baker once told him that ‘when you are playing, it’s wonder-
a film whether it is or is not a Franco: the director has an un-
ful to close your eyes, begin to improvise and, to pass the
mistakable signature style that you either love or (as is appar-
time, see your life fragment by fragment, to feel transported
ently most commonly the case) hate. Every Franco film con-
to an unreal world... and when you finish the solo, and two
tains visual and narrative echoes from previous films. Names
minutes have passed, you look at the faces of the specta-
of characters and the actors who perform their parts appear
tors, which are the same as before you closed your eyes – but
and reappear from film to film, but with slight alterations, as
you’ve been away and you’ve come back’ (Tohill and Tombs
if every film were a variation on a theme. Franco obsessively
1995: 100; see also Aguilar 1999: 158). Whether Baker actually
returns to these themes again and again, turning his body of
told Franco this is of no real importance; what matters is that
work into a rhizome of references. This works both for and
this description fits Franco’s style very well. His films are in-
against him. His detractors will see this obsession as a clear
deed structured like visits to a parallel universe that is organ-
indication of his lack of talent or vision, whereas his admirers
ised around the filmmaker’s own obsessions. In this sense,
will simply point out that all great artists have always obses-
Franco’s work is much closer to the experimental cinema of
sively returned to a given set of themes and motifs. When
the 1960s than it is to commercial sex-films or pornography.
they do so in mainstream cinema, they are usually referred to
Many of his best films have a framing device that sets the
as auteurs.
erotic vision apart form the everyday world. Very often the
Stéphane du Mesnildot has called Franco’s cinema a ‘cinema
scenes that establish this frame are either set in a bar or
of trance’ (o.c. 93). It is not through their plots that Franco’s
introduce us to dreams or hallucinations. Another possible
films intrigue, but through the way they are filmed. There is
framing device is setting the film in a remote or isolated loca-
something in the images themselves that mesmerises the
tion, be it an exotic island, an exclusive club, or a mansion
spectator. In this sense, Franco’s work is entirely visual and
high on a hill. Such devices are very popular in mainstream
exceedingly cinematic. His best films (and it should be admit-
erotic films as well, and for exactly the same reason as the
ted that he has also made his share of very bad films) are not
use of soft focus is popular: it clearly identifies the film as
structured around narrative, but along a musical line. Franco
a daydream and a fantasy, a form of escapism into sensual
has often been forced to improvise due to budget restraints.
reverie. What sets Franco apart is the intensity with which he
And when he improvises, he likes to do so to jazz rhythms.
obsessively fills the realm of fantasy that is cleared by closing
Franco’s love of jazz music is in evidence even in his earliest
the film off from the real world.
films, where his eccentric camera positions echo the imag-
In Vampyros Lesbos (1970), possibly Franco’s most famous film,
ery of jazz album covers of the 1950s, often taking low angle
the blonde lawyer Linda (Ewa Strömberg) is hired by Nadine
453
454
von Karlstein (Soledad Miranda) to take care of the inheri-
of sadistic libertines who torture her (at one point assaulting
tance of the Dracula family. To do this Linda must travel to
her with no less an aphrodisiac than the mace) while she is
Nadine’s private island, where she soon comes under the
sedated, so that they can tell her afterwards that the whole
enthralling influence of the vampiric brunette. The first
hellish experience was only a bad dream. So the erotic imag-
scene of the film is very famous and is a key to the structure
ery of Eugénie is framed twice, as a dream-within-the-dream.
of what follows. Linda is sitting in a bar where a brunette is
A paradigmatic image of Franco cinema is the title sequence
performing an erotic cabaret with a mannequin. We will later
of La comtesse noire (1973), which is an erotic film of unusual
learn that the dancer is in fact Nadine, who apparently has
intensity. It tells of Irina von Karlstein, the last descendant of
the gift of travelling through time and space. Right from the
a family of vampires, who wants to free both herself and the
start, Nadine infiltrates Linda’s mind, speaking to her sub-
world from the curse of her family. As the title credits roll we
consciously as she performs. Other successful Franco films
see Irina appear from a fog as she walks towards the camera.
begin with similar scenes that blur the lines between fact
She is naked, except for a black cape, a black belt, and black
and fiction. Both Necronomicon (1967) and the very fascinating
boots. She approaches the camera until her black pubic hair
Exorcisme (1974; probably best known under its alternative
almost fills the screen (abundant pubic hair is a particular
titles Le Sadique de Notre Dame and Demoniac, but best enjoyed
obsession of Franco’s). Since she seems to materialise out
in its original French language version since bad dubbing
of the fog, Irina becomes an immaterial creature, inhabiting
spoils the atmosphere of the film) open with sadistic torture
a shadow world between the material world and the realm
scenes that are revealed to be cabaret acts performed for a
of the spirit. The film clearly illustrates her ability to move
select crowd of jet-set libertines. Both performances end in
between worlds. Every time she kills, we see Irina leading
a murder that is revealed to be staged. Such scenes make
her victims through a misty forest to the underworld. But
clear the theatrical and phantasmatic nature of the film: be-
the clearest sign of her otherworldly nature is the fact that
yond this point the viewer is invited and in fact required to
she remains mute throughout the film. Irina communicates
leave behind all his presuppositions about ordinary reality.
with her victims telepathically and it is her disembodied
We are cautioned to consider that we are entering a parallel
voice that also provides the narrative in an interior mono-
universe. Justine (1968) is framed by scenes of the Marquis de
logue on the soundtrack (considering the economic context
Sade (Klaus Kinski) writing in his cell, inspired by the pres-
of sex-films, the fact that Lina Romay, who plays the part of
ence of naked tortured women. The entire film is a visualisa-
Irina, never actually speaks on-screen is a great advantage
tion of his fantasies about the virtuous Justine and her licen-
when it comes to dubbing the film in other languages, giv-
tious sister Juliette. And the stunning Eugénie (1969) is in fact
ing the film a potentially global market). This means that all
simply an onanistic daydream of the heroine in question. In
the characters who fall for Irina’s charms are subconsciously
this daydream she imagines falling into the hands of a bunch
seduced by her. They can feel her presence even when she is
455
456
not there. One character who is especially aware of her pres-
of a jewel’ (o.c. 447). Among the examples she lists are Leon-
ence in Madeira is the mortician Dr. Orloff, played by critic
ardo da Vinci’s The Virgin with St. Anne, where both women
Jean-Pierre Bouyxou. When a police officer who is trying to
look like twin sisters (o.c. 156); Hymen’s doubling of Rosalind
track Irina down (and who is played by Franco himself) visits
in her reading of As You Like It (o.c. 211); and Dante Gabriel
the doctor to gather information, he is urged by the mortician
Rossetti’s The Bower Meadow and Astarte Syriaca (o.c. 447); to
to leave reason behind and submit to Irina’s call. This way, he
which I would add the almost clone-like figures that fill many
will discover real life. But to surrender to Irina means to sur-
paintings of Burne-Jones or Puvis de Chavannes. To be sure,
render to the fantasy, to the sexual force-field that lies at the
Franco does not fill a single image with multiple Romays;
heart of this film. We are not simply invited to have sex with
but if we look at his body of work as one extended work,
Irina but to engage a style of living and of experiencing that
then the recurrence of bodies, scenes, motifs, and characters
is drenched in sensuality. It is an invitation to leave the ratio-
throughout his many films blurs the lines that separate each
nal universe behind and enter the world of phantasm.
individual film from every other to the point that titles might
It is this interior world of lust that Franco wants to capture in
even become interchangeable. If allegorical repletion does
images. At its heart lie a series of images, scenes, and motifs
not figure within any one scene, it is surely the driving force
to which Franco obsessively returns again and again. And at
behind the oeuvre, which, in its most intensely fascinating
the heart of this obsession there also lies a body, which is the
moments, simply reproduces itself in countless variations on
body of Lina Romay, who started making films with Franco in
the same theme. In the eye of this sexually obsessive storm
1972 and who has since starred in most of his many dozens
lies the powerful body of Romay, who was given free range
of films. She is also his partner in real life, despite an age
by Franco to improvise her many sex scenes and whose flesh
difference of a generation. This circling around a hard core of
seems to harbour infinite resources of sexual ecstasy.
images and a given set of bodies (for apart from Romay, Fran-
It is in the recording of Romay’s sexual convulsions that soft
co had a stock of several actresses who reappear in film after
focus comes into play again. Unlike his more mainstream
film) recalls the way the Pre-Raphaelites would obsessively
colleagues Franco does not usually use soft focus as a sty-
reproduce Jane Burden’s face or the way Fernand Khnopff
listic tool; it simply occurs in his films. It is often said, and
would paint all the figures in a painting in the image of his
usually not by way of praise, that Franco is obsessed with
beloved sister. As was already mentioned in our discussion of
the so-called crash zoom, which means that the camera will
Anthony Goicolea, Camille Paglia has called this process al-
frantically zoom to single out a point of interest in an image.
legorical repletion, ‘a redundant proliferation of homologous
The crash zoom is a cheap way of avoiding an edit, which
identities in a matrix of sexual ambiguity’ (Paglia 1991: 157)
would require a new shot and a new camera position during
or ‘the filling up of fictive space with a single identity appear-
filming. Instead, Franco allows Romay her performance, cir-
ing simultaneously in different forms, juxtaposed like facets
cles around it with the camera and zooms in on anything and
457
458
everything that grabs his attention. But Franco often uses this
other filmmaker using his camera this way, recreates ‘the
technique to great poetic effect, especially when he combines
interior space of thought’ (Du Mesnildot 2004: 127). This con-
it with reflected images or images filmed through windows
nects back to Scarry, with whom we started this discussion.
with a moving camera. The results of such cheap but effec-
Scarry has pointed out that, neurologically, the eyes are an
tive filming can be stunningly poetical, as in several scenes
extension of the brain (DB 68). In the hands of filmmakers
in Vampyros Lesbos, especially a surreal sequence where blood
like Franco or Warhol the camera becomes the extension of
trickles down a window pane in which several layers of re-
their eyes, and hence of their brains, and hence of their deep-
flected images jump in and out of focus. This sequence plays
est desires. These filmmakers reveal (themselves) through
like a magic lantern for voyeurs. In such sequences Franco’s
their gaze. The restless camera eye, making soft focus occur
films almost become abstract and recall the lyrical cinema
through obsessive movement rather than consciously con-
of Stan Brakhage. In La Comtesse noire Franco uses the zoom
structing it, is constantly trying to focus when it is almost too
in the sex scenes, and especially in an extended sequence of
late to see anything. It makes visible the frustration and ob-
Romay masturbating. Franco tries to focus on Romay’s crotch,
sessive searching of the voyeur or the lover who feels he has
but the image becomes blurry, jumps into focus, goes blurry
never “really” or “fully” seen the desired or beloved body. That
again and then glides away along her thighs. When several
is why he keeps looking. He keeps looking for the body’s se-
people are involved in sex it is sometimes difficult to tell the
cret, and to do this, he must keep looking at the body, return-
bodies apart. But all the time the camera is roving the scene,
ing to it again and again. As an effect of this obsessive gaze,
anxious not to miss anything.
soft focus becomes something entirely different from a cheap
Franco is a true voyeur, constantly looking for that one mo-
commercial trick: it is the phenomenology of desire.
ment or that one detail that will unlock the mystery of the body before him. ‘When I use the zoom,’ Franco explains, ‘it
Cinechroma
is because at that moment there appears on the actor’s face
Apichatpong likes to combine his own memories with those
a unique expression, which will not be repeated and which
of his collaborators to create a new, fictional memory that
must be captured’ (Du Mesnildot 2004: 121-122). Franco has
seems to exist in a parallel universe that is very similar to
also called himself ‘a voyeur not just of fucking, but of ev-
ours and yet ever so slightly different. In Uncle Boonmee Who
erything’ (Tohill and Tombs 1995: 119; Aguilar 1999: 157). And
Can Recall His Past Lives this merging of memories becomes
Franco’s obsessively wandering gaze indeed does not limit
very clear in the remembering-ahead of a society that will be
itself to sexual matters. Very often his camera will drift to a
able to do away with all unwanted individuals. The sensual
detail in a scene that is not dramatically relevant, echoing
flow of the film is suddenly interrupted by a series of still
Warhol’s errant camera eye. Jean-Louis Leutrat has claimed
photos that show the violence of the army against helpless
that in doing so Franco, and by extension Warhol and any
citizens. In an interview in the Belgian press kit for the film
459
460
Apichatpong explains that ‘with that photo scene in the film,
a series of memories of the king in his cell before his execu-
Boonmee’s and my memories merge’ because, obviously, the
tion. The biopic Wittgenstein (1992) is seen through the eyes of
pictures that are remembered-ahead by Boonmee actually
the child Wittgenstein who narrates his own life story in the
refer back to the violence of the 1960s that Apichatpong was
past tense. And, finally, Blue is a sheer projection of inward-
researching for the Primitive project and in which Boonmee
ness, the mind’s eye made cinematic in a monochrome field
is said to have participated. A similar merging of memories
of blue. This structural characteristic of Jarman’s films puts
occurs in Terence Davies’ film Of Time and the City, where Da-
them in the avant-garde tradition of what P. Adams Sitney
vies overlays the general memories of archive footage with
has called the lyrical film. Sitney explains that ‘the lyrical
the more intimate reminiscences of his very personal com-
film postulates the film-maker behind the camera as the
mentary. But the artist and filmmaker who has most radically
first-person protagonist of the film. The images of the film are
fused his own memories with collective history to create a
what he sees, filmed in such a way that we never forget his
synthetic visionary experience of cinematic remembrance is
presence and we know how he is reacting to his vision. In the
Derek Jarman. His film Caravaggio (1986) opens with a shot
lyrical form there is no longer a hero; instead, the screen is
of the painter’s hand preparing the ground on a canvas in
filled with movement, and that movement, both of the cam-
strong repetitive streaks. The canvas fills the screen and is a
era and the editing, reverberates with the idea of a person
fitting metaphor for Jarman’s cinematic practices. For Jarman,
looking. As viewers we see this mediator’s intense experience
the film screen was a moving painting, a celluloid canvas for
of seeing’ (Sitney 2002: 160). The lyrical film was invented
private dreams and memories. This applies most strongly to
by Stan Brakhage, and Pasolini’s notion of the “cinema of
his early experimental shorts, but also to his features, where
poetry” clearly has a family resemblance to the lyrical film.
Jarman often brings his own point of view into the material.
It is also clear that much of Jarman’s work, especially the
Many of Jarman’s features are structured like dreams, memo-
alchemical shorts and the great features The Last of England,
ries, or visions. Jubilee (1978) is framed as a vision of a future
The Garden, and Blue, are firmly anchored in this tradition.
England conjured up by John Dee for Elizabeth I. The Tempest
Other features, such as The Angelic Conversation, fit the form of
(1979) is framed as a pageant dreamt by Prospero. The Angelic
the psychodrama or trance film, out of which the lyrical film
Conversation (1984) is entirely presented as a series of dream
developed. A trance film shows a protagonist (often played by
images. Caravaggio is structured as a series of memories that
the filmmaker him- or herself) engaged in a dreamlike quest
linger in the mind’s eye of the artist on his deathbed. The Last
for sexual identity. The great classical psychodrama’s are Jean
of England (1987) and The Garden (1990) are both framed by im-
Cocteau’s Le Sang d’un poète (1930), which can be said to have
ages of Jarman himself, writing at his desk, conjuring up the
invented the genre, and American films such as Maya Deren’s
films’ episodes and visions. Edward II (1991), based on the play
Meshes of the Afternoon (1942) and Kenneth Anger’s Fireworks
by Christopher Marlowe, has been restructured to resemble
(1947). In fact, Jarman often works in the space between the
461
462
two genres, mixing highly lyrical passages of almost abstract
same time an image and a word. So in hieroglyphs and, by
imagery with fragmented narratives centred on the quest for
extension, in Jarman’s films, word becomes image (and vice
a gay or queer identity.
versa). Jarman once referred to super-8 cinema as ‘contrac-
Jarman started out as a painter and designer, but in 1970 he
tion to a point, the 20th century hieroglyphic monad’ (O’Pray
took up an 8mm camera and started to make experimental
1996: 71). And in his memoir Dancing Ledge (1984) Jarman ex-
shorts. At this time, and partly inspired by his research for
plains that ‘the pleasure of Super 8s is the pleasure of seeing
the sets he designed for Ken Russell’s furious film poem The
language put through the magic lantern. [...] The first viewers
Devils (1971), Jarman was very much influenced by hermetism
wracked their brains for a meaning instead of relaxing into
and alchemy, a Renaissance tradition that was (falsely) traced
the ambient tapestry of random images’ (Jarman 1991: 129).
to Hermes Trismegistos and which had flourished particularly
Jarman’s most ambitious experiments in this personal form
in the English Renaissance with such figures as John Dee and
of cinema are In the Shadow of the Sun (1980), which is to a
Robert Fludd. The idea of the alchemist as a man who can see
large extent a collage of material culled from the earlier
past and future in a mirror fascinated Jarman and inspired
shorts, and The Angelic Conversation (1985), which combines al-
him to introduce alchemical imagery into his films: mirrors,
chemical imagery referring to John Dee’s conversations with
but also fire (as the purifying element), and an expressive
angels with Shakespeare’s homosexual sonnets to create a
use of colour. Jarman’s most important film from this period
reverie of homosexual desire. In these films the screen be-
is The Art of Mirrors (1973), a highly stylised collage of highly
comes a canvas that is engulfed by images that overlap and
symbolical images. The most impressive sequences show
melt away into abstract patches of colour; effects that were
three figures clad in black who move through a maze of burn-
realised through a series of technical manipulations ranging
ing patterns on the ground in a derelict urban site. As they
from double exposures and re-filming of videotaped footage
move about, they use small mirrors to reflect the sunlight
through the use of unusual film speeds and transferring vid-
directly into the camera. The mirrors refer both to the alche-
eotape to film and vice versa. Jarman especially loved to film
mist’s practice of scrying, or: seeing the future in a reflecting
or project (and refilm) at three (or sometimes six) frames per
surface, and to the cult of the sun disc in ancient Egypt. Apart
second, a speed of which he said that it equalled the rhythm
from that the film’s iconography seems rather opaque. This
of the human heartbeat (Peake 2001: 179; O’Pray 1996: 127-
holds for most of Jarman’s experimental work. This is due to
128). The first of Jarman’s films to be made this way was Gar-
the fact that Jarman saw the alchemical imagery mainly as a
den of Luxor (1972), for which he ‘projected two films, one on
visual motif and not as a key to a belief system. Jarman never
top of the other, on his living-room wall and refilmed the re-
practised magic nor did he believe in it. What did fascinate
sult. He used this primitive but perfectly adequate means of
him was the fact that in hieroglyphs and hermetic symbols
achieving such an effect without the use of an optical printer
the visual and the verbal coincide: a hieroglyph is at the
until the mid-80s’ (O’Pray 1996: 65). At some points, the films
463
464
seem to become a cinematic equivalent of the all-over field
violently hypnotic series of visual explosions. A young man
of Abstract Expressionism. The effect amounts to a trance
is seen shooting up in the bombed-out remnants of a house;
film in which the smallest movement of the figures becomes
another young man aggressively kicks a painted reproduction
important, a poetic event, because every single frame of the
of a Caravaggio painting (originally created as a prop for Cara-
film is treated as if it were a self-sufficient painting. In Kicking
vaggio) and proceeds to rub against it in a fucking movement;
the Pricks (1987) Jarman explains that ‘the single frame makes
a naked man gnaws at a raw cauliflower; and there are travel-
for extreme attention, a concentration that is voyeuristic.
ling shots through derelict suburbs shot through with violent
Time seems suspended. The slightest movement is amplified.
visual effects created through manic montage that could be
This is the reason I call it “a cinema of small gestures”’ (Jar-
the envy of Stan Brakhage. The very bare elements of narra-
man 1996a: 146). This phrase was first introduced in the final
tive that hold this despairing vision together point towards
intertitle of Imagining October (1984) but seems especially apt
a totalitarian system. Masked men herd people together at
to describe The Angelic Conversation, which is the tenderest of
gunpoint on the London docks. A young man (Spencer Leigh)
films, focusing to a large extent on the gestures of longing
roams around this urban wasteland, separated from his be-
and love that two young men exchange.
loved (Tilda Swinton). Finally, he is captured and shot by the
But despite its poetic imagery The Angelic Conversation also
masked men. The film culminates in his beloved’s furious
has an undercurrent of menace. ‘Destruction hovers in the
dance on the docks during which she cuts apart her wed-
background of The Angelic Conversation,’ Jarman writes, ‘the
ding dress. This sequence is a whirling montage of image and
feeling one is under psychic attack [...]. In the background of
sound set to a Diamanda Galás soundscape. The imagery of
The Angelic Conversation there is surveillance by Nobodaddy’
The Last of England is at once entirely fragmented and entirely
(o.c. 133). This is made clear in recurrent images of a radar,
coherent. It is a kaleidoscopic mental landscape that entirely
sounding back the silence of the surroundings it is scan-
overwhelms the viewer.
ning, or in a sequence where the lovers toil on the rocky
In a sense, The Last of England is the cinematic culmination
coast, carrying barrels about. The latent threat of The Angelic
of Jarman’s practice of assemblage and montage, which is a
Conversation would become manifest in Jarman’s greatest
constant factor throughout his work. Discussing assemblage,
trance film, The Last of England (1987), which is also one of
Roger Wollen points to ‘Jarman’s interest in film superimpo-
the great achievements in modern experimental cinema. The
sition; montages of positive and negative, black and white,
Last of England takes us into a furiously fragmented world
colour, tinted and untinted sequences in his films and videos;
that is filmed in highly anti-naturalistic colours and seems
and in the books, the interweaving of journal entries, autobi-
to be situated in a vision of London gutted by fire. The film
ography, personal philosophising, gardening notes, social and
is apocalyptic in every sense of the word, both in its themes
political campaigning, poetry and commonplace book com-
and in the way it translates these themes to the screen in a
position’ (Wollen 1996: 26). To which we should add Jarman’s
465
466
work as a painter in the 1980s, assembling found objects and
style of filmmaking, especially in the painting of Giotto and
broken glass onto heavily worked surfaces of pitch or oil. As
Duccio. Similarly, Andy Warhol’s The Chelsea Girls (1966) also
a filmmaker, narration was never Jarman’s strong suit and
juxtaposes, in non-synchronised double projection, vignettes
his best work is always intuitive and associative. But it is held
or stories that supposedly take place in different rooms of the
together by his strong and persistent vision as an artist who
Chelsea Hotel. This technique of storytelling is in a way taken
knows very well what he wants to achieve. But in fracturing
to its extreme in The Last of England, where not only stories or
even the non-narrative sequences that make up The Last of
sequences but sometimes sheer clusters of film frames are
England Jarman in a sense achieves a profoundly postmod-
put next to each other in a whirl of imagery. In the final reck-
ern style. If we remember that Kondylis saw the postmodern
oning, Jarman’s montage leads us back to his claim, referred
sensibility as one constructed through the metaphor of space,
to earlier, that every frame of a film should be treated like a
with all the elements in the world available at once and next
self-contained painting. In his case, an abstract painting with
to each other and in total equality, then the art of montage
leanings towards the all-over field of Abstract Expressionism;
in cinema is clearly a thoroughly postmodern art for it allows
but in spirit there is also a similarity with Giotto and Duccio
the creator to shift time and space about at random (as we
and their series of narrative panel-paintings for altarpieces.
saw already in our discussion of Uncle Boonmee). But Jarman
467
is certainly not the only or even the first director to use mon-
Gardens of the Underworld
tage in such a way and he has in fact acknowledged a debt to
Another important key to The Last of England, but also more
Eisenstein. But other interesting parallels can be suggested.
broadly to Jarman’s work in general, is that the city of London
For instance, Pasolini used the technique of putting several
is itself a character in this film. It is a burned-out ruin that lies
stories next to each other in his Trilogy of Life. In Il Decamerone
broken with its torched innards exposed. Michael O’Pray has
(1970) and in I Racconti di Canterbury (1971) he used a fram-
argued that Jarman was inspired by the work of William Blake
ing story with himself in the role of the narrator or, more
to create this vision. ‘Like Blake,’ O’Pray writes, ‘Jarman was a
precisely, the dreamer of the stories. But in the stunningly
Londoner who believed the city physically embodied the woes
beautiful Il Fiore delle mille e una notte (1973), his film version of
of its times – in sixteenth-century alchemical terms, it was
the Arabian Nights, Pasolini eliminates the framing device of
a microcosm’ (O’Pray 1996: 12). In his poem ‘London’ Blake
Sheherazade and lets the stories melt into each other. It could
describes the city as a claustrophobic space where factories
be argued that the juxtapositioning of several stories in the
devour pale and sickly men. As Blake wanders through this
films and in the literary sources on which they are based is
suffering city, the clamour of the oppressed rises up around
related to the panel painting of the early Renaissance, which
him. Camille Paglia has called this ‘the cinema of Blake’s great
shares a cultural space with the Decamerone and the Canter-
poem “London,” where solitary, excluded voices smear or mar
bury Tales and which was a profound influence on Pasolini’s
the cold stone walls of society’s institutions’ (Paglia 1993:
468
41). But there is also another way in which London functions
describes this underworld as a labyrinthine parallel universe.
as a microcosm in Jarman’s work. Since the 1960s Jarman
Writing of his expeditions to the piers of New York, where
had been part of the homosexual underworld of London. We
men come to cruise at all hours of the day and the night, he
should remember that until the late 1960s, homosexual acts
comments that ‘as you stepped into the dark you entered
were still illegal in Britain. So gay men would meet in illicit
the world of strangers, on the derelict piers you left the im-
bars and meeting places. The homosexual underworld, in
prisoned daylight world behind. The ground was strewn with
London as in any major city, was a parallel world governed
glittering glass from the smashed windows, every shadow
by codes and signs that the straight world did not (want to)
was a potential danger, you kept your money in your shoes.
notice. On this level, the city splits up in two Londons, the
You walked through a succession of huge empty rooms,
“visible” city of the normal world, and the shadow city of the
with young men often naked in the shafts of light which fell
underworld. Geographically, these places are the same. But for
through the windows. The piers had their own beauty; sur-
the members of the underworld society, everyday places have
rounded by water, they were a secret island’ (Jarman 1996a:
a double meaning. A subway station, a bar, or a public lava-
63). The vision of Rome in Pasolini’s unfinished novel Petrolio
tory are often not simply what they seem, but double their
is a similar island, and we last visited it when Carlo was giv-
function as meeting places and points of orientation for those
ing himself to twenty young street thugs on a derelict patch
who are moving among the normal people, visibly indistin-
of urban wasteland. Pasolini, too, makes the city a character
guishable from them, but guided by a different set of cues and
in the novel, as if it were an organism, alive on its many dif-
signs. Under every major city such a clandestine geography
ferent levels, a moloch that harbours its inhabitants like
lies hidden, an alternative lay-out with places and signs that,
micro-organisms that make their ways through its arteries
like hieroglyphs, speak a coded language to those who are in
and organs. On these endless journeys many of the inhabit-
the know about their hermetic meanings. It is a world within
ants end up in the dark crevices of the urban body, where
the world that is guided by a language all its own. Still today
the organism delights in excretory functions that have been
tourists or families with children will lounge on the grass in
edited out of the neatly structured, normalised top-layers of
public parks while unbeknownst to them men are cruising in
external tissue. The normal world is but the surface of such
the shrubbery. Meeting places, secret holes, and corners that
an urban body, the aesthetic bag that holds together all that
are damp with the libations of decades of lubricated nightly
moves and wallows inside.
meetings are spread out through these parks like dots on a
Jim Ellis has made an interesting and convincing connection
map that is not announced at the entrance. There is more to
between Jarman’s creation of parallel worlds and the practic-
any city than its official layout, but one needs the key to the
es of the Situationist International. The Situationists argued
code to be able to read the hidden geography.
for an art that would undermine the commodified world of
In Jarman’s diaries there are exquisite passages in which he
capitalism, which they famously labelled the society of the
469
470
spectacle. Among their favoured practices was the dérive or
cinquecento street urchins have bicycles to roam the streets
drift, which would be a walk through an urban environment
of Rome: these are but a few of Jarman’s many anachronis-
that was unplanned and in which the participants would
tic interventions in these films. But even in their narrative
simply be guided by what drew their attention as they moved
structure the films happily jump back and forth between past
along. This introduces an element of chance that also allows
and present or between reality and dream. ‘When Caravag-
for unconscious desires and longings to surface in the choice
gio is just ten minutes underway,’ Kevin Dillon argues, ‘we
of elements that guide the walk. ‘The dérive has as its goal
have passed through six or seven sheets of time: we see the
the discovery of a certain knowledge about the authentic life
dying Caravaggio, Caravaggio buying the little Jerusaleme,
of the city and the everyday, knowledge that can be used to
Caravaggio’s brief memory of the adult Jerusaleme, and the
challenge modern urban alienation’ (Ellis 2009: 5). Ellis argues
young Caravaggio. Later, we will even see the little Michele
that Jarman has used the dérive in several of his early films,
as he seems to look upon his adult self’ (Dillon 2004: 160). All
notably in his very first film, Studio Bankside (1972), which is a
places, objects, and sheets of time (as Dillon very beautifully
portrait of his studio that moves from object to object in the
calls them) are interchangeable and can flow in and out of
room, mapping a journey through space by connecting com-
each other. This approach is especially salient in Caravag-
monplace points of interest. A similar approach can be found
gio because the artist himself also engaged in such breaking
in Duggie Fields (1973), which records the studio of the art-
open of time and space: his historical and biblical scenes
ist Duggie Fields, and Journey to Avebury (1973), among other
are clearly peopled with contemporary figures. Caravaggio’s
films. The technique of the dérive ‘has the effect of rendering
saints are street people from contemporary Rome. ‘Part of
everything within the studio as equivalent. The paintings,
Jarman’s method in the film is to pick up on Caravaggio’s use
furniture, props, photographs, and the artist himself all be-
of lowlife models and extend it, making the models all char-
come interrelated elements of a larger experience of space’
acters in an invented biography: del Monte, whose surname
(o.c. 24). But this experience of space is the postmodern
was Francesco, becomes the model for the Saint Francis
notion of space that Panajotis Kondylis introduced, where
paintings; Pipo, a young hustler, becomes Love in Amor Vincit
everything and everyone is set on a plane of equality. Every-
Omnia’ (o.c. 123). And the dead Virgin, both in Caravaggio’s
thing, even the most commonplace object, can be a point of
painting and in Jarman’s film, is possibly a drowned prosti-
interest or a source of beauty. Hierarchies fall away.
tute. In the end, such postmodern levelling of space and time
In line with Kondylian space, Jarman also expands this ap-
can result in a form of nihilism that is linked to the ethos of
proach to the experience of time. Several of his films, and
Punk. Jarman developed this in his film Jubilee through the
notably the “historical” films Caravaggio and Edward II, revel in
character of Amyl Nitrate, who is a self-styled ‘historian of
anachronism. Historical characters appear in twentieth cen-
the void’ (o.c. 58). Amyl is writing a new history of England,
tury dress, cardinal Del Monte has a pocket calculator, and
titled Teach Yourself History, from which she reads in the film:
471
472
‘history still fascinates me – it’s so intangible. You can weave
native, parallel universe for the oppressed to live in. This is
facts any way you like. Good guys can swap places with bad
one reason why Jarman often wrote very poetically about his
guys. You might think Richard III of England was bad, but
cruising forays in public parks and on Hampstead Heath. The
you’d be wrong. What separates Hitler from Napoleon or even
surreal night-time world of anonymous sexual encounters is
Alexander? The size of the destruction? Or was he closer to
part of the clandestine urban parallel world that exists under
us in time?’ (Jarman 1996b: 49). It is also in light of this ‘radi-
the neat surface of London. Jim Ellis has linked this creation
cal levelling of the past’ (Ellis 2009: 59) that Punk’s use of the
of parallel spaces to Michel Foucault’s idea of heterotopias,
swastika as a decorative motif should be read. It had nothing
‘real spaces that do not conform to a society’s dominant
to do with anti-Semitism but was an indictment of a govern-
spatial paradigm, that offer space for refuge, resistance, or
ment that claimed to reject fascism and prided itself on hav-
retreat. [...] Foremost among Foucault’s examples of the het-
ing fought Hitler, while at the same time organising totalitar-
erotopia is the garden; other spaces include the theatre, the
ian oppression at home. In levelling history Punk was simply
cinema, prisons, cemeteries, and old-age homes’ (Ellis 2009:
spitting the majority’s moral degeneracy back in its corporate
xiii). Jean Genet’s film Un chant d’amour (1950) chose a prison
face.
as its setting for heterotopia, and in Terence Davies’ films we
In Jubilee it is the capitalist entrepreneur Borgia Ginz (Jack
found that the cinema could be a powerful space of escape.
Birkett) who represents this corrupt society. It is also he
But when he finally set about creating his own heterotopia,
who delivers a leering speech that quite accurately sums up
Derek Jarman chose to retreat into the garden.
the dark side of postmodern relativism: ‘You wanna know my story, babe, it’s easy. This is the generation who grew up
Into The Garden
and forgot to lead their lives. They were so busy watching
Shortly after finishing The Last of England Jarman was diag-
my endless movie. It’s power, babe, Power! I don’t create it, I
nosed hiv-positive. In the remaining years of his life he was
own it. I sucked, and sucked, and sucked. The media became
very open about his status and used it as a way to shape his
their only reality and I owned their world of flickering shad-
activism for the cause of gay rights. About the same time of
ows. BBC, TUC, ATV, ITV, CIA, CBA, NFT, MGM, KGB, C of E.
his diagnosis, Jarman discovered and bought Prospect Cot-
You name it, I bought them all and rearranged the alphabet.
tage, a fisherman’s cabin in Dungeness on the coast of Kent, a
Without me they don’t exist’ (Jarman 1996b: 56-57). It is from
rough and uninhabitable place with a shingle coast. The area
this totalitarian reality that the refugees of The Last of England
was dominated by two nuclear sites. And as there was no soil
are trying to escape. Living in the United Kingdom under
under the shingle, only the most robust plants could flourish
Thatcher, Jarman, as a homosexual, an artist, and a person
in the area. Remarkably, Jarman succeeded in cultivating a
with aids, felt himself, and many others with him, under
garden at Prospect Cottage which has since become famous
attack. Much of his artistic work is aimed at creating an alter-
as one of the most original contemporary gardens. It was also
473
474
to become the centre of his film The Garden (1990), which is
mimicks the working of memory, as we saw in our discussion
a requiem for the many victims of aids. It is a film of anger
of Terence Davies through Elaine Scarry. But The Garden also
and remembrance that is anchored to a poem that expresses
highlights the frailty of memory. The film in fact ends with a
very succinctly what the film is about: ‘I walk in this garden /
stunningly beautiful scene that expresses this frailty better
holding the hands of dead friends’ (Jarman and Sooley 1995:
than any other cinematic image I know. The two young men
81). Like Orpheus descending into the netherworld Jarman
sit together with a woman (Tilda Swinton), a boy, and an old
invites us to share his memories of lives lost in the cold and
man at a table in a bare space. The woman brings in a basket
desperate years of Thatcherism. The film is structured from
of Amaretti sweets. They eat the sweets and then light the
memory, Jarman’s memories of a life spent in an oppressive
wrappers, which rise above them in a brief flurry of fire. Then
society and of lives wasted by that society’s negligence in
the ashes slowly drift down and are caught in the cups of the
dealing with a major health crisis. The film thus takes us into
characters’ hands. In touching the ashes, they are careful not
a very personal garden of remembrance. But this personal
to destroy the remains of the wrappers, which seem to repre-
meditation is combined with an evocation of the Passion,
sent all that is fragile and beautiful in life, in our memories,
with Christ represented by a young gay couple who are ar-
and on this planet.
rested, tortured and humiliated by (who else?) the police. The
In Modern Nature (1991), his published diary of the period
two young men sit bound and gagged at a table, are smeared
when he was making The Garden, Jarman also repeatedly ad-
with syrup, humiliated, intimidated, and flogged. It is a har-
dresses memory and its fragility and links it explicitly to the
rowing sequence that is genuinely infuriating.
garden and to the frailty of flowers. ‘The gardener digs in an-
But The Garden is also a film about resilience in the face of
other time,’ Jarman writes, ‘without past or future, beginning
violence. Living in a society that would be happy to erase
or end. A time that does not cleave the day with rush hours,
homosexuality from its surface of normality, the oppressed
lunch breaks, the last bus home. As you walk in the garden
have gone underground and created a parallel world to
you pass into this time – the moment of entering can never
live out their lives. It is the heterotopia of Jarman’s garden
be remembered. Around you the landscape lies transfigured’
at Dungeness. There is a moving montage near the end of
(Jarman 1992: 30). The garden is a world outside the world,
the film that brings together the elements of nature within
or, a world within the world, similar to the way the vision-
the compass of the garden. In a stream of lyrical images,
ary London of The Last of England appeared to be a parallel
filmed at faster than normal speed, visions of the sea, the
universe that Jarman had projected over the actual city. The
shore, and the surrounding landscape are welded together
visionary power of the garden of remembrance is stressed by
into a visual poem. In this burst of vital imagery Jarman’s
Jarman’s repeated quoting, in the diaries, of medieval her-
film brings the repressed world of the garden back into the
baria that highlight the medicinal or visionary properties of
viewer’s conscious experience. This is the way the cinema
herbs and flowers. Many of the properties Jarman singles out
475
476
have to do with the gift of the seer. ‘My garden is a memo-
thousand pieces’ (Jarman 2001: 330).
rial,’ Jarman writes, ‘each circular bed and dial a true lover’s
As the symptoms of his illness intensified, as they did rap-
knot – planted with lavender, helichryssum and santolina’
idly after the filming of Edward II (1991), a noticeable shift
(o.c. 55). He notes that ‘a sprig of lavender held in the hand or
occurred in Jarman’s diaries. Modern Nature revelled in a lyri-
placed under the pillow enables you to see ghosts, travel to
cism of looking, recording the details and colours of plants
the land of the dead’ (ibid.). ‘Egyptian seers placed the flowers
and herbs. As his eyesight deteriorated in the period covered
of forget-me-not on the eyes of initiates to bring dreams’ (o.c.
in Smiling in Slow Motion Jarman’s observations shifted to-
60). In the garden of memory the various aspects of time, past
wards a lyricism of the hazy: he observes the mist hanging
and future, coalesce. The mind’s eye is free to rove through
over the sea, the haze of dawn, and the almost abstract ex-
time. Dream becomes reality and reality is made dreamlike.
panse of landscapes. But even with failing eyesight his pow-
This means we can see the future, like the alchemist could
ers of perception are remarkable. He writes of ‘a cotton wool
see it in a reflecting surface, and we can bring the past to
mist blowing in veils from the sea, the horizon disappears
life again. Flowers are of central concern in this imagery of
making a very secret garden’ (o.c. 43). ‘Half an hour before the
memory. This should not surprise us in light of Elaine Scarry’s
sun rose, in the first white light of dawn, the shingles are a
discussion of flowers and the space of memory. Their petals
ghostly bleached bone, grisaille silhouetting the grey of the
are sheer and luminous, like the transparent visions of cine-
shrubs and black of the broom, a silent light unshattered by
ma or the interior screen of the mind’s eye. And like the base-
colour’ (o.c. 131). Jarman describes how ‘the grey washes an
less fabric of this inner vision or the ashen texture of burnt
intense colour into the garden’ (o.c. 136) and how a dense
Amaretti wrappers the petals of flowers are easily destroyed;
mist ‘left the garden sparkling with dewy spiders’ webs. As
all it takes, is a careless flick of the finger or the crushing
the sun came up the mist glowed an iridescent white’ (o.c.
step of a foot. ‘You can’t pick bluebells,’ Jarman reminds us
140). Alongside the observations there is another shift, away
in Kicking the Pricks, ‘they wilt, even as you touch them. How
from the material world and towards the mystical, as if Jar-
often that happened as a child: the terrible guilt you felt, put-
man’s losing battle with aids were preparing him for his final
ting them in water you knew would never revive them. The
goodbye to this world. Elaine Scarry has described how pain
feeling of loss the next morning as you threw them into the
locks people in their bodies and Jarman’s observations on his
dustbin. It’s easy to murder a bluebell wood’ (Jarman 1996a:
own agonies express this with painful accuracy. ‘At moments
237-239). In the posthumously published diaries of Smiling in
I wish my physical self would evaporate, cease, no more
Slow Motion (2000) Jarman tells us how Keith Collins, his true
aches and pains’ (o.c. 114). He describes his increasing blind-
love, ‘shocked us by picking up a daffodil and plunging it into
ness as a ‘strange feeling, disembodied eyesight; there is a
the liquid nitrogen for burning my molluscum. It came out
distinct falling off of vision on my left, a grey area that comes
smoking. He flicked it with his finger and it shattered into a
and goes’ (o.c. 187) almost like a mist blowing in from over
477
478
the sea and retreating again. ‘One interviewer asked me how
intimidating about mere formlessness: it is a muddle. What
much the illness dictated my life. At this moment almost
makes the true sublime so discomforting is the fact that it
completely, there’s no life outside it, I’m locked in. My entire
still harbours the shape that it is about to undo. The sublime
physical self is a ruin that hurts’ (o.c. 372).
is a form shown on the verge of its disappearance, as in the
Turning inward Jarman produced one final film, Blue (1993),
melting figures of Francis Bacon’s paintings. Similarly, Blue
a monochrome blue screen over which we hear a collage of
invites us in to partake in Jarman’s experience of self as the
diary entries, observations, street sounds, and music. The text
outside world takes its leave with encroaching blindness. But
of the film is included in his book Chroma (1993), in which
the inner eye, the mind’s eye, is as quick and alert as ever.
the objects in the world give way to colour, an abstract haze
Jim Ellis writes that because of the monochrome blue screen,
that fills the field of vision as blindness takes over. Just as he
‘the film’s image track is constructed in the viewer’s head.
was careful to note the alchemical and magical properties of
This intimacy of film and audience is furthered by the physi-
flowers in his diaries, Jarman here remarks on the magical
cal properties of the medium: the blue screen lulls us into
or ritual significance of colours. About the black draperies
receptivity, while we are surrounded and penetrated by the
that are the backdrop for his immaculate film on Wittgen-
soundtrack. Sound is a more intimate medium than vision.
stein (1992) he writes that ‘black velvet registers as infinity
It is vision that allows for the separation between ourselves
on film with no form or boundary, a black without end, that
and the object or the image, and we can shut our eyes to
lurks behind the blue sky’ (Jarman 1995: 137). Kevin Dillon
close off the experience. There is less voluntary control of
notes that the film is set in ‘a series of open interiors with-
the sense of sound, and it serves to connect us rather than
out horizons’ (Dillon 2004: 218). Finally, Jarman accepts and
separate us from the world, helping us to orient ourselves in
embraces with relief the liberating abstraction of the colour
space’ (Ellis 2009: 241). Observing and acutely experiencing
field: ‘From the bottom of your heart, pray to be released from
his own disappearance from this world, Jarman has found
image’ (Jarman 1995: 115). Having reduced (or replenished)
in Blue an artistic form that objectively represents this most
cinema to an immaculate blue screen that whispers voices
subjective of processes. Memories rise up and mingle with
into our consciousness, Jarman is literally living among the
the experience of the present, again obliterating the ordinary
voices of dead friends (he once said that ‘the only real thing
relations of time and space. Experience becomes an eternal,
I like about my films is that it is possible to see my dead and
expansive now where past and present coalesce, aware of
dying friends in all the nooks and crannies’; Hacker and Price
the fact that there is precious little future left to turn to. ‘Why
1991: 260). Blue captures a consciousness on the verge of its
have I escaped from the garden?’ Jarman asks (Jarman and
disappearance. This makes it a sublime work. It is a common
Sooley 1995: 63). ‘Because it has no fence or boundaries, so
misconception to link the sublime in art with shapelessness.
who can guess where it ends?’
But there is nothing especially impressive, overwhelming, or
479
480
481
Carlos Aguilar, Jess Franco. El sexo del horror, Florence, Glittering Images, 1999. Christopher Alexander, The Timeless Way of Building, New York, Oxford University Press, 1979. Keimpe Algra, Jonathan Barnes, Jaap
John Armstrong, Move Closer. An Intimate Philosophy of Art, New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2000. Julie Ault, ‘The Subject Is Exhibition’, in: Russell Ferguson and Dominic Molon (eds.), Wolfgang Tillmans, Los
(eds.), The Cambridge History of Hel-
Angeles/Chicago/New Haven/London,
lenistic Philosophy, Cambridge, Cam-
Hammer Museum/Museum of Con-
bridge University Press, 2005.
temporary Art/Yale University Press,
Hunt. The True Pre-Raphaelite, London, Constable, 1989. Callie Angell, Andy Warhol Screen
Bibliography
Press, 1982.
Mansfeld, and Malcolm Schofield
Anne Clark Amor, William Holman
482
Chicago, The University of Chicago
2006, p. 119-137. Clive Barker, Weaveworld [1987], London, HarperCollins, 1999. Jonathan Barnes, ‘Rhetoric and po-
Tests. The Films of Andy Warhol. Cata-
etics’, in: Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The
logue Raisonné. Volume 1, New York,
Cambridge Companion to Aristotle,
Abrams/Whitney Museum of Ameri-
Cambridge, Cambridge University
can Art, 2006.
Press, 1995, p. 259-285.
Timothy Archibald, Sex Machines.
Roland Barthes, La chambre claire.
Photographs and Interviews, Carrboro/
Note sur la photographie, Paris, Cahiers
Los Angeles, Daniel 13/Process, 2005.
du cinéma/Gallimard/Seuil, 1980.
Hannah Arendt, The Origins of To-
Heiner Bastian, Sammlung Marx. Andy
talitarianism [1951], new edition with
Warhol: Frühe Zeichnungen, Munich,
added prefaces, San Diego/New York/
Schirmer/Mosel, 1996.
London, Harcourt, 1968. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condi-
Charles Baudelaire, Au-delà du romantisme. Écrits sur l’art, edited by
tion [1958], second edition with an
Michel Draguet, Paris, Flammarion,
introduction by Margaret Canovan,
1998.
Chicago/Londen, The University of Chicago Press, 1998. Hannah Arendt, Between Past and
Mark Bauerlein (ed.), National Endowment for the Arts: A History, 1965-2008, Washington, National Endowment for
Future. Eight Exercises in Political
the Arts, 2009 (http://www.nea.gov/
Thought [1961, expanded 1968], Har-
pub/nea-history-1965-2008.pdf; ac-
mondsworth, Penguin, 1977.
cessed February 23, 2010).
Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s
Frederick C. Beiser, The Fate of Reason.
Political Philosophy, edited with and-
German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte,
interpretative essay by Ronald Beiner,
Cambridge/London, Harvard Univer-
483
sity Press, 1987. Bernardo Bertolucci and Jean-Louis
Kenneth Burke, The Philosophy of
Arthur C. Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. A Philosophy of Art,
University of Texas Press, 2004. Anne Distel, Douglas W. Druick, Gloria
Comolli, ‘Le cinéma selon Pasolini’,
Literary Form. Studies in Symbolic Ac-
Cambridge/London, Harvard Univer-
Groom, Rodolphe Rapetti, and Julia
in: Cahiers du Cinéma, Nr. 169, August
tion [1941], third edition, Berkeley/Los
sity Press, 1981.
Sagraves, Gustave Caillebotte. Urban
1965, p. 20-25 and 76-77.
Angeles/London, University of Califor-
Daniel Birnbaum, ‘A New Visual Register for Our Perceptual Apparatus’, in:
nia Press, 1973. Walter Burkert, Homo Necans. The An-
Arthur C. Danto, ‘Foreword’, in: Su-
Impressionist, Chicago/New York, The
sanne K. Langer, Mind: An Essay on
Art Institute of Chicago/Abbeville
Human Feeling, abridged by Gary Van
Press, 1995.
Russell Ferguson and Dominic Molon
thropology of Ancient Greek Sacrificial
Den Heuvel, Baltimore/London, Johns
E.R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irra-
(eds.), Wolfgang Tillmans, Los Angeles/
Ritual and Myth [Homo Necans, 1972],
Hopkins University Press, 1988, p. v-vi.
tional, Berkeley/Los Angeles/London,
Chicago/New Haven/London, Hammer
translated from the German by Peter
Museum/Museum of Contemporary
Bing, Berkeley/Los Angeles/London,
The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Per-
Art/Yale University Press, 2006, p.
University of California Press, 1983.
spective, Berkeley/Los Angeles/London,
Bloom. The Art and Life of Georgia
University of California Press, 1992.
O’Keeffe, New York, Norton, 2004.
15-29. Daniel Birnbaum, ‘Late’, in: Cerith
484
Main, Suhrkamp, 1974.
Walter Burkert, Greek Religion. Archaic and Classical [Griechische Religion der
Arthur C. Danto, Beyond the Brillo Box.
Arthur C. Danto, Playing with the
University of California Press, 1951. Hunter Drohojowska-Philp, Full
Simon Dwyer, Rapid Eye Movement,
Wyn Evans, ...visibleinvisible, with es-
archaischen und klassischen Epoche,
Edge. The Photographic Achievement
says by Daniel Birnbaum and Octavio
1977], translated from the German by
of Robert Mapplethorpe, Berkeley/Los
Zaya, Ostfildern, Hatje Cantz, 2008a,
John Raffan, Malden/Oxford, Blackwell,
Angeles/Londen, University of Califor-
Conversations, Minneapolis/London,
p. 23-29.
1985.
nia Press, 1996.
University of Minnesota Press, 2009.
Daniel Birnbaum, ‘“At that point...”’,
Robert Christopher and Townseley
Arthur C. Danto, After the End of Art.
London, Creation Books, 1999. Jim Ellis, Derek Jarman’s Angelic
Kodwo Eshun, ‘Under the Flightpath’,
in: Wolfgang Tillmans, Lighter, Ostfil-
Parker, ‘Greek sacrifice’, in: Simon
Contemporary Art and the Pale of His-
in: i-D The White Issue, Nr. 203, Novem-
dern, Hatje Cantz, 2008b, p. 7-9.
Hornblower and Antony Spawforth
tory, Princeton, Princeton University
ber 2000, p. 104-116.
Harold Bloom, The Western Canon. The
(eds.), The Oxford Companion to Classi-
Press, 1997.
Books and School of the Ages, New York,
cal Civilization, Oxford/New York, Ox-
Harcourt Brace & Company, 1994.
ford University Press, 2004, p. 628-629.
Harold Bloom, Shakespeare. The Invention of the Human, New York, Riverhead Books, 1998. Harold Bloom, Genius. A Mosaic of One Hundred Exemplary Creative Minds, New York, Warner Books, 2002. David Bockris, Warhol: the biography [1988], New York, Da Capo, 1997. David Bourdon, Warhol, New York, Abrams, 1989. Sylvia Bourdon, L’Amour est une fête [1976], Paris, Éditions Blanche, 2001. Peter Bürger, Theorie der Avantgarde, with a new postscript, Frankfurt am
Kenneth Clark, The Nude [1956], Harmondsworth, Penguin/Pelican, 1960. Larry Clark, Tulsa, New York, Grove Press, 1971. Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy. Volume 6: The Enlightenment,
Arthur C. Danto, The Abuse of Beauty. Aesthetics and the Concept of Art, Chi-
Octavio Zaya, Ostfildern, Hatje Cantz,
cago/La Salle, Open Court, 2003.
2008.
Arthur C. Danto, The Philosophical
des Baron von Kempelen, Dortmund,
a foreword by Jonathan Gilmore, New
Harenberg, 1983.
York, Columbia University Press, 2005a. Arthur C. Danto, Unnatural Wonders. Essays from the Gap Between Art and
Continuum, 1960 (reprint 2008).
Life, New York, Columbia University
‘Waiting For The Prince: an interview
Marion Faber, Der Schachautomat
Disenfranchisement of Art [1986], with
Voltaire to Kant, London/New York, Fergus Daly and Maximilian Le Cain,
Cerith Wyn Evans, ...visibleinvisible, with essays by Daniel Birnbaum and
Press, 2005b. Denis Diderot, Le rêve de d’Alembert,
Richard Falcon, ‘Last tango in Lewisham’, in: Sight and Sound, NS Vol. 11, Nr. 7, July 2001, p. 20-24. Felix Lance Falkon, Gay Art. A Historic Collection [1972], edited with an introduction and captions by Thomas
with Béla Tarr’, in: Senses of Cinema,
edited by Colas Duflo, Paris, Flam-
Waugh, Vancouver, Arsenal Pulp Press,
Nr. 12, February-March 2001
marion, 2002.
2006.
(www.sensesofcinema.com/contents/01/12/tarr.html).
Steven Dillon, Derek Jarman and Lyric Film. The Mirror and the Sea, Austin,
Russell Ferguson and Dominic Molon (eds.), Wolfgang Tillmans, Los Angeles/
485
Chicago/New Haven/London, Hammer
2 Vols., Baltimore/London, The Johns
avec Ovidie’, in: La voix du regard, Nr.
cal Civilization, Oxford/New York, Ox-
Museum/Museum of Contemporary
Hopkins University Press, 1993.
15 (L’obscène, acte ou image?), fall 2002,
ford University Press, 2004, p. 232-235.
Art/Yale University Press, 2006. Russell Ferguson, ‘Faces in the Crowd’,
sang’, in: La voix du regard, Nr. 15
p. 78-90. W.K.C. Guthrie, The Greeks and Their
in: Russell Ferguson and Dominic
(L’obscène, acte ou image?), fall 2002, p.
Gods [1950], Boston, Beacon Press,
Molon (eds.), Wolfgang Tillmans, Los
172-179.
1954.
Angeles/Chicago/New Haven/London,
Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Faust.
Paul Guyer, ‘Kant’s ambitions in the
Hammer Museum/Museum of Con-
Der Tragödie erster und zweiter Teil.
third Critique’, in: Paul Guyer (ed.),
temporary Art/Yale University Press,
Urfaust, edited with a commentary by
The Cambridge Companion to Kant
2006, p. 65-83.
Erich Trunz, Munich, Beck, 1986.
and Modern Philosophy, Cambridge,
Paul Flynn, ‘Mr. Wolfgang Tillmans. The particularities of the artist who
Anthony Goicolea, Anthony Goicolea, Santa Fe, Twin Palms, 2003.
Robert Hewison, John Ruskin, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2007. Howard Hibbard, Michelangelo, second edition [1985], Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1992. Timothy Hilton, The Pre-Raphaelites, London, Thames and Hudson, 1970. David Hockney, That’s the way I see
Cambridge University Press, 2006, p.
it, edited by Nikos Stangos, London,
538-587.
Thames and Hudson, 1993.
makes the ordinary extraordinary’, in:
RoseLee Goldberg, Performance Art.
Jonathan Hacker and David Price,
Fantastic Man, Nr. 11, Spring/Summer
From Futurism to the Present, revised
Take Ten. Contemporary British Film
Rediscovering the lost techniques of the
and expanded edition, New York,
Directors, Oxford/New York, Oxford
Old Masters, new and expanded edi-
Thames & Hudson, 2001.
University Press, 1991.
tion, London, Thames and Hudson,
2010, p. 92-109. E.M. Forster, Howards End [1910], edited by Oliver Stallybrass, Harmond-
486
Sophie Gayet, ‘Journiac, la fête du
sworth, Penguin, 1989. Elizabeth Frank, ‘The End of Art Ac-
Nan Goldin, I’ll Be Your Mirror, edited by Nan Goldin, David Armstrong, and
of Martha Nussbaum’, in: Representa-
Hans Werner Holzwarth, New York/
tions, 77, winter 2002, p. 52-81.
cording to Arthur Danto’, in: Robert
Zurich, Whitney Museum of American
Boyers and Peggy Boyers (eds.), The
Art/Scalo, 1996.
New Salmagundi Reader, s.l., Syracuse University Press, 1996, 270-284.
Geoffrey Galt Harpham, ‘The Hunger
Nan Goldin, The Devil’s Playground, London, Phaidon, 2003.
Neil Harris, The Artist in American Society. The Formative Years 1790-1860 [1966], with a new preface, Chicago/ London, The University of Chicago Press, 1982.
David Hockney, Secret Knowledge.
2006. Christina Hoff Sommers, Who Stole Feminism? How Women Have Betrayed Women, New York, Touchstone, 1995. Fred Hoffman (ed.), Chris Burden, London, Thames & Hudson, 2007. Alan Hollinghurst, The Line of Beauty
Manfred Frank, Eine Einführung in
Kenneth Goldsmith (ed.), I’ll Be Your
Schellings Philosophie, Frankfurt am
Mirror. The Selected Andy Warhol Inter-
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Phän-
Main, Suhrkamp, 1985.
views, 1962-1987, with an introduction
omenologie des Geistes [1807], edited by
forth (eds.), The Oxford Companion to
[2004], London, Picador, 2005. Simon Hornblower and Antony Spaw-
by Reva Wolf and an Afterword by
Hans-Friedrich Wessels and Heinrich
Classical Civilization, Oxford/New York,
romantische Philosophie. Vorlesungen,
Wayne Koestenbaum, New York, Car-
Clairmont with an introduction by
Oxford University Press, 2004.
Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 1989.
roll & Graf, 2004.
Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Hamburg, Mei-
Manfred Frank, Einführung in die früh-
Manfred Frank, “Unendliche Annäher-
Robert Graves, The Greek Myths, re-
ung”. Die Anfänge der philosophischen
vised edition, 2 Vols., Harmondsworth,
Frühromantik, Frankfurt am Main,
Penguin, 1960.
Suhrkamp, 1997. Manfred Frank, Auswege aus dem Deutschen Idealismus, Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 2007. Timothy Gantz, Early Greek Myth. A Guide to Literary and Artistic Sources,
ner, 1988. Christoph Heinrich (ed.), Emotions and Relations. Nan Goldin. David Arm-
Robert Hughes, Culture of Complaint. The Fraying of America, New York, Warner Books, 1994. Robert Hughes, American Visions. The
strong. Mark Morrisroe. Jack Pierson.
Epic History of Art in America, London,
Job, Philadelphia, Temple University
Philip-Lorca diCorcia, Cologne, Taschen,
The Harvill Press, 1997.
Press, 2003.
1998.
Roy Grundmann, Andy Warhol’s Blow
Anna Guilló, Jocelyn Maixent, and
Albert Henrichs, ‘Dionysus’, in: Simon
Alexander von Humboldt, Kosmos. Entwurf einer physischen Weltbesch-
Véronique Dimicoli, ‘“La pornographie
Hornblower and Antony Spawforth
reibung, 2 Vols., edited by Ottmar Ette
sans obscène, c’est triste.” Entretien
(eds.), The Oxford Companion to Classi-
and Oliver Lubrich, Frankfurt am Main,
487
Eichborn, 2004. Alice L. Hutchison, Kenneth Anger. A Demonic Visionary, London, Black Dog Publishing, 2004. Timothy Hyman, Bonnard, London, Thames and Hudson, 1998.
tage, 1995. Derek Jarman, Up In The Air. Collected Film Scripts, with an introduction by Michael O’Pray, London, Vintage, 1996b.
Robert E. Innis, Susanne Langer in
Derek Jarman, Smiling in Slow Motion
Focus. The Symbolic Mind, Blooming-
[2000], edited by Keith Collins, London,
ton/Indianapolis, Indiana University
Vintage, 2001.
Press, 2009. Jonathan I. Israel, Radical Enlightenment. Philosophy and the Making of Modernity 1650-1750, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2001. Margaret Iversen, ‘What is a photograph?’, in: Art History, Vol. 17, Nr. 3, September 1994, p. 450-463.
488
Derek Jarman, Chroma. A Book of Colour – June ’93 [1994], London, Vin-
Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, Über die Lehre des Spinoza in Briefen an den Herrn Moses Mendelssohn [1785, sec-
Derek Jarman and Howard Sooley, der-
Phaidon, 2000, p. 16-47. William E. Jones, ‘Fred Halsted. Rather Late Yet Interesting Interview With Dead Porno Artist’, in: BUTT, Nr. 22, Spring 2008, p. 24-28. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen
Immanuel Kant, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, edited by Horst D. Brandt and Heiner F. Klemme, Hamburg, Meiner, 2003.
2008, p. 35-39.
Urteilskraft, edited with an introduc-
Derek Jarman, Kicking the Pricks [= Vintage, 1996a. Derek Jarman, Modern Nature. The Journals of Derek Jarman [1991], London, Vintage, 1992.
University Press, 1957a.
Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1957b.
Beilage: Erste Einleitung in die Kritik der
The Last of England, 1987], London,
edition, Cambridge/Londen, Harvard
1960-1971. Der zertrümmerte Spiegel/
kogler, Klagenfurt, Ritter, 1989.
Amelia Jones, ‘Survey’, in: Tracey Warr (ed.), The Artist’s Body, London,
mans, Lighter, Ostfildern, Hatje Cantz,
tet Books, 1991.
of Reason, Rite, and Art [1942], third
mus/Viennese Aktionism. Wien/Vienna
Susanne K. Langer, Problems of Art.
Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft.
edited by Shaun Allen, London, Quar-
Hubert Klocker (ed.), Wiener Aktionis-
Susanne K. Langer, Philosophy in a New Key. A Study in the Symbolism
Ten Philosophical Lectures, New York,
Truth Study Center’, in: Wolfgang Till-
Derek Jarman, Dancing Ledge [1984],
London, Penguin, 2008.
(reprint 1973).
Mühl, Hermann Nitsch, Rudolf Schwarz-
Hamburg, Meiner, 1998.
Wolfgang Tillmans’s Major Project
The Rise of Disaster Capitalism [2007],
Routledge & Kegan Paul Limited, 1953
Hudson, 1995.
Hammacher, Irmgard-Maria Piske and
Joachim Jäger, ‘Labyrinth of Truths.
Naomi Klein, The Shock Doctrine.
‘Philosophy in a New Key’, Londen,
The Shattered Mirror. Günter Brus, Otto
Vernunft, edited by Jens Timmermann,
2000.
Naomi Klein, No Logo, London, Flamingo, 2000.
Susanne K. Langer, Feeling and Form. A Theory of Art Developed From
ek jarman’s garden, London, Thames &
ond edition 1789], edited by Klaus Marion Lauschke, Hamburg, Meiner,
James T. Kirk, The Shaker World. Art, Life, Belief, New York, Abrams, 1997.
Stephen Koch, Stargazer. The Life,
Sketches, Baltimore, The Johns Hopkins
revised edition, New York/London,
Press, 1962.
Marion Boyars, 1991.
on Human Feeling. Volume I, Baltimore/
von Volker Koch (1972) ein Gespräch
London, The Johns Hopkins University
mit Pier Paolo Pasolini’, in: Filmkritik,
Press, 1967.
Nr. 305, May 1982, p. 204-210. Wayne Koestenbaum, Andy Warhol, Harmondsworth/New York, Viking/ Penguin, 2001. Panajotis Kondylis, Macht und Entscheidung. Die Herausbildung der Weltbilder und die Wertfrage, Stuttgart, Klett-Cotta, 1984. Panajotis Kondylis, Der Niedergang der bürgerlichen Denk- und Lebensform.
Meiner, 2006.
Die liberale Moderne und die massende-
Abstracts, New York, Prestel, 1993. Philip Kemp, ‘Gone to earth’, in: Sight
Susanne K. Langer, Mind: An Essay
Volker Koch, ‘Aus dem Film S.P.Q.R.
tion by Heiner F. Klemme, Hamburg, Thomas Kellein (ed.), Andy Warhol:
Susanne K. Langer, Philosophical
World and Films of Andy Warhol [1973],
Nigella Lawson, How To Eat. The Pleasures and Principles of Good Food, London, Chatto & Windus, 1998. Edward Lucie-Smith, Movements in Art since 1945. New edition, London, Thames and Hudson, 2001. Armando Maggi, The Resurrection of the Body. Pier Paolo Pasolini from Saint Paul to Sade, Chicago/London, The University of Chicago Press, 2009. Robert Mapplethorpe, Altars, edited
mokratische Postmoderne, Weinheim,
by Mark Holborn and Dimitri Levas
VCH/Acta Humaniora, 1991.
with an essay by Edmund White, Lon-
Panajotis Kondylis, Die Aufklärung im
don, Jonathan Cape, 1995.
and Sound, NS Vol. 11, Nr. 1, January
Rahmen des neuzeitlichen Rationalis-
2001, p. 22-24.
mus [1981], Hamburg, Meiner, 2002.
by Dimitri Levas with an essay by In-
Dean R. Koontz, Demon Seed, New
grid Sischy, s.l., Arena Editions, 1999.
G.S. Kirk, The Nature of Greek Myths, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1974.
York, Bantam, 1973.
Robert Mapplethorpe, Pictures, edited
Ari Marcopoulos, Transitions and Ex-
489
manity. Disgust, Shame, and the Law,
Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari,
Princeton/Oxford, Princeton University
Gérard A. Goodrow and Peter Weier-
politischen Ökonomie. Erster Band. Buch
Munich/Berlin/New York, Deutscher
Press, 2004.
mair, Kilchberg/Zurich, Edition Stem-
I: Der Produktionsprozess des Kapitals
Taschenbuch Verlag/de Gruyter, 1999a,
[1867], edited by Walter Schulz, Berlin,
p. 9-156.
Karl Marx, Das Kapital. Kritik der
Karl Dietz, 1962. Karl Marx, Ökonomisch-philosophische
Friedrich Nietzsche, Die fröhliche Wissenschaft [1882], in: Friedrich Ni-
Michael O’Pray, Derek Jarman. Dreams of England, London, British Film Institute, 1996. Camille Paglia, Sexual Personae. Art
mle, 1997. Jack Pierson, every single one of them, Santa Fe, Twin Palms, 2004. Jack Pierson, Jack Pierson, Dublin/Mi-
Manuskripte, edited with an introduc-
etzsche, Kritische Studienausgabe, Vol.
and Decadence from Nefertiti to Em-
lan/New York, Irish Museum of Modern
tion and notes by Barbara Zehnpfen-
3, edited by Giorgio Colli and Mazzino
ily Dickinson [1990], Harmondsworth,
Art/Charta, 2008.
nig, Hamburg, Meiner, 2005.
Montinari, Munich/Berlin/New York,
Penguin, 1992.
Will McBride, I Will McBride, Cologne, Könemann, 1997. Stéphane du Mesnildot, Jess franco.
Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag/de Gruyter, 1999b, p. 343-651. Hermann Nitsch, Das Orgien Mys-
Camille Paglia, Sex, Art and American Culture. Essays [1992], Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1993. Camille Paglia, Vamps & Tramps. New
Énergies du fantasme, Pertuis, Rouge
terien Theater. Manifeste. Aufsätze.
Profond, 2004.
Vorträge, Salzburg/Vienna, Residenz
Essays [1994], Harmondsworth, Pen-
Verlag, 1990.
guin, 1995.
Debra Miller, Billy Name: Stills From The Warhol Films, Munich/New York,
490
Jack Pierson, The Lonely Life, edited by
tische Studienausgabe, Vol. 1, edited by
its, New York, powerHouse Books, 2000.
Prestel, 1994. Mark Morrisroe, Mark Morrisroe, Santa Fe, Twin Palms, 1999.
Hermann Nitsch, Das Sechstagespiel des Orgien Mysterien Theaters 1998,
Dream Thing I Do’, in: Joseph S. Cze-
Ostfildern-Ruit, Hatje Cantz, 2003.
stochowski (ed.), Georgia O’Keeffe.
Hermann Nitsch, Das Sein. Zur Theorie
Patricia Morrisroe, Mapplethorpe. A
des Orgien Mysterien Theaters, 3 Vols.,
Biography, London, Macmillan/Paper-
Vienna/Graz/Klagenfurt, Styria, 2009.
mac, 1995. Regula Maria Müller, Werken 19902003, Rotterdam, Phoebus, 2003. Regula Maria Müller, Regula Maria Müller, with an essay by Helga Scholl, Aachen, Raum für Kunst, 2007. Regula Maria Müller, De Muzen van Erasmus/The Muses of Erasmus, s.l., RTBOOKS, 2010. Angelika Muthesius (ed.), Jeff Koons, with an essay by Jean-Christophe Ammann, Cologne, Benedikt Taschen, 1992. Friedrich Nietzsche, Die Geburt der Tragödie aus dem Geiste der Musik [1872], in: Friedrich Nietzsche, Kri-
Eugenia Parry, ‘That Memory or
Martha C. Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge. Essays on Philosophy and Literature, New York/Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1990. Martha C. Nussbaum, Poetic Justice. The Literary Imagination and Public Life, Boston, Beacon Press, 1995. Martha C. Nussbaum, Cultivating Humanity. A Classical Defense of Reform in
Visions of the Sublime, Memphis, International Arts, 2004, p. 1-11. Pier Paolo Pasolini, ‘Le cinéma de poésie’, in: Cahier du Cinéma, Nr. 171, October 1965, p. 55-64.
Michael Polanyi and Harry Prosch, Meaning, Chicago/London, The University of Chicago Press, 1975. James Quandt, ‘Ride Lonesome’, in: Artforum, Vol. XLVII, Nr. 3, November 2008, p. 331-335. James Quandt (ed.), Apichatpong Weerasethakul, Vienna, Synema, 2009. Herbert Read, The Philosophy of Modern Art, London, Faber and Faber, 1952. Donald F. Reuter, Shirtless! The Hollywood Male Physique, New York, Universe, 2000. Frank Rodriguez, ‘Joe Gage. Top Pornographer Loves To Bang Out A Load
Pier Paolo Pasolini, Pétrole [Petrolio,
While Watching His Own Legendary
1992], enlarged edition, edited by Au-
Films’, in: BUTT, Nr. 19, Spring 2007,
relio Roncaglia, translated by René De
p. 16-23.
Ceccatty, Paris, Gallimard, 2006. Scott Pearson, Ultimate Falcon, Berlin, Bruno Gmünder, 2009. F.E. Peters, Greek Philosophical Terms,
Richard Rorty, Contingency, irony, and solidarity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1989. Aaron Rose and Christian Strike
Liberal Education, Cambridge/London,
New York/London, New York University
(eds.), Beautiful Losers, second edition,
Harvard University Press, 1997.
Press/University of London Press, 1967.
s.l., Iconoclast, 2008.
Martha C. Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought. The Intelligence of Emotions, New York, Cambridge University Press, 2001. Martha C. Nussbaum, Hiding from Hu-
Anita Phillips, A Defence of Masoch-
Robert Rosenblum, Modern Painting
ism, London, Faber and Faber, 1998.
and the Northern Romantic Tradition:
Jack Pierson, All of a sudden [1995],
Friedrich to Rothko, London, Thames
second edition, New York, powerHouse Books, 1999.
and Hudson, 1975. Harry Ruhé, Het Beste van/The Best
491
of Wim T. Schippers, Utrecht, Centraal Museum, 1997. John Ruskin, Modern Painters [1873],
Friedrich Schlegel, Kritische Schriften und Fragmente, 6 Vols., edited by Ernst
The H.W. Wilson Company, 1988, p.
edition, New York, Thames and Hud-
141-145.
son, 1987.
Harvey Siegel, Rationality Redeemed?
David Sylvester, Francis Bacon. The
edited and abridged by David Barrie,
Behler and Hans Eichner, Paderborn,
Further Dialogues on an Educational
Human Body, Berkeley/Los Angeles/
revised edition, London, Pilkington
Schöningh, 1988.
Ideal, New York/London, Routledge,
London, The University of California
1997.
Press, 1998.
Press, 2000. Aaron Sachs, The Humboldt Current.
Eckhard Schneider (ed.), Santiago Sierra. 300 Tons and Previous Works,
Nineteenth-Century Exploration and the
Cologne/Bregenz, Walther König/Kun-
Roots of American Environmentalism,
sthaus Bregenz, 2004.
New York, Viking, 2006.
Florian Schreiner, Das Aktionstheater
P. Adams Sitney, Visionary Film. The
Wolfgang Tillmans, Wolfgang Till-
American Avant-Garde 1943-2000,
mans, edited by Burckhard Riemsch-
third edition, Oxford/New York, Oxford
neider with an essay by Simon Watney,
University Press, 2002.
Cologne, Taschen, 1995.
des Hermann Nitsch zwischen Herkunft
P. Adams Sitney, Eyes Upside Down.
trated History of the Cinema of Trans-
und Zukunft, s.l., Edition Kröthenhayn,
Visionary Filmmakers and the Heritage
lebt morgen, Wolfsburg/Ostfildern, Kun-
gression, London, Creation Books, 1995.
2006.
of Emerson, New York, Oxford Univer-
stmuseum Wolfsburg/Cantz, 1996.
Jack Sargeant, Deathtripping. An Illus-
492
Stuttgart, Reclam, 2000.
Wolfgang Tillmans, Wer Liebe wagt
Elaine Scarry, The Body in Pain. The
Duane P. Schultz and Sydney Ellen
Making and Unmaking of the World,
Schultz, A History of Modern Psychol-
New York/Oxford, Oxford University
ogy, sixth edition, Fort Worth, Harcourt
The Cambridge Companion to Wittgen-
Wolfgang Tillmans, Soldiers: The nine-
Press, 1985
Brace College Publishers, 1996.
stein, Cambridge, Cambridge Univer-
ties, Cologne, Verlag der Buchhandlung
sity Press, 1996.
Walther König, 1999.
Elaine Scarry, Resisting Representation,
David Sedley (ed.), The Cambridge
sity Press, 2008. Hans Sluga and David G. Stern (eds.),
Wolfgang Tillmans, Burg, Cologne, Taschen, 1998.
New York/Oxford, Oxford University
Companion to Greek and Roman Phi-
Press, 1994.
losophy, Cambridge, Cambridge Uni-
and Films, Ann Arbor/London, UMI
Zdenek Felix, Ostfildern, Hatje Cantz,
versity Press, 2003.
Research Press, 1986.
2001.
Elaine Scarry, On Beauty and Being Just, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1999.
David Sedley, ‘Hellenistic physics and metaphysics’, in: Keimpe Algra, Jona-
Patrick S. Smith, Andy Warhol’s Art
Stephen Snyder, Pier Paolo Pasolini, Boston, Twayne, 1980.
Elaine Scarry, Dreaming by the Book,
than Barnes, Jaap Mansfeld and Mal-
Princeton, Princeton University Press,
colm Schofield (eds.), The Cambridge
London, Thames and Hudson/British
2001.
History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cam-
Film Institute, 1969.
Simon Schama, Landscape and Memory [1995], New York, Vintage, 1996. Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, System des transzendentalen Idealis-
bridge, Cambridge University Press, 2005, p. 355-411. Richard Sennett, The Craftsman [2008], Harmondsworth, Penguin, 2009.
mus [1800], edited by Horst D. Brandt
Mary Shelley, Frankenstein, or, The
and Peter Müller with an introduction by Walter Schulz and notes by Walter E. Ehrhardt, Hamburg, Meiner, 2000.
Hindle, Harmondsworth, Penguin,
Friedrich Schiller, Über die ästhetische Erziehung des Menschen in einer Reihe
Oswald Stack, Pasolini on Pasolini,
Wolfgang Tillmans, Aufsicht, edited by
Wolfgang Tillmans, truth study center, Cologne, Taschen, 2005. Wolfgang Tillmans, Lighter, Ostfildern, Hatje Cantz, 2008. Cathal Tohill and Pete Tombs, Immoral
Alan Stanbrook, ‘Is God In Showbusi-
Tales. European Sex and Horror Mov-
ness Too?’, in: Sight and Sound, Vol. 59,
ies 1956-1984, New York, St. Martin’s
Nr. 4, Fall 1990, p. 259-263.
Griffin, 1995.
Jack Stevenson (ed.), Fleshpot. Cin-
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Tijgers Tem-
ema’s Sexual Myth makers & Taboo
men. Voor een Cinema van de Traa-
Modern Prometheus, edited with an
Breakers, second edition, Manchester,
gheid’, in: Cinemagie, Nr. 251, Summer
introduction and notes by Maurice
Headpress, 2002.
2005a, p. 5-10.
1992. Roy Sherwood, ‘John Boorman’, in:
von Briefen. Mit den Augustenburger
John Wakeman (ed.), World Film Direc-
Briefen, edited by Klaus L. Berghahn,
tors. Volume II: 1945-1985, New York,
Philip Strick, ‘Zardoz and John Boor-
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Lust Wil
man’, in: Sight and Sound, Vol. 43, Nr. 2,
Eeuwigheid. Een Metafysica van het
Spring 1974, p. 73-77.
Gluren’, in: Streven, Vol. 72, Nr. 9, Octo-
David Sylvester, The Brutality of Fact. Interviews with Francis Bacon, enlarged
ber 2005b, p. 783-794. Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Cinetrauma.
493
Ontreddering is een Plek naar Ner-
MENT%20-%20Christophe%20Van%20
gens’, in: rekto:verso, Nr. 17, May-June
Eecke.pdf)
2006a, p. 10. Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Begeestering. Manifest voor een Nieuwe Kunstkritiek’, in: rekto:verso, Nr. 18, July-August 2006b, p. 10-11. Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Andy Warhol’,
Fragment, Breda, Lokaal 01, 2009e (http://www.lokaal01.nl/actueel/pdf/ ABSOLUTEBEGINNINGSdefinitief.pdf). Christophe Van Eecke, Stock Footage
in: Cinemagie, Nr. 256, Fall 2006c, p.
& Shock Tactics. Marx, Eisenstein and
73-84.
Filming ‘Capital’, Breda, Lokaal 01, 2009f
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Arendtsogen. Over de Verbeelding van Geweld’, in: Streven, Vol. 74, Nr. 2, February 2007a, p. 114-124. Christophe Van Eecke, ‘De Mythen van een Late Pasolini’, in: Cinemagie, Nr. 259, Summer 2007b, p. 73-89.
494
Christophe Van Eecke, Absolute Beginnings. Detours Towards a History of the
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Nel Mezzo del
(http://www.lokaal01.nl/actueel/pdf/ STOCKFOOTAGEdefinitief.pdf). Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Vlees is het Taaiste. Kleine Fenomenologie van The
New York/London, Harvest/Harcourt
Press, 2002.
Brace & Company, 1990. Marina Warner, Fantastic Metamorphoses, Other Worlds. Ways of Telling the Self, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2002. Tracey Warr (ed.), The Artist’s Body, London, Phaidon, 2000. Steven Watson, Factory Made. Warhol
Tomalin, Oxford/New York, Oxford University Press, 1992.
Lawrence Weschler, True to life.
p. 49-53.
Dream. De Herinneringscinema van
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘De Kelder van
London, University of California Press, 2008. Mark Wigley, ‘The Space of Exposure’, in: Russell Ferguson and Dominic Molon (eds.), Wolfgang Tillmans, Los Angeles/Chicago/New Haven/London, Hammer Museum/Museum of Con-
Tarr’, in: Cinemagie, Nr. 266, Spring
2010b, p. 13.
temporary Art/Yale University Press,
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Mad Caps and
2006, p. 145-156. Oscar Wilde, Plays, Prose Writings and
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Lijnen Van
Flowered Cups. Some Notes on Seeing
Geleidelijkheid’, in: Kris Van Dessel
Regula Maria Müller’s Work’, in: Regula
Poems, with an introduction by Terry
(ed.), Drawing Actions, exhib. cat., Geel,
Maria Müller, De Muzen van Erasmus/
Eagleton, London, Everyman’s Library,
De halle, 2009b, [p. 2-7].
The Muses of Erasmus, s.l., RTBOOKS,
1991.
2010c, [p. 1-3].
Linda Williams, Hard Core. Power,
And Radiate. De Verloren Talen van de
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Zij Cool, Wij
Pleasure and the “Frenzy of the Visible”
Dia’, in: rekto:verso, Nr. 36, July-August
Cool. De Kinderen van Larry Clark’, in:
[1989], expanded edition, Berkeley/Los
2009c, p. 22.
Metropolis M, Vol. 31, Nr. 3, June-July
Angeles/London, University of Califor-
2010d, p. 38-47 (English translation, p.
nia Press, 1999.
(http://www.lokaal01.nl/actueel/ pdf/DISPLACEMENT%20THISPLACE-
Dan Yakir, ‘The Sorcerer’, in: Film
David Hockney, Berkeley/Los Angeles/
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Perchance To
geten’, in: rekto:verso, Nr. 41, May-June
Moderne Kunst, Breda, Lokaal 01, 2009d
Virginia Woolf, Mrs Dalloway [1925], edited with an introduction by Claire
Books, 2003.
Het Demonische Universum van Béla
This Placement. Het Standpunt in de
New York, Knopf, 2002.
and the Sixties, New York, Pantheon
Kruithof. Verzamelen Tegen het Ver-
Christophe Van Eecke, Displacement/
Gaby Wood, Edison’s Eve. A Magical History of the Quest for Mechanical Life,
269, Winter 2009g, p. 37-47.
January-February 2010a, p. 5-6.
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Fade Away
1996.
Comment, Vol. 17, Nr. 3, May-June 1981,
Film’, in: Cinemagie, Nr. 265, Winter
2009a, p. 46-53.
Roger Wollen (ed.), Derek Jarman: A Portrait, London, Thames and Hudson,
Twenty-five years of conversations with
Terence Davies’, in: rekto:verso, Nr. 39,
Christophe Van Eecke, ‘Verdoemenis.
Jonathan Wolff, Why Read Marx Today?, Oxford, Oxford University
Wrestler en Hunger’, in: Cinemagie, Nr.
Camin. Moeilijke Mannelijkheid in de 2008, p. 25-36.
Andy Warhol and Pat Hackett, POPism. The Warhol ‘60s [1980], San Diego/
105-107). Lea Vergine, Body Art and Performance.
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus logicophilosophicus. Logisch-philosophische
The Body as Language, Milan, Skira,
Abhandlung [1921], Frankfurt am Main,
2000.
Suhrkamp, 1963.
495
Only Connect is een uitgave van Lokaal 01 en is verschenen naar aanleiding van de tentoonstelling Pleasure Ground (25 februari – 18 juni 2010) Tekst Christophe Van Eecke Vormgeving M/vG ontwerpers, Berry van Gerwen, Breda Druk Gianotten, Tilburg oplage 500 ISBN 978-90-811954-7-8 Niets uit deze uitgave mag openbaar gemaakt worden of verveelvuidigd zonder voorafgaande schriftelijke toestemming van de uitgever, kunstenaars en auteurs.
496
Lokaal 01_Breda Kloosterlaan 138 4811 EE Breda +31 (0)76 514 1928 breda@lokaal01.org www.lokaal01.org Š Lokaal 01, 2011