Booka

Page 1

Past & Present: philosophy for everyone

Edited by Stephen Law




Past & Present: philosophy for everyone Edited by Stephen Law Š 2014 Cambridge University Press Designed by Victoria Kleymenova Typeset in Minion Pro and Franklin Gothic by ..., London Printed in Falmouth, UK The Royal Institute of Philosophy 14 Gordon Square London WC1H 0AR United Kingdom T. 020 7387 4130 www.royalinstitutephilosophy.org


Past & Present: philosophy for everyone

Edited by Stephen Law


6

“

The reasonable man adapts himself to the world: the unreasonable one persists in trying to adapt the world to himself. Therefore all progress depends on the unreasonable man. George Bernard Shaw


7

Foreword The dominant view nowadays is that the philosophy of nature no longer exists. That branch of philosophy died out with the emergence of the modern empirical sciences. Its domain of inquiry was divided among the various particular sciences. Admittedly, there are still some philosophers who try to cultivate a philosophy of nature, but when one takes a closer look at their work it turns out that most of their effort is devoted to defining what exactly the philosophy of nature is supposed to study. The philosophy of nature as traditionally understood only prepared the ground for the future natural sciences and at their emergence lost its reason for being. Does that mean the elimination of philosophy from science? Not at all. In the first place, the very existence of science is a fact which requires philosophical reflection. That task was taken up by the philosophy of science. That branch of philosophy is flourishing and, just as happens with any respectable science, has many schools and specializations - from research into the kind of rationality represented by various sciences and the logic of the development of scientific theories, through analysis of the methods used by various sciences, to specialized analytic research into those aspects of scientific theories which the sciences themselves cannot handle. Does that exhaust the tasks which philosophy must fulfill in relation to science?


Introduction Stephen Law

Biographies 011

Ian James Kidd

000

Christine Korsgaard

000

Tyler Burge

000

Thomas Nagel

000

Derek Parfit

000

John Searle

000

Mary Warnock

000

Jerry Fodor

000

Ned Block

000

Derek Parfit

000

Bernard Williams

000

J端rgen Habermas

000

Anthony Kenny

000

Simon Blackburn

000

Noam Chomsky

000

John McDowell

000

T. M. Scanlon

000


Morals & Intentions Christine Korsgaard

Religion & Society 000

Personhood, Animals,

Ian James Kidd

Mind & Body 000

Humility And History

000

Conceiving the Impossible

And The Law

and the Mind-Body Problem Alasdair MacIntyre

Simon Blackburn

Thomas Nagel

000

The Sovereignty of Reason

000

Social Structures and their

Mary Warnock

threats to Moral Agency

What is Natural and

000

Should We Care About It? John Searle

000

Bernard Williams

000

Freedom of the Will as a

Philosophy as a Humanist

Jerry Fodor

Problem in Neurobiology

Discipline

Mental Representation

000

without Conceptualization Noam Chomsky

000

J端rgen Habermas

000

Some Thoughts on Terror,

The Pacemaker for

Ned Block

Justice and Self-defence

Cultural Rights

Attention and Mentalism

John McDowell

000

Intention in Action T. M. Scanlon Reassessing Reasons

Anthony Kenny

000

Derek Parfit

Is Religion Really the Root of

Is Personal Identity

all Evil?

what matters?

000

000

000 Tyler Burge Perception: Where Mind Begins

000


10

“

Don’t bite off more than you can chew because nobody looks attractive spitting it back out... Carroll Bryant


11

Introduction The dominant view nowadays is that the philosophy of nature no

then the natural sciences arose and liquidated the place of philosophy

longer exists. That branch of philosophy died out with the emergence

in science is a crude oversimplification of the historical process. The

of the modern empirical sciences. Its domain of inquiry was divided

natural sciences did not arise on the ruins of the philosophy of nature.

among the various particular sciences. Admittedly, there are still some

They existed in parallel to it, though they were not always explicitly

philosophers who try to cultivate a philosophy of nature, but when one

separated from it. It is sufficient to name the Greek sciences:

takes a closer look at their work it turns out that most of their effort is

astronomy, optics, acoustics, statics, not to mention geometry. One

devoted to defining what exactly the philosophy of nature is supposed

can only speak of a period of the domination of the philosophy of

to study. The philosophy of nature as traditionally understood only

nature over the sciences until the beginning of the modern period,

prepared the ground for the future natural sciences and at their

after which one must speak of the period of the domination of the

emergence lost its reason for being. Does that mean the elimination

sciences. The transition between those two periods was a continuous

of philosophy from science? Not at all. In the first place, the very

transition, although one rich in dramatic tensions. Notice how

existence of science is a fact which requires philosophical reflection.

many typically philosophical problems were found in the spheres of

That task was taken up by the philosophy of science. That branch of

interest of various scientific theories. The problems of time, space, and

philosophy is flourishing and, just as happens with any respectable

causality will serve as typical examples. Right down to our own day

science, has many schools and specializations - from research into the

they are thought of as “great problems of philosophy” though at the

kind of rationality represented by various sciences and the logic of the

same time all the fundamental theories of physics have much to say on

development of scientific theories, through analysis of the methods

these topics.

used by various sciences, to specialized analytic research into those

It is of course true that when some problem migrates from

aspects of scientific theories which the sciences themselves cannot

philosophy to the empirical sciences, it thereby changes its

handle.

significance. We know that context is just as important as the

Does that exhaust the tasks which philosophy must fulfill in relation

“internal” connections between concepts. What is more, the problems

to science? In answering that question, let us appeal to history. Above

and concepts transformed by the migration from philosophy to the

all, the statement that first there was the philosophy of nature and

sciences often come back for further philosophical deliberation, in that


12

way thickening the connections between the two realms of knowledge.

in typescript through the kindness of Professor Ladrière, were of

The strengthening of that connection creates an interesting field of

invaluable assistance to me.

investigation. I have called it “philosophy in science,” no doubt a

The many references to Professor Ladrière’s notes in the text

summary expression and one which includes only some aspects of

of this book indicate my debt to him only partially. However, my

the phenomena which interests us here, but I hope that the entire

own series of lectures is not a copy of the lectures given in Louvain.

book will constitute a justification for it. As I have already noted, the

Professor Ladrière concentrated his attention principally on one

history of science itself bears witness to the presence in science of

problem, namely, on the relation of physics to metaphysics in the most

philosophical threads and it is for that reason that I have to write this

important systems of the philosophy of nature.

book from a philosophical point of view. That does not mean that the study of philosophy in science has

That is indeed one of the key problems, but I decided to go beyond that problem, and to undertake a more comprehensive discussion of

to limit itself to purely historical considerations; it means only that

the particular systems. As a result, the more focused formulation of

historical considerations seem to be an indispensable element of a

Professor Ladrière has, in my book, become a more general series of

strategy which would allow us to see the philosophical significance of

lectures. That has manifested itself also in the method of the lectures.

the sciences. In my opinion, a thorough knowledge of at least the most

Professor Ladrière limited himself to a discussion of the relation

important trends which have appeared in the history of philosophy

between physics and metaphysics in Aristotle, Descartes, Leibniz,

and science is a necessary condition of a responsible research program

Kant, and Whitehead. I have supplemented that account with a look

in the area of contemporary philosophico-scientific problems, and

at Plato, Newton, Popper and the so-called Romantic philosophy of

at the same time is an indispensable minimum of knowledge for the

nature. I also added a chapter on Aristotle’s treatise On the Heavens

researcher working in other areas of philosophy. I borrowed the idea

and a chapter discussing the philosophical themes in contemporary

of developing a series of lectures around the most important figures

science.

and themes from the history of place of philosophy in science from Professor Jean Ladrière, who gave such a series of lectures at the Institut Supérieur de Philosophie of the University of Louvain in 1982–1983. The unpublished notes from those lectures, made available

Introduction

Stephen Law


13

Human beings are born into this little span of life of which the best thing is its friendship and intimacies, and soon their places will know them no more, and yet they leave their friendships and intimacies with no cultivation, to grow as they will by the roadside, expecting them to “keep” by force of inertia. William James


“

He who thinks great thoughts, often makes great errors Martin Heidegger


Morals & Intentions

/01


16

Humility and History by Ian James Kidd

Philosophy is an ancient subject, but what is the value of an understanding of its history for its practice? What can contemporary philosophers draw from an historical understanding of their subject? I argue that amongst its many benefits, the history of philosophy is an excellent resource for the cultivation of certain intellectual virtues1, most notably gratitude, humility, and justice. Acquaintance with the history of philosophy can, therefore, be edifying, in the sense of being conducive to

to sustain vigorous, dynamic traditions. Indeed, one striking fact evidenced by history is the ubiquity2 of philosophical reflection. Across the scope of human cultures, in different times and climes, one finds sustained philosophical reflection, on topics ranging from knowledge and justice, to society and education, to reality and meaning. Although philosophy, like any subject, has its ‘boom and bust’ periods, recent scholarship indicates that even periods previously considered to be rather barren – such as the ‘Dark Ages’ of medieval Europe – were, in fact, philosophically dynamic, even if their questions and problems reflected concerns rather different from ours. The fact

the cultivation and exercise of virtues. These virtues can be cultivated in many ways, but the history of philosophy offers unique means for securing those virtues just mentioned – or so I will argue. In what follows, I hope to show that some familiar pedagogical and intellectual uses of the history of philosophy in fact reflect its edifying functions. The origins of philosophy are unclear, but certainly there were, in Greece, India, and China, vigorous philosophical traditions by the sixth to fifth centuries BCE. Indeed, it is possible that Confucius, the Buddha, Thales and the authors of the Upanisads may have been contemporaries. The last six thousand years have, of course, seen philosophy, both ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’, go on

of the historical ubiquity of philosophy of course pleases those engaged in the ‘business’ of philosophy today. Certainly philosophers, whether professional or lay, should find a legitimate sense of pride in their participation in a venerable3 tradition of thought. This should include an appreciation of the sincere and sustained efforts, by men and women historically and culturally distant from us, to articulate ideas about their place in the ‘order of things’, which we may, today, profitably draw upon. And there isn’t, one hopes, too much vainglory4 in the optimistic sentiment5 that philosophy has been, and continues to be, an ennobling6 feature of human life. Although such sentiments have their place, the history of

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


17

1. Virtue - behavior showing high moral standards. 2. Ubiquity - the state or capacity of being everywhere, especially at the same time. 3. Venerableness - Commanding respect by virtue of age, dignity, character, or position; honorableness.

philosophy surely offers us more than just a sense of pride of one’s place within a venerable tradition. Those things matter, if only to motivate, but the value of the history of philosophy should not be narrowly construed7 as a capacity to encourage young philosophers – those sitting through hard going undergraduate lectures on Kant, say – to ‘keep at it’ and work hard. A sense of ‘standing on the shoulders of giants’, to borrow Newton’s handy phrase, is useful. But so, too, is one’s knowing something about those ‘giants’ and about how, and why, they worked and wondered as they did. In the history of philosophy, these ‘giants’ would be all those earlier thinkers whose work is now part of our shared history. Some of the giants are obvious and familiar, such as Plato or the Buddha, whereas others, like Nāgārjuna or Josiah Royce, remain reliably obscure, at least within certain areas of academic philosophy. Both familiarity and obscurity can be fickle things, of course. Some philosophical giants are prominent for their notoriety, like Nietzsche, and others for their accessibility, like Russell. But what does it mean to say that these figures, and others more like them, are part of a ‘shared history’, and how and why does that history matter? The significance of the history of philosophy turns on the answer to that question. Certainly there are many reasons

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

4. Vainglory - inordinate pride in oneself or one’s achievements; excessive vanity. 5. Sentiment - a view of or attitude toward a situation or event; an opinion. 6. Ennoble - to make noble. 7. Construe - to interpret (a word or action) in a particular way.

why one might not want to teach philosophy in a historical manner. One might prefer, for instance, to teach or write about philosophy in terms of ‘problems’ or discrete ‘areas’, like ‘Metaphysics’, ‘Consciousness’, or ‘Topics in Philosophy of Science’. This way of philosophising focuses on topics, issues, and themes, like the nature of time, mental causation, or scientific methodology. And that can be a valuable and effective way of ‘doing’ philosophy, especially within the context of the structure of modern universities.

That man is wisest who, like Socrates, realizes that his wisdom is worthless Plato

Yet a focus on abstract argument divorced from concrete context does, at least sometimes, compromise one’s understanding and appreciation of the ideas and problems being discussed. One could, for instance, take a course on ‘Knowledge and Scepticism’, covering Pyrrho, Descartes, Kant and others, without ever detailing why, for each of those figures, questions about knowledge and scepticism mattered.

Ian James Kidd


18

1. Inherent - existing in something as a permanent, essential, or characteristic attribute. 2. Suffice - to be enough or adequate.

4. Presocratics - a pre-Socratic philosopher. 5. Reform - make changes in (something, typically a social, political, or economic institution or practice) in order to improve it.

3. Axiom - a statement or proposition that is regarded as being established, accepted, or self-evidently true.

An appeal to the inherent1 fascination or trickiness of their questions usually suffices2, at least for those who opt to take such courses, but often those questions are presented without a clear account of why those philosophers were troubled by them. Most philosophers, at least in the past, were troubled by philosophical questions not simply out of mere curiosity, but rather because they perceived that those questions, even the most abstract ones, had implications for aspects of life which mattered to them. Such concerns are easily to neglect. A philosopher’s ‘position’ can be summarised as an argument, or a series of bullet-points on a PowerPoint slide, but this format is apt to neglect the vital concerns that animated them. For instance, it often tends to obscure the biographical and historical context of a philosopher’s life, reducing them to names and dates, of the form ‘Thomas Hobbes (1588– 1679)’.

for sure – and not solely in the life of Ludwig Wittgenstein – but the value of historical context goes further than that. Showing the wider

social and political conditions within which philosophers worked, worried and wondered can help us to appreciate their ‘practical’ objectives.

Excellence is never an accident. It is always the result of high intention, sincere effort, and intelligent execution; it represents the wise choice of many alternatives - choice, not chance, determines your destiny. Aristotle

The Presocratics4 offer interesting arguments against traditional

Where, after all, is the contextual richness of a biography such as that

Greek religion, but they were, ultimately, intended to facilitate

which Heidegger offered for Aristotle: ‘he was born . . . he worked,

social and political reform5. Or to take a slightly later example, the

and . . . he died’. Heidegger may have been right that, for certain

Pyrrhonian6 sceptics did not engage in abstract epistemology7, asking

purposes, Aristotle’s biography is not ‘of interest’, but that fact is only

abstruse8 questions about the nature of knowledge, just because they

true at a certain level of analysis. Certainly it is not a general axiom3

were interested. Rather, it was because they perceived that a person

of philosophizing. Context is not only pedagogically or interpretively

who is to be happy must understand, first, what things are like and,

valuable. There are entertaining anecdotes in the history of philosophy,

second, how one should be disposed towards them. Put another

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


19

6. Pyrrhonian - Pyrrhonism, or Pyrrhonian skepticism, was a school of skepticism founded by Aenesidemus in the 1st century BC and recorded by Sextus Empiricus in the late 2nd century or early 3rd

8. from opinion. Abstruse - difficult to understand; obscure. 9. Derisive - expressing contempt or ridicule, sarcasm. 10. Perennial - lasting or existing for a long or apparently infinite time;

century AD. 7. Epistemology - the investigation of what distinguishes justified belief

enduring or continually recurring.

way, they thought that knowledge of things was essential if we are

they return, each generation, often in evolving forms. Questions about

to act properly regarding them, therefore interlinking epistemology

beauty and art, justice and goodness, knowledge and certainty, and

and ethics in a way that will, one worries, remain invisible if one

the like have featured within the public and private lives of human

concentrated simply on the arguments themselves. Many derisive9

beings across all times and cultures. A historical understanding of

assessments of the value of philosophy arise because, in many

the philosophers that responded to them can help us, today, in our

cases, those critics do not see how the ‘abstract’ issues raised by the

own efforts to address them. The history of philosophy is, therefore, a

philosophically-minded bear on ‘practical’ issues. The fault may

feature of philosophising itself.

be shared, but it can, I think, be partially resolved by an historical

To ask and address philosophical questions is to enter into a

perspective upon philosophy. Once one becomes accustomed to a

longstanding tradition of inquiry. The specific content and form of

historical articulation of philosophy, the task of providing accounts of

philosophical questions changes over time, of course, in response

the ‘practical’ import of ‘abstract’ philosophising should become much

to changing social and intellectual conditions. Questions about the

easier. By being able to explain how earlier philosophers came to their

certainty of knowledge, say, were changed by the development of

ideas, or what provoked their questions, it should become easier for us

the modern sciences. But appreciating this involves an historical

to do the same for our own inquiries. And this should be understood,

sensitivity. It requires us to look not only at earlier philosophers

not as ‘accounting for ourselves’, but, rather, as explaining ourselves,

who asked similar questions, but also at the context within which

for our benefit, and for that of our critics. Certainly a knowledge and

those questions were asked. After all, it is often context which lends

appreciation of the history of philosophy can be a valuable feature of

our questions urgency, vitality, and significance. There are many

the actual practice of philosophy. An understanding of philosophy

philosophical questions and puzzles, but which ones matter to us, and

as an historical discipline shows how it is bound up with social and

why, is as much a matter of history as it is of curiosity and inquiry.

political change, religious controversy, scientific innovation, and so

The role of history in shaping our own ideas points to another role

on. Those sorts of issues are, of course, features of our world today;

for the history of philosophy. Many questions face us, but not all of

indeed, many philosophical questions are perennial in the sense that

them matter to us. Certain questions move us, either by disturbing

10

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


20

1. Genealogy - a record or account of the ancestry and descent of a person, family, group, etc. 2. Salience - prominent or conspicuous.

4. Haecceity - a term from medieval scholastic philosophy, first coined by Duns Scotus, which denotes the discrete qualities, properties or characteristics of a thing which make it a particular thing.

3. Flux - a flowing or flow. * for further biography see last page of transcript

or fascinating us (or, indeed, both). Other questions are curiosities –

I think, because its questions and concerns are not usually of the sort

interesting, but deemed neither urgent nor essential. Understanding

of invite historical input. The salience2 of history depends upon the

the distribution of significance across the philosophical landscape

questions being asked and the kind of answers one is seeking. My

will, again, require a historical perspective. After all, we are ourselves

emphasis on the role of the history of philosophy is directed at those

subjects of a history. To ape Nietzsche’s* famous remark, when we

with more vital, ‘practical’ concerns. The refinement of a complex

stare into history, history also stares back into us, insofar as the

argument about logical relations might not invite historical reflection;

concerns and issues of contemporary society are products, at least in

but questions about the nature of ‘the good life’, for instance, surely are,

part, of that society’s history – that is, of our history. Such a reflexive

for the reason that it is questions of this sort that are perennial, which

historical stance is, of course, only useful beyond a certain point.

appear across different cultures and generations. And it is, I suspect,

We can get on much of the business of philosophising, debating and

such ‘big questions’ which command the interest and attention of

arguing without ever engaging in the historical project of tracing what

most of those drawn to philosophy. It is these questions, and the richer

Nietzsche called the ‘genealogy1’ of our questions and methods. But

conception of philosophy they reflect, which Kant had in mind when

that point at which history becomes essential is, I think, reached far

he wrote of the ‘cosmopolitan sense’ in philosophy, which issues in

sooner than is often imagined. Beyond a certain point, philosophical

four questions: ‘What can I know? What ought I to do? What may I

understanding must, if it is to satisfy us, become historically sensitive.

hope? What is man?’ The history of philosophy, then, is an essential

This would include an understanding of how and why those questions

feature of a certain broad conception of philosophy. It may be called

came down to us, what presuppositions must be in place to enable

cosmopolitan, after Kant, or ‘humanistic’, after Bernard Williams,

our inquiries, and of why those questions and their answers matter to

or it may be judged, following Pierre Hadot, as a series of ‘spiritual

us. A great deal of valuable philosophical work can proceed without

exercises’ manifesting in a certain ‘way of life’. Whatever its name, it

the sort of historical understanding just described. A philosopher

is a conception of philosophy focused upon questions and concerns

would be foolish to pursue a historical perspective where that would

of vital importance to thinking, reflective human beings: questions

neither aid nor complement their concerns. Analytic philosophy, for

of beauty, meaning, goodness, and the like, where these questions are

instance, is often said to be largely ‘ahistorical’, but that is most often,

understood, not as exercises in conceptual ingenuity, but as essential

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


21

5. Mind-body dualism - In philosophy of mind, dualism is the position

8. Cartesian dualism - Descartes’ concept of dualism. 9. Presuppositions - a thing tacitly assumed beforehand at the beginning

that mental phenomena are, in some respects, non-physical, or that the mind and body are not identical.

of a line of argument or course of action.

6. Iconoclasm - the forceful opposition to the veneration of inanimate

10. (Margaret) Thatcher - UK. prime minister (1979-1990).

7. Representations, religious icons, and other symbols or monuments.

components of one’s practical activities within the world. These

commitments today’.

questions are certainly not absent from ahistorical philosophising,

Such a historical conception should also help protect philosophy

but arguably they may be better served by an historical approach.

from certain persistent and ill-informed challenges to it. Those who

Abstract reflection has a part to play in articulating and addressing

object that philosophy is ‘abstract’ and ‘detached’ often, I suspect, have

these questions, but often they cannot be fully appreciated, or

certain caricatures of contemporary academic philosophy in mind.

answered, without an historical appreciation of those earlier

Certainly successive British Governments since Thatcher9 seem to have

generations of philosophers who, troubled by similar worries, offered

shared that view, the present one included. Other philosophers have

their own responses.

also expressed worries about the deleterious impact of certain features

Sensitivity to the history of philosophy therefore offers resources for understanding that may be unavailable to those who forsake context

inquiry.

for raw argument. By neglecting the context of philosophical inquiry, one deprives many problems of their urgency and salience. Earlier philosophers, stripped of context, may seem peculiar, even perverse, for persisting in abstruse intellectual inquiries – about flux , haeccities , 3

4

mind-body dualism5, and the like. However to accuse them thus does

Every man is a creature of the age in which he lives and few are able to raise themselves above the ideas of the time

them an injustice, and indicates, at the same time, our own ignorance. Once Cynic iconoclasm6, say, or Cartesian7 dualism is located within

of academic philosophy upon the genuine pursuit of philosophical

Voltaire

its proper intellectual and historical context, their urgency and

However, the objection that philosophy is detached is invalid

salience may be clarified and amplified. The result is, argue two recent

because it relies upon a false conception of philosophy. That image of

writers, ‘the maturing of a kind of modesty or humility’, an ‘increased

philosophy – as detached, abstract speculation, isolated from a practical

perception’ not only of the ‘presuppositions and prejudices of earlier

context – would certainly make it difficult to see what, if anything, those

eras’, but also an increased capacity, on our own part, to ‘expose similar

speculations had to do with the world. However that conception of

presuppositions and prejudices that may be shaping beliefs and

philosophy is dependent upon an ahistorical approach to the subject,

8

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


22

1. Hubris - excessive pride or self-confidence.

5. Impoverished - poor, weakened.

2. Predilections - a preference or special liking for something;

a bias in favor of something. 3. Parochial - of or relating to a church parish. 4. Prefigure - to show or represent beforehand by a figure or type.

one which strips it of context and isolates it from those ‘real-world’

badly upon us, especially if, as d’Alembert reminds us, we are but a

concerns which animate it. Reaffirming the contextual and historical

‘passing generation’, our concerns being, perhaps, ‘nothing for the

nature of philosophy should also help to insure us against various vices.

next one, still less for distant posterity’. Once a historical approach to

The awareness that our problems are not new and that earlier

philosophy is in place, that impoverished5 view of philosophy – and

generations also encountered them should encourage a certain

the stereotypes it sponsors, of philosophers as intellectual narcissists

humility on our own part. Only presentist hubris could persuade us

preoccupied with their own uncertainties, say – should dissolve.

1

that our predilections – our anxieties and insights – are privileged 2

There is a place for abstract reflection, for sure, but philosophy is,

guides to the nature of reality. An appreciation of context should, one

for many, necessarily rooted in the practical concerns of human beings

hopes, indicate that our anxieties and insights arise from ideas and

who are, themselves, subjects of a history. Understanding that history

developments which are not wholly of our making. Our achievements

will not only illuminate our contemporary concerns, but, one hopes,

are, therefore, not ours alone. At the least, we owe a debt to both

also renew our appreciation of philosophy. Our participation in that

the errors and the insights of earlier generations, a debt which an

history will, at the least, enable us to do justice to those who came

understanding of the history of philosophy can help to make apparent.

before, and hopefully enable us to endow future generations, as best we

There is ignorance, injustice and also ingratitude in the attitudes of

can, with ideas which, in time, may be of use to those who follow us.

those who deride the value of philosophy whilst living within a society

At the very least, such historical philosophising brings with it a set of

so shaped by it. Voltaire urged us, when considering our history,

intellectual virtues – gratitude, humility, and justice – which lend it a

to admire those who ‘first brought us to the path of truth’ as much

moral as well as an intellectual significance.

as those ‘who afterwards conducted us through it’. To cherry-pick from the history of philosophy those figures whose views prefigure3 ours smacks of what historians of science call ‘Whig history’: a neglect of the role of critics, rival schools and the like in shaping the ideas that, from a parochial4 perspective, ‘won’ in the end. Failure to acknowledge those who brought us to our current path reflects

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


23

Meet & Greet

*

Find out more about selected philosophers who starred in the transcript

Friedrich Nietzsche 1844-1900

Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was a German philosopher of the

and intoxication, the other one of order and the lending of form.

late 19th century who challenged the foundations of Christianity

These Nietzsche associated with an aesthetic disposition in which

and traditional morality. He was interested in the enhancement of

life be viewed as a work of art. He demonstrated that the Greeks had

individual and cultural health, and believed in life, creativity, power,

theorized the relation of the two principles in which art is a willed

and the realities of the world we live in, rather than those situated

illusion and is composed of both form-giving and intoxication, and

in a world beyond. Central to his philosophy is the idea of “life-

thus, art offers one a vantage point of life. Therefore, life itself becomes

affirmation,” which involves an honest questioning of all doctrines

recognizable as unknowable in terms of an ultimate truth, as proposed

that drain life’s expansive energies, however socially prevalent those

by an idealist metaphysics.

views might be. Often referred to as one of the first existentialist philosophers along with Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855), Nietzsche’s revitalizing philosophy has inspired leading figures in all walks of

Notable work/

cultural life, including dancers, poets, novelists, painters, psychologists, philosophers, sociologists and social revolutionaries. In his first published book, Die Geburt der Tragödie aus dem Geist

The Birth of Tragedy (published in 1872) Human, All Too Human (completed in 1879)

der Musik (The Birth of Tragedy), he diagnosed that human beings

Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1885)

are subject to Dionysian instincts — unconscious desires, impulses,

Beyond Good and Evil (1886)

or overwhelmingly self-destructive tendencies. Nietzsche pointed out

The Antichrist (1888)

that the Greeks had opposed Apollonian principles of sobriety and rationale to such destructive drives. These became to major principles in his future work, the Dionysian and Apollonian, one of chaos, dream

Meet & Greet

Friedrich Nietzche


24

Ian James Kidd

About Born: 02/04/1982

Papers Origin: Lousiana, U.S.

Doing Science An Injustice: Midgley on Scientism Educating for Intellectual Humility

Works in epistemology, philosophy of medicine, philosophy

Nature, Mystery, and Morality: A Daoist View

of religion, history and philosophy of science, and the

Epistemic Injustice in Healthcare: A Philosophical Analysis

philosophical traditions of Asia and Continental Europe.

Doing Away With Scientism Feyerabend on Politics, Education, and Scientific Culture

Epistemic virtues and vices (especially epistemic injustice

Phenomenology, Psychiatric Illness, and Religious Commitment

and epistemic humility); the experience and value of illness;

Feyerabend on Science and Education

the nature of a religious life; contingency and pluralism

Was Sir William Crookes Epistemically Virtuous?

in science; scientism and anti-scientism; the practice and

Reappraising Feyerabend

nature of philosophy; and the life and thought of Paul

Transformative Suffering and the Cultivation of Virtue

Feyerabend.

History and Humility Emotion, Religious Practice, and Cosmopolitan Secularism

Founded the Durham Philosophy Department’s Gender Action Group and is committed to improving the representation of women in philosophy, and is also involved with the Leeds University chapter of Minorities in Philosophy (MAP).

Biographies

Ian James Kidd


25

Talks Illness, Virtue, and Exemplarist Ethics

Religious Beauties

Location: University of Leeds

Time: 11 AM to 1 AM

Event Date: Feb 25, 2015

Location: University of Leeds

Organization: Centre for Ethics

Event Date: Nov 20, 2014 Organization: Centre for the Philosophy of Religion

Learning from the Best: Ethical Exemplarism in Confucius’ 'Analects'

Books

Location: University of Durham Event Date: Jan 21, 2015

Science and the Self: Animals, Evolution, and Ethics:

Organization: Durham University Philosophical Society

Essays in Honour of Mary Midgley

'World Philosophies' series

co-edited with Elizabeth McKinnell Publisher: London: Routledge

Epistemic Injustice and Religious Experience Location: Durham University

The Routledge Handbook to Epistemic Injustice

Event Date: 2015

co-edited with José Medina and Gaile Pohlhaus

Organization: Epistemic Injustice and the Philosophy of Religion

Publisher: London: Routledge

Experiences of Illness and Narratives of Edification

Historiography and the Philosophy of the Sciences

Location: University of Bristol

co-edited with Robin Hendry

Event Date: Jul 9, 2013

Publisher: special section of Studies in History and

Organization: Illness, Narrative, Phenomenology

Philosophy of Science

Anthropogenic Climate Change, Humility, and ‘Epistemic Activism’

Reappraising Feyerabend

Event Date: Oct 31, 2014

(co-edited with Matthew Brown, UT Dallas, in preparation as a

Organization: Philosophy and Public Policy:

special issue of Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2013)

Philosophical Activism III Mystery and Humility Confidence, Humility, and Philosophy

(co-edited with Guy Bennett-Hunter, Durham)

Location: EIDOS Durham University

European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 40/3 (2012).

Event Date: Jun 17, 2014

Biographies

Ian James Kidd





Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.