Kleymenova victoria typo publication

Page 1

Past & Present: Philosophy for everyone by Stephen Law




Past & Present: Philosophy for Everyone Edited by Stephen Law Š 2014 Cambridge University Press Designed by Victoria Kleymenova Typeset in Minion Pro and Proxima Nova Printed in Falmouth, UK The Royal Institute of Philosophy 14 Gordon Square London WC1H 0AR United Kingdom T. 020 7387 4130 www.royalinstitutephilosophy.org


Past & Present: Philosophy for everyone

Edited by Stephen Law


6

“

The reasonable man adapts himself to the world: the unreasonable one persists in trying to adapt the world to himself. Therefore all progress depends on the unreasonable man. George Bernard Shaw


7

Foreword

T

he dominant view nowadays is that the philosophy of nature no longer exists. That branch of philosophy died out with the emergence of the modern empirical sciences.

Its domain of inquiry was divided among the various particular sciences. Admittedly, there are still some philosophers who try to cultivate a philosophy of nature, but when one takes a closer look at their work it turns out that most of their effort is devoted to defining what exactly the philosophy of nature is supposed to study. The philosophy of nature as traditionally understood only prepared the ground for the future natural sciences and at their emergence lost its reason for being. Does that mean the elimination of philosophy from science? Not at all. In the first place, the very existence of science is a fact which requires philosophical reflection. That task was taken up by the philosophy of science. That branch of philosophy is flourishing and, just as happens with any respectable science, has many schools and specializations - from research into the kind of rationality represented by various sciences and the logic of the development of scientific theories, through analysis of the methods used by various sciences, to specialized analytic research into those aspects of scientific theories which the sciences themselves cannot handle. Does that exhaust the tasks which philosophy must fulfill in relation to science?

Gottlob Frege


Table of contents

Introduction Stephen Law

Biographies 011

Ian James Kidd Alasdair MacIntyre Bernard Williams J端rgen Habermas Anthony Kenny Christine Korsgaard Simon Blackburn John Searle

024

Noam Chomsky John McDowell T. M. Scanlon Thomas Nagel Mary Warnock Jerry Fodor Tyler Burge Ned Block Derek Parfit

094

032 040 050 058 066 072 080 102 114 116 128 136 142 154 160


Religion & Society

Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd Humility And History

016

Alasdair MacIntyre Social Structures and their threats to Moral Agency

026

Bernard Williams

034

Philosophy as a Humanist Discipline

Mind & Body

Christine Korsgaard Personhood, Animals, And The Law

062

Thomas Nagel Conceiving the Impossible and the Mind-Body Problem

118

Simon Blackburn The Sovereignty of Reason

068

Mary Warnock What is Natural and Should We Care About It?

130

John Searle

074

Jerry Fodor Mental Representation without Conceptualization

138

Tyler Burge Perception: Where Mind Begins

144

Ned Block

156

Freedom of the Will as a Problem in Neurobiology

J端rgen Habermas The Pacemaker for Cultural Rights

042

Anthony Kenny Is Religion Really the Root of all Evil?

052

Noam Chomsky Some Thoughts on Terror, Justice and Self-defence

082

John McDowell Intention in Action

096

Attention and Mentalism T. M. Scanlon Reassessing Reasons

104

Derek Parfit Is Personal Identity what Matters?

162


10

“

Don’t bite off more than you can chew because nobody looks attractive spitting it back out... Carroll Bryant


11

Introduction

T

he dominant view nowadays is that the philosophy of nature

and then the natural sciences arose and liquidated the place of

no longer exists. That branch of philosophy died out with the

philosophy in science is a crude oversimplification of the historical

emergence of the modern empirical sciences. Its domain of inquiry

process. The natural sciences did not arise on the ruins of the

was divided among the various particular sciences. Admittedly, there

philosophy of nature. They existed in parallel to it, though they were

are still some philosophers who try to cultivate a philosophy of nature,

not always explicitly separated from it. It is sufficient to name the

but when one takes a closer look at their work it turns out that most

Greek sciences: astronomy, optics, acoustics, statics, not to mention

of their effort is devoted to defining what exactly the philosophy of

geometry. One can only speak of a period of the domination of the

nature is supposed to study. The philosophy of nature as traditionally

philosophy of nature over the sciences until the beginning of the

understood only prepared the ground for the future natural sciences

modern period, after which one must speak of the period of the

and at their emergence lost its reason for being. Does that mean the

domination of the sciences. The transition between those two periods

elimination of philosophy from science? Not at all. In the first place,

was a continuous transition, although one rich in dramatic tensions.

the very existence of science is a fact which requires philosophical

Notice how many typically philosophical problems were found in the

reflection. That task was taken up by the philosophy of science.

spheres of interest of various scientific theories. The problems of time,

That branch of philosophy is flourishing and, just as happens with

space, and causality will serve as typical examples. Right down to our

any respectable science, has many schools and specializations - from

own day they are thought of as “great problems of philosophy” though

research into the kind of rationality represented by various sciences

at the same time all the fundamental theories of physics have much to

and the logic of the development of scientific theories, through

say on these topics.

analysis of the methods used by various sciences, to specialized

It is of course true that when some problem migrates

analytic research into those aspects of scientific theories which the

from philosophy to the empirical sciences, it thereby changes

sciences themselves cannot handle.

its significance. We know that context is just as important as the

Does that exhaust the tasks which philosophy must fulfill in

“internal” connections between concepts. What is more, the problems

relation to science? In answering that question, let us appeal to history.

and concepts transformed by the migration from philosophy to the

Above all, the statement that first there was the philosophy of nature

sciences often come back for further philosophical deliberation, in that


12

way thickening the connections between the two realms of knowledge.

those lectures, made available in typescript through the kindness of

The strengthening of that connection creates an interesting field of

Professor Ladrière, were of invaluable assistance to me. The many

investigation. I have called it “philosophy in science,” no doubt a

references to Professor Ladrière’s notes in the text of this book indicate

summary expression and one which includes only some aspects of

my debt to him only partially. However, my own series of lectures

the phenomena which interests us here, but I hope that the entire

is not a copy of the lectures given in Louvain. Professor Ladrière

book will constitute a justification for it. As I have already noted, the

concentrated his attention principally on one problem, namely, on the

history of science itself bears witness to the presence in science of

relation of physics to metaphysics in the most important systems of

philosophical threads and it is for that reason that I have to write this

the philosophy of nature.

book from a philosophical point of view. That does not mean that the study of philosophy in science has

That is indeed one of the key problems, but I decided to go beyond that problem, and to undertake a more comprehensive

to limit itself to purely historical considerations; it means only that

discussion of the particular systems. As a result, the more focused

historical considerations seem to be an indispensable element of a

formulation of Professor Ladrière has, in my book, become a more

strategy which would allow us to see the philosophical significance of

general series of lectures. That has manifested itself also in the method

the sciences. In my opinion, a thorough knowledge of at least the most

of the lectures. Professor Ladrière limited himself to a discussion of

important trends which have appeared in the history of philosophy

the relation between physics and metaphysics in Aristotle, Descartes,

and science is a necessary condition of a responsible research program

Leibniz, Kant, and Whitehead. I have supplemented that account

in the area of contemporary philosophico-scientific problems, and

with a look at Plato, Newton, Popper and the so-called Romantic

at the same time is an indispensable minimum of knowledge for the

philosophy of nature. I also added a chapter on Aristotle’s treatise

researcher working in other areas of philosophy.

On the Heavens and a chapter discussing the philosophical themes in

I borrowed the idea of developing a series of lectures around

contemporary science.

the most important figures and themes from the history of place of philosophy in science from Professor Jean Ladrière, who gave such a series of lectures at the Institut Supérieur de Philosophie of the University of Louvain in 1982-–1983. The unpublished notes from

Introduction

Stephen Law


13

Human beings are born into this little span of life of which the best thing is its friendship and intimacies, and soon their places will know them no more, and yet they leave their friendships and intimacies with no cultivation, to grow as they will by the roadside, expecting them to “keep” by force of inertia. William James


“

He who thinks great thoughts, often makes great errors Martin Heidegger


Religion & Society


16

Humility and History Ian James Kidd

Philosophy is an ancient subject, but what is the value of an understanding of its history for its practice? What can contemporary philosophers draw from an historical understanding of their subject?

I

Across the scope of human cultures, in different times and climes, one finds sustained philosophical reflection, on topics ranging from knowledge and justice, to society and education, to reality and meaning. Although philosophy, like any subject, has its ‘boom and bust’ periods, recent scholarship indicates that even periods previously considered to be rather barren – such as the ‘Dark Ages’ of

argue that amongst its many benefits, the history of philosophy

medieval Europe – were, in fact, philosophically dynamic, even if their

is an excellent resource for the cultivation of certain intellectual

questions and problems reflected concerns rather different from ours.

virtues , most notably gratitude, humility, and justice. Acquaintance

The fact of the historical ubiquity of philosophy of course pleases those

with the history of philosophy can, therefore, be edifying, in the sense

engaged in the ‘business’ of philosophy today.

1

of being conducive to the cultivation and exercise of virtues. These

Certainly philosophers, whether professional or lay, should

virtues can be cultivated in many ways, but the history of philosophy

find a legitimate sense of pride in their participation in a venerable3

offers unique means for securing those virtues just mentioned –

tradition of thought. This should include an appreciation of the sincere

or so I will argue. In what follows, I hope to show that some familiar

and sustained efforts, by men and women historically and culturally

pedagogical and intellectual uses of the history of philosophy in fact

distant from us, to articulate ideas about their place in the ‘order of

reflect its edifying functions. The origins of philosophy are unclear,

things’, which we may, today, profitably draw upon. And there isn’t,

but certainly there were, in Greece, India, and China, vigorous

one hopes, too much vainglory4 in the optimistic sentiment5 that

philosophical traditions by the sixth to fifth centuries BCE. Indeed,

philosophy has been, and continues to be, an ennobling6 feature of

it is possible that Confucius, the Buddha, Thales and the authors of

human life. Although such sentiments have their place, the history

the Upanisads may have been contemporaries. The last six thousand

of philosophy surely offers us more than just a sense of pride of one’s

years have, of course, seen philosophy, both ‘Eastern’ and ‘Western’,

place within a venerable tradition. Those things matter, if only to

go on to sustain vigorous, dynamic traditions. Indeed, one striking

motivate, but the value of the history of philosophy should not be

fact evidenced by history is the ubiquity of philosophical reflection.

narrowly construed7 as a capacity to encourage young philosophers –

2

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


17

2. Ubiquity - the state or capacity of being everywhere, especially at the same time. 3. Venerableness - Commanding respect by virtue of age, dignity, character, or position; honorableness.

4. Vainglory - inordinate pride in oneself or one’s achievements; excessive vanity. 5. Sentiment - a view of or attitude toward a situation or event; an opinion. 6. Ennoble - to make noble.

1. Virtue - behavior showing high moral standards.

7. Construe - to interpret (a word or action) in a particular way.

those sitting through hard going undergraduate lectures on Kant, say

context of the structure of modern universities. Yet a focus on abstract

– to ‘keep at it’ and work hard. A sense of ‘standing on the shoulders of

argument divorced from concrete context does, at least sometimes,

giants’, to borrow Newton’s handy phrase, is useful. But so, too, is one’s

compromise one’s understanding and appreciation of the ideas and

knowing something about those ‘giants’ and about how, and why, they

problems being discussed.

worked and wondered as they did. In the history of philosophy, these ‘giants’ would be all those earlier thinkers whose work is now part of our shared history. Some of the giants are obvious and familiar, such as Plato or the Buddha, whereas others, like Nāgārjuna or Josiah Royce,

That man is wisest who, like Socrates, realizes that his wisdom is worthless

remain reliably obscure, at least within certain areas of academic philosophy. Both familiarity and obscurity can be fickle things, of

Plato

course. Some philosophical giants are prominent for their notoriety, like Nietzsche, and others for their accessibility, like Russell. But what

One could, for instance, take a course on ‘Knowledge and Scepticism’,

does it mean to say that these figures, and others more like them, are

covering Pyrrho, Descartes, Kant and others, without ever detailing

part of a ‘shared history’, and how and why does that history matter?

why, for each of those figures, questions about knowledge and

The significance of the history of philosophy turns on the

scepticism mattered. An appeal to the inherent1 fascination or

answer to that question. Certainly there are many reasons why one

trickiness of their questions usually suffices2, at least for those who opt

might not want to teach philosophy in a historical manner.

to take such courses, but often those questions are presented without

One might prefer, for instance, to teach or write about philosophy

a clear account of why those philosophers were troubled by them.

in terms of ‘problems’ or discrete ‘areas’, like ‘Metaphysics’,

Most philosophers, at least in the past, were troubled by philosophical

‘Consciousness’, or ‘Topics in Philosophy of Science’. This way of

questions not simply out of mere curiosity, but rather because they

philosophising focuses on topics, issues, and themes, like the nature

perceived that those questions, even the most abstract ones, had

of time, mental causation, or scientific methodology. And that can be

implications for aspects of life which mattered to them.

a valuable and effective way of ‘doing’ philosophy, especially within the

Such concerns are easily to neglect.

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


18

1. Inherent - existing in something as a permanent, essential, or characteristic attribute.

4. Presocratics - a pre-Socratic philosopher. 5. Reform - make changes in (something, typically a social, political, or

2. Suffice - to be enough or adequate.

economic institution or practice) in order to improve it.

3. Axiom - a statement or proposition that is regarded as being established, accepted, or self-evidently true.

A philosopher’s ‘position’ can be summarised as an argument, or a

were interested. Rather, it was because they perceived that a person

series of bullet-points on a PowerPoint slide, but this format is apt to

who is to be happy must understand, first, what things are like and,

neglect the vital concerns that animated them. For instance,

second, how one should be disposed towards them. Put another

it often tends to obscure the biographical and historical context of

way, they thought that knowledge of things was essential if we are

a philosopher’s life, reducing them to names and dates, of the form

to act properly regarding them, therefore interlinking epistemology

‘Thomas Hobbes (1588– 1679)’. Where, after all, is the contextual

and ethics in a way that will, one worries, remain invisible if one

richness of a biography such as that which Heidegger offered for

concentrated simply on the arguments themselves.

Aristotle: ‘he was born ... he worked, and ... he died’. Heidegger may have been right that, for certain purposes, Aristotle’s biography is Certainly it is not a general axiom3 of philosophizing. Context is not

Excellence is never an accident. It is always the result of high intention, sincere effort, and intelligent execution; it represents the wise choice of many alternatives -

only pedagogically or interpretively valuable. There are entertaining

choice, not chance, determines your destiny

not ‘of interest’, but that fact is only true at a certain level of analysis.

anecdotes in the history of philosophy, for sure – and not solely in the life of Ludwig Wittgenstein – but the value of historical context goes further than that. Showing the wider social and political conditions

Aristotle

within which philosophers worked, worried and wondered can help us

Many derisive9 assessments of the value of philosophy arise because,

to appreciate their ‘practical’ objectives.

in many cases, those critics do not see how the ‘abstract’ issues raised

The Presocratics offer interesting arguments against traditional 4

by the philosophically-minded bear on ‘practical’ issues. The fault

Greek religion, but they were, ultimately, intended to facilitate

may be shared, but it can, I think, be partially resolved by an historical

social and political reform5. Or to take a slightly later example, the

perspective upon philosophy. Once one becomes accustomed to a

Pyrrhonian sceptics did not engage in abstract epistemology , asking

historical articulation of philosophy, the task of providing accounts of

abstruse questions about the nature of knowledge, just because they

the ‘practical’ import of ‘abstract’ philosophising should become much

6

8

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

7

Ian James Kidd


19

6. Pyrrhonian - Pyrrhonism was a school of skepticism founded by Aenesidemus in the 1st century BC and recorded by Sextus Empiricus in the late 2nd century or early 3rd century AD. 7. Epistemology - the investigation of what distinguishes justified belief

8. Abstruse - difficult to understand; obscure. 9. Derisive - expressing contempt or ridicule, sarcasm. 10. Perennial - lasting or existing for a long or apparently infinite time; enduring or continually recurring.

from opinion.

easier. By being able to explain how earlier philosophers came to their

to changing social and intellectual conditions. Questions about the

ideas, or what provoked their questions, it should become easier for us

certainty of knowledge, say, were changed by the development of

to do the same for our own inquiries. And this should be understood,

the modern sciences. But appreciating this involves an historical

not as ‘accounting for ourselves’, but, rather, as explaining ourselves,

sensitivity. It requires us to look not only at earlier philosophers

for our benefit, and for that of our critics. Certainly a knowledge and

who asked similar questions, but also at the context within which

appreciation of the history of philosophy can be a valuable feature of

those questions were asked. After all, it is often context which lends

the actual practice of philosophy.

our questions urgency, vitality, and significance. There are many

An understanding of philosophy as an historical discipline shows how it is bound up with social and political change, religious controversy, scientific innovation, and so on. Those sorts of issues are,

philosophical questions and puzzles, but which ones matter to us, and why, is as much a matter of history as it is of curiosity and inquiry. The role of history in shaping our own ideas points to another

of course, features of our world today; indeed, many philosophical

role for the history of philosophy. Many questions face us, but not all

questions are perennial10 in the sense that they return, each

of them matter to us. Certain questions move us, either by disturbing

generation, often in evolving forms. Questions about beauty and art,

or fascinating us (or, indeed, both). Other questions are curiosities –

justice and goodness, knowledge and certainty, and the like have

interesting, but deemed neither urgent nor essential. Understanding

featured within the public and private lives of human beings across

the distribution of significance across the philosophical landscape

all times and cultures. A historical understanding of the philosophers

will, again, require a historical perspective. After all, we are ourselves

that responded to them can help us, today, in our own efforts to

subjects of a history. To ape Nietzsche’s* famous remark, when we

address them. The history of philosophy is, therefore, a feature of

stare into history, history also stares back into us, insofar as the

philosophising itself.

concerns and issues of contemporary society are products, at least in

To ask and address philosophical questions is to enter into a

part, of that society’s history – that is, of our history. Such a reflexive

longstanding tradition of inquiry. The specific content and form of

historical stance is, of course, only useful beyond a certain point.

philosophical questions changes over time, of course, in response

We can get on much of the business of philosophising, debating and

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


20

1. Genealogy - a record or account of the ancestry and descent of a person, family, group, etc.

4. Haecceity - a term from medieval scholastic philosophy, first coined by Duns Scotus, which denotes the discrete qualities, properties or

2. Salience - prominent or conspicuous.

characteristics of a thing which make it a particular thing.

3. Flux - a flowing or flow. * for further biography see last page of transcript

arguing without ever engaging in the historical project of tracing what

questions’ which command the interest and attention of most of those

Nietzsche called the ‘genealogy ’ of our questions and methods.

drawn to philosophy. It is these questions, and the richer conception

But that point at which history becomes essential is, I think,

of philosophy they reflect, which Kant had in mind when he wrote of

reached far sooner than is often imagined. Beyond a certain point,

the ‘cosmopolitan sense’ in philosophy, which issues in four questions:

philosophical understanding must, if it is to satisfy us, become

‘What can I know? What ought I to do? What may I hope?

historically sensitive. This would include an understanding of how and

What is man?’ The history of philosophy, then, is an essential

why those questions came down to us, what presuppositions must be

feature of a certain broad conception of philosophy. It may be called

in place to enable our inquiries, and of why those questions and their

cosmopolitan, after Kant, or ‘humanistic’, after Bernard Williams,

answers matter to us. A great deal of valuable philosophical work can

or it may be judged, following Pierre Hadot, as a series of ‘spiritual

proceed without the sort of historical understanding just described.

exercises’ manifesting in a certain ‘way of life’. Whatever its name, it

A philosopher would be foolish to pursue a historical perspective

is a conception of philosophy focused upon questions and concerns

where that would neither aid nor complement their concerns. Analytic

of vital importance to thinking, reflective human beings: questions

philosophy, for instance, is often said to be largely ‘ahistorical’, but

of beauty, meaning, goodness, and the like, where these questions are

that is most often, I think, because its questions and concerns are not

understood, not as exercises in conceptual ingenuity, but as essential

usually of the sort of invite historical input.

components of one’s practical activities within the world. These

1

The salience2 of history depends upon the questions being

questions are certainly not absent from ahistorical philosophising,

asked and the kind of answers one is seeking. My emphasis on the

but arguably they may be better served by an historical approach.

role of the history of philosophy is directed at those with more vital,

Abstract reflection has a part to play in articulating and addressing

‘practical’ concerns. The refinement of a complex argument about

these questions, but often they cannot be fully appreciated, or

logical relations might not invite historical reflection; but questions

answered, without an historical appreciation of those earlier

about the nature of ‘the good life’, for instance, surely are, for the

generations of philosophers who, troubled by similar worries, offered

reason that it is questions of this sort that are perennial, which appear

their own responses. Sensitivity to the history of philosophy therefore

across different cultures and generations. And it is, I suspect, such ‘big

offers resources for understanding that may be unavailable to those

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


21

5. Mind-body dualism - In philosophy of mind, dualism is the position that mental phenomena are, in some respects, non-physical, or that the

8. Cartesian dualism - Descartes’ concept of dualism. 9. Presuppositions - a thing tacitly assumed beforehand at the beginning

mind and body are not identical.

of a line of argument or course of action.

6. Iconoclasm - the forceful opposition to the veneration of inanimate

10. (Margaret) Thatcher - UK. prime minister (1979-1990).

7. Representations, religious icons, and other symbols or monuments.

who forsake context for raw argument. By neglecting the context of

However, the objection that philosophy is detached is invalid

philosophical inquiry, one deprives many problems of their urgency

because it relies upon a false conception of philosophy. That image

and salience. Earlier philosophers, stripped of context, may seem

of philosophy – as detached, abstract speculation, isolated from a

peculiar, even perverse, for persisting in abstruse intellectual inquiries

practical context – would certainly make it difficult to see what, if

– about flux , haeccities , mind-body dualism , and the like. However

anything, those speculations had to do with the world. However that

to accuse them thus does them an injustice, and indicates, at the same

conception of philosophy is dependent upon an ahistorical approach

time, our own ignorance. Once Cynic iconoclasm , say, or Cartesian

to the subject, one which strips it of context and isolates it from those

dualism is located within its proper intellectual and historical context,

‘real-world’ concerns which animate it. Reaffirming the contextual

their urgency and salience may be clarified and amplified. The result

and historical nature of philosophy should also help to insure us

is, argue two recent writers, ‘the maturing of a kind of modesty or

against various vices.

4

5

6

7

humility’, an ‘increased perception’ not only of the ‘presuppositions and prejudices of earlier eras’, but also an increased capacity, on our own part, to ‘expose similar presuppositions and prejudices that 8

may be shaping beliefs and commitments today’. Such a historical

Every man is a creature of the age in which he lives and few are able to raise themselves above the ideas of the time

conception should also help protect philosophy from certain persistent and ill-informed challenges to it. Those who object that philosophy is ‘abstract’ and ‘detached’ often, I suspect, have certain caricatures of contemporary academic philosophy in mind. Certainly successive

3

Voltaire

The awareness that our problems are not new and that earlier

British Governments since Thatcher seem to have shared that view,

generations also encountered them should encourage a certain

the present one included. Other philosophers have also expressed

humility on our own part. Only presentist hubris1 could persuade us

worries about the deleterious impact of certain features of academic

that our predilections2 – our anxieties and insights – are privileged

philosophy upon the genuine pursuit of philosophical inquiry.

guides to the nature of reality. An appreciation of context should, one

9

hopes, indicate that our anxieties and insights arise from ideas and

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


22

1. Hubris - excessive pride or self-confidence.

4. Prefigure - to show or represent beforehand by a figure or type.

2. Predilections - a preference or special liking for something;

5. Impoverished - poor, weakened.

a bias in favor of something. 3. Parochial - of or relating to a church parish.

developments which are not wholly of our making. Our achievements

Understanding that history will not only illuminate our contemporary

are, therefore, not ours alone. At the least, we owe a debt to both

concerns, but, one hopes, also renew our appreciation of philosophy.

the errors and the insights of earlier generations, a debt which an

Our participation in that history will, at the least, enable us to do

understanding of the history of philosophy can help to make apparent.

justice to those who came before, and hopefully enable us to endow

There is ignorance, injustice and also ingratitude in the attitudes of

future generations, as best we can, with ideas which, in time, may

those who deride the value of philosophy whilst living within a society

be of use to those who follow us. At the very least, such historical

so shaped by it.

philosophising brings with it a set of intellectual virtues –

urged us, when considering our history, to

admire those who ‘first brought us to the path of truth’ as much as

gratitude, humility, and justice – which lend it a moral as well as an

those ‘who afterwards conducted us through it’. To cherry-pick from

intellectual significance.

the history of philosophy those figures whose views prefigure ours 3

smacks of what historians of science call ‘Whig history’: a neglect of the role of critics, rival schools and the like in shaping the ideas that, from a parochial4 perspective, ‘won’ in the end. Failure to acknowledge those who brought us to our current path reflects badly upon us, especially if, as d’Alembert reminds us, we are but a ‘passing generation’, our concerns being, perhaps, ‘nothing for the next one, still less for distant posterity’. Once a historical approach to philosophy is in place, that impoverished5 view of philosophy – and the stereotypes it sponsors, of philosophers as intellectual narcissists preoccupied with their own uncertainties, say – should dissolve. There is a place for abstract reflection, for sure, but philosophy is, for many, necessarily rooted in the practical concerns of human beings who are, themselves, subjects of a history.

Transcripts / Morals & Intentions

Ian James Kidd


23

Meet & Greet

*

Find out more about selected philosophers who starred in the previous transcript

Friedrich Nietzsche 1844-1900 Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900) was a German philosopher

sobriety and rationale to such destructive drives. These became to

of the late 19th century who challenged the foundations of

major principles in his future work, the Dionysian and Apollonian,

Christianity and traditional morality.

one of chaos, dream and intoxication, the other one of order and

H

the lending of form. These Nietzsche associated with an aesthetic

e was interested in the enhancement of individual and cultural

disposition in which life be viewed as a work of art. He demonstrated

health, and believed in life, creativity, power, and the realities

that the Greeks had theorized the relation of the two principles in

of the world we live in, rather than those situated in a world beyond.

which art is a willed illusion and is composed of both form-giving and

Central to his philosophy is the idea of “life-affirmation,” which

intoxication, and thus, art offers one a vantage point of life. Therefore,

involves an honest questioning of all doctrines that drain life’s

life itself becomes recognizable as unknowable in terms of an ultimate

expansive energies, however socially prevalent those views might

truth, as proposed by an idealist metaphysics.

be. Often referred to as one of the first existentialist philosophers along with Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855), Nietzsche’s revitalizing philosophy has inspired leading figures in all walks of cultural

Notable work

life, including dancers, poets, novelists, painters, psychologists, philosophers, sociologists and social revolutionaries. In his first published book, Die Geburt der Tragödie aus dem

The Birth of Tragedy (published in 1872) Human, All Too Human (completed in 1879)

Geist der Musik (The Birth of Tragedy), he diagnosed that human

Thus Spoke Zarathustra (1885)

beings are subject to Dionysian instincts — unconscious desires,

Beyond Good and Evil (1886)

impulses, or overwhelmingly self-destructive tendencies. Nietzsche

The Antichrist (1888)

pointed out that the Greeks had opposed Apollonian principles of

Meet & Greet

Friedrich Nietzche


24

Ian James Kidd

About

Papers

Born: 02/04/1982

Doing Science An Injustice: Midgley on Scientism

Origin: Lousiana, U.S.

Educating for Intellectual Humility Nature, Mystery, and Morality: A Daoist View

Works in epistemology, philosophy of medicine, philosophy of

Epistemic Injustice in Healthcare: A Philosophical Analysis

religion, history and philosophy of science, and the philosophical

Doing Away With Scientism

traditions of Asia and Continental Europe.

Feyerabend on Politics, Education, and Scientific Culture Phenomenology, Psychiatric Illness, and Religious Commitment

Epistemic virtues and vices (especially epistemic injustice and

Feyerabend on Science and Education

epistemic humility); the experience and value of illness; the nature of

Was Sir William Crookes Epistemically Virtuous?

a religious life; contingency and pluralism in science; scientism and

Reappraising Feyerabend

anti-scientism; the practice and nature of philosophy; and the life and

Transformative Suffering and the Cultivation of Virtue

thought of Paul Feyerabend.

History and Humility Emotion, Religious Practice, and Cosmopolitan Secularism

Founded the Durham Philosophy Department’s Gender Action Group and is committed to improving the representation of women in philosophy, and is also involved with the Leeds University chapter of Minorities in Philosophy (MAP).

Biographies

Ian James Kidd


25

Talks Illness, Virtue, and Exemplarist Ethics

Religious Beauties

Location: University of Leeds

Time: 11 AM to 1 AM

Event Date: Feb 25, 2015

Location: University of Leeds

Organization: Centre for Ethics

Event Date: Nov 20, 2014 Organization: Centre for the Philosophy of Religion

Learning from the Best: Ethical Exemplarism in Confucius’ 'Analects'

Books

Location: University of Durham Event Date: Jan 21, 2015

Science and the Self: Animals, Evolution, and Ethics:

Organization: Durham University Philosophical Society

Essays in Honour of Mary Midgley

'World Philosophies' series

co-edited with Elizabeth McKinnell Publisher: London: Routledge

Epistemic Injustice and Religious Experience Location: Durham University

The Routledge Handbook to Epistemic Injustice

Event Date: 2015

co-edited with José Medina and Gaile Pohlhaus

Organization: Epistemic Injustice and the Philosophy of Religion

Publisher: London: Routledge

Experiences of Illness and Narratives of Edification

Historiography and the Philosophy of the Sciences

Location: University of Bristol

co-edited with Robin Hendry

Event Date: Jul 9, 2013

Publisher: special section of Studies in History and

Organization: Illness, Narrative, Phenomenology

Philosophy of Science

Confidence, Humility, and Philosophy

Reappraising Feyerabend

Location: EIDOS Durham University

(co-edited with Matthew Brown, UT Dallas, in preparation as a special

Event Date: Jun 17, 2014

issue of Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2013)

Anthropogenic Climate Change, Humility, and ‘Epistemic Activism’

Mystery and Humility

Event Date: Oct 31, 2014

(co-edited with Guy Bennett-Hunter, Durham)

Organization: Philosophy and Public Policy:

European Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 40/3 (2012).

Philosophical Activism III

Biographies

Ian James Kidd





Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.