Marxist political economy and bourdieu: economic and cultural capital, classes and state 1st edition

Page 1


Marxist Political Economy and Bourdieu: Economic and Cultural Capital, Classes and State 1st Edition

George Economakis

Visit to download the full and correct content document: https://textbookfull.com/product/marxist-political-economy-and-bourdieu-economic-an d-cultural-capital-classes-and-state-1st-edition-george-economakis/

More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant download maybe you interests ...

American Exceptionalism: Economics, Finance, Political Economy, and Economic Laws Lall Ramrattan

https://textbookfull.com/product/american-exceptionalismeconomics-finance-political-economy-and-economic-laws-lallramrattan/

Economic Rationality (What is Political Economy?) 1st Edition Stephen G. Engelmann

https://textbookfull.com/product/economic-rationality-what-ispolitical-economy-1st-edition-stephen-g-engelmann/

Female Olympians: A Mediated Socio-Cultural and Political-Economic Timeline 1st Edition Linda K. Fuller (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/female-olympians-a-mediatedsocio-cultural-and-political-economic-timeline-1st-edition-lindak-fuller-auth/

China's Economic Rise: Lessons from Japan’s Political Economy Sangaralingam Ramesh

https://textbookfull.com/product/chinas-economic-rise-lessonsfrom-japans-political-economy-sangaralingam-ramesh/

Biota Grow 2C gather 2C cook Loucas

https://textbookfull.com/product/biota-grow-2c-gather-2c-cookloucas/

The Political Economy of Russian Aluminium: Between the Dual State and Global Markets 1st Edition Jakub M. Godzimirski

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-political-economy-ofrussian-aluminium-between-the-dual-state-and-global-markets-1stedition-jakub-m-godzimirski/

The Paradox of Creativity in Art Education Bourdieu and Socio cultural Practice Kerry Thomas

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-paradox-of-creativity-inart-education-bourdieu-and-socio-cultural-practice-kerry-thomas/

China-India Relations: Geo-political Competition, Economic Cooperation, Cultural Exchange and Business Ties Young-Chan Kim

https://textbookfull.com/product/china-india-relations-geopolitical-competition-economic-cooperation-cultural-exchange-andbusiness-ties-young-chan-kim/

Marx, Capital, and the Madness of Economic Reason 1st Edition David Harvey

https://textbookfull.com/product/marx-capital-and-the-madness-ofeconomic-reason-1st-edition-david-harvey/

Marxist Political Economy and Bourdieu

This book systematically addresses Bourdieu’s key ideas and concepts in the context of Marxist thought. In this book, Bourdieu’s central theoretical points are analyzed within a political, sociological and politico-economic framework which allows for the development of a sequential narrative of his key ideas. Thus, the authors are able to highlight the theoretical consistencies and political conclusions which can be derived from Bourdieu’s work. For example, Bourdieu’s antineoliberal narrative is correlated with his analysis of class, and especially with his canonization of the petty bourgeoisie and its strategy for a reformed anti-neoliberal capitalism. The book also analyzes this coherent synthesis of Bourdieu’s work in the context of Marxist political economy, including not only Marx but also Lenin, Althusser and Poulantzas. In this context, the book explores Bourdieu’s work on the state, class strategy, socialism and capitalism. This unique perspective will be of great interest to social scientists, particularly in economics, politics and sociology, working on Bourdieu, Marx and capitalism.

George Economakis is Professor of Political Economy at the Department of Business Administration of the University of Patras.

Theofanis Papageorgiou is Assistant Professor of Economic Analysis at the Department of Business Administration of the University of Patras.

Routledge Frontiers of Political Economy

Why are Presidential Regimes Bad for the Economy?

Understanding the Link between Forms of Government and Economic Outcomes

Richard McManus and Gulcin Ozkan

Critical Theory and Economics

Philosophical Notes on Contemporary Inequality

Robin Maialeh

Corporate Financialization

An Economic Sociology Perspective

Marcelo José do Carmo, Mário Sacomano Neto and Julio Cesar Donadone

The Political Economy of Corruption

Edited by Chandan Jha, Ajit Mishra and Sudipta Sarangi

Post-Keynesian Theories of the Firm

Kalecki and Radical Uncertainty

Nobantu L. Mbeki

Socialist Economic Systems

21st Century Pathways

Steven Rosefield

COVID-19 and Economic Development in Latin America

Theoretical Debates, Financing Dilemmas and Post-Pandemic Scenarios

Monika Meireles, Bruno De Conti and Diego Guevara

Marxist Political Economy and Bourdieu

Economic and Cultural Capital, Classes and State

George Economakis and Theofanis Papageorgiou

For more information about this series, please visit: www.routledge.com/RoutledgeFrontiers-of-Political-Economy/book-series/SE0345

Marxist Political Economy and Bourdieu

Economic and Cultural Capital, Classes and State

First published 2023 by Routledge

4 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge

605 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10158

Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business © 2023 George Economakis and Theofanis Papageorgiou

The right of George Economakis and Theofanis Papageorgiou to be identified as authors of this work has been asserted in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.

Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe.

British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

ISBN: 978-1-032-45103-9 (hbk)

ISBN: 978-1-032-45104-6 (pbk)

ISBN: 978-1-003-37540-1 (ebk)

DOI: 10.4324/9781003375401

Typeset in Bembo by SPi Technologies India Pvt Ltd (Straive)

of illustrations

1 ‘Capitals’, ‘fields’, dominant class, intellectuals and state: aspects of Bourdieu’s analysis 6

1.1 ‘Capitals’, ‘fields’ and classes 6

1.2 Dominant class and ‘field of power’ 11

1.3 ‘Organic solidarity’ and the increasing importance of the ‘general bureaucratic training’ 15

1.4 The ‘priority’ of ‘consent’ 18

1.5 The rejection of the ‘dichotomy’ between economic base and superstructure 19

1.6 The struggles within the dominated fraction of the dominant class: ‘left hand of the state’ and ‘right hand of the state’ 20

1.6.1 The defence of the ‘social conquest’ of the past and the ‘left hand of the state’ 21

1.7 The state as ‘meta-field’ 26

2 A first critical codification: intellectuals, capitalism and the principal contradiction of capitalism 33

2.1 The centrality of the intellectuals: the two theoretical instances 33

2.1.1 The first theoretical instance 34

2.1.2 The second theoretical instance 36

2.1.3 The integration of the ‘left’ and ‘right’ and the ‘two states’ 41

2.2 The non-theorization of capitalism 43

3 The social classes: Bourdieu’s and Marxist analysis 48

3.1 Relations of production, modes of production and class affiliation: preliminary discussion 48

3.2 The capitalist mode of production, the capitalist state, the bourgeoisie and the working class 50

3.2.1 The elementary and the specific feature of the capitalist mode of production and the emergence of the bourgeoisie and the working class 51

3.3 The new petty bourgeoisie of the capitalist mode of production and its distinction from the working class and the higher managers 52

3.3.1 The working class and the new petty bourgeoisie of the capitalist mode of production 52

3.3.2 The higher managers 57

3.4 The heads of the state apparatus and the new petty bourgeoisie of the state 60

3.4.1 The heads of state apparatus 61

3.4.2 The new petty bourgeoisie of the state 62

4 Potential ideological-political class position of the new petty bourgeoisie of the capitalist mode of production and of the state: a critical reading of Poulantzas’s analysis 74

4.1 Class structural determination (structural class position) and potential ideological-political position: the distinction 74

4.2 Digression: the merger of all the middle classes through ‘pertinent effects’, the enlargement of the new petty bourgeoisie and the shrinkage of the working-class in Poulantzas’s analysis 84

4.2.1 The unification of middle classes 84

4.2.2 The enlargement of the new petty bourgeoisies and the shrinking of the working class 86

4.3 The potential ideological-political position of the new petty bourgeoisie (of the capitalist mode of production and of the wider state) and the question of the ‘autonomous class strategy’ 87

4.3.1 At the ideological level 87

4.3.2 At the political level 103

4.3.3 ‘Demands’ and ‘political interests’ of the new petty bourgeoisie 106

4.4 The state capitalism as a potential strategic orientation of the new petty bourgeoisie 108

5 Again for the state: class and ‘universal’ 122

5.1 Bourdieu’s ambiguities: introductory remarks 122

5.2 The ‘bourgeois’ as ‘universal’ 124

5.3 ‘The double character of the State’ and the question of class struggle within the state 130

5.4 The ‘bearers’ of ‘universal’: ‘Right hand of the state’ and ‘left hand of the state’ 135

5.4.1 The ‘right hand of the state’ as the ‘bearer’ of ‘universal’ 135

5.4.2 The ‘left hand of the state’ as the ‘bearer’ of ‘universal’ against ‘the ultra-liberal conservative revolution’ and Marxism 137

Illustrations

Figures

3.1 The social classes of the CMP

3.2 The dominant class and the ‘two states’ in Bourdieu’s analysis

Table

4.1 Structural class position and potential ideological-political class position

Introduction

Research questions

The relationship of Pierre Bourdieu’s work with Marxism is considered rather vague. This is clearly expressed by Pallotta, who argues that ‘Bourdieu’s relationship with Marxism was a vexed one, involving a mixture of proximity and deliberate distancing’ (Pallotta 2015: I). Nonetheless, as Riley suggests, during the 1990s Bourdieu was considered ‘the organic intellectual of the gauche de la gauche’ (Riley 2017: 108). Riley highlights a puzzling situation: a theory with a questionable relationship to Marxism has been regarded as a far-left theory by the intellectual left, at least by some parts of it.

Regarding Bourdieu’s theoretical influence on academics, especially the left, Riley argues, among others,1 that Bourdieu’s sociology ‘offers an ersatz political identity to left-oriented academics’, appealing to their ‘reformist impulses’ (ibid.: 110, 131). Moreover, ‘Bourdieusian sociology is … best understood not as social theory at all, but as an ideological formation … providing a political project that can integrate the academic “Left” and “Right”’ (ibid.: 131).

In this study we are rethinking aspects of Bourdieu’s analysis, attempting to understand what could it mean ‘a political project that can integrate the academic “Left” and “Right”’, from a Marxist class point of view, and, especially why Bourdieu was considered ‘the organic intellectual of the gauche de la gauche’. In this framework, Bourdieu’s relationship with Marxism is examined, focusing in particular on the question of the principal contradiction of the capitalist system, on the class dimension of Bourdieusian ‘reformist impulses’ and on their signification for the class struggle. For this purpose, we decode Bourdieu’s ‘class analysis’ in terms of Marxist class analysis, submitting Bourdieu’s theoretical categories to Marxist concepts and attempting, as much as possible, to make them comparable. The distinction between structural class position and potential ideological-political class position – through a critical reading of Poulantzas’s analysis – is central in this research.

The puzzle of understanding the class dimension of Bourdieu’s theoretical interventions becomes more complex if we take into account that he never accepted the theoretical-political identity of ‘the gauche de la gauche’. On the contrary, he emphasized the anti-neoliberal social-democratic character of his interventions against the neoliberal mutation of social-democracy, expressed ‘by the neo-liberal troika Blair-Jospin-Schröder’. ‘The horizon of the social movement is an international of resistance to neoliberalism and all forms of conservatism’ in the direction

DOI: 10.4324/9781003375401-1

of a ‘social Europe’, he argued. In fact, he rejected the theoretical-political identity of a ‘gauche de la gauche’, maintaining that:

All that is just the invention, most often malicious, of journalists. We have spoken of a ‘left on the left’ [‘gauche de gauche’] (and not of the left [de la gauche]), that is to say, quite simply, of a truly leftist left, of a left truly respectful of the promises it has given to obtain the votes of the left voters – in terms of the rights granted to foreigners or to homosexuals, for example. To speak of the ‘left of the left’, as journalists spontaneously do, is to transform an almost banal intervention – isn’t it normal for voters to remind elected officials of their commitments? – taking a radical, extremist position, easy to condemn. From there to inventing that researchers will engage in the political struggle, while there job is not, there is only one step.

(Bourdieu 1998)

Vandenberghe (1999: 61) considers Bourdieu ‘[a]s the main spokesperson of the “collective autonomous intellectual”’. Attempting to determine the ‘spirit’ of Bourdieu’s interventions, Vandenberghe does not hesitate to characterize as ‘enemies’ of Bourdieu those that attribute to him the label of the ‘left of the left’:

In the true spirit of the Enlightenment, advancing science in the name of emancipation and emancipation in the name of science, the most famous sociologist of France has chosen to intervene as a political agitator in the public sphere to give a voice to the excluded (the unemployed and the new poor, the gays and the lesbians, the Algerian intellectuals and the illegal immigrants in France, etc.) and to undermine the neoliberal hegemony. Indeed, since the December 1995 strike2 …, he has multiplied his interventions ‘for a left on the left’ … – and not for a ‘left of the left,’ as his enemies like to misread him, critically analyzed and attacked the media intellectuals and other ‘fast thinkers’ for their complicity with the dominant classes.

(ibid.: 60)

As Wacquant (2005: 11) points out,

From early on in his youth, Bourdieu was consistently a man of the left – of the ‘gauche de gauche,’ as he famously put it in a biting criticism of the rightward turn and renunciations of the Socialist Party in the mid-nineties, an expression that has since become a standard phrase of French political language.

That is, Bourdieu was a socialist (social democrat) who criticized the Socialist Party of France for its ‘rightward turn’, and not a far-left advocate of the revolutionary overthrow of capitalism.

We would like to make clear that in the present study we examine, from a Marxist political economy perspective, aspects of Bourdieu’s work that are related to the posed research questions and not the totality of his work. Our interpretation to the posed research questions is not the only possible interpretation. Not because

3 (or not only because), as Loyal (2017: 6) argues, Bourdieu’s theoretical work ‘can be difficult to understand’ or because there are – in our point of view – ambiguities in Bourdieu’s analysis, but mainly because the interpretation given in this study is based on our conception of the Marxist theory, and especially on our conception of the Marxist theory of relations of production, modes of production, social classes and state. Finally, we would also like to point out that, on the basis of our theoretical point of view, we are investigating – in relation to the posed research questions of this study – implicit consequences arising from Bourdieu’s analyses, of which he may not have been – at least clearly or consciously – aware. Perhaps in these implicit consequences arising from Bourdieu’s analyses, the declination between the ‘left of the left’ and the ‘left on the left’ is registered, that is, the declination between the perception of his work by others (by some class sections and especially by some intellectuals) and the theoretical-political self-identification of Bourdieu himself.

Chapter 1 presents and explores (at a first level) main aspects of Bourdieu’s analysis that will be investigated in this research. The Bourdieusian concepts of ‘capital’, ‘field’, ‘field of power’, Bourdieu’s conception of the state, of the social classes, of the dominant class and its fractions, of the principal contradiction of the social system, which is the opposition between economic and cultural capital, and of the prominent social role of intellectuals, and especially of the state bureaucracy intellectuals, in the reproduction of the social system, are main points of concern in this chapter.

In Chapter 2 a first critical codification of Bourdieu’s analysis is attempted. The opposition between economic and cultural capital, which formulates the principal contradiction of the social system in Bourdieu’s analysis underlining the centrality of the intellectuals in the social system, is analyzed in relation to two theoretical instances extracted from Bourdieu’s theoretical scheme. The first theoretical instance concerns the unification of the dominated fraction of the dominant class, that is, the holders of cultural capital, against the dominant fraction of the dominant class, that is, the holders of economic capital. In the struggle between these two fractions, which constitute the dominant class, the prominent social role of intellectuals (especially of the state bureaucracy) in the reproduction of the social system through the state emerges, while the state is indicated as the base of the social system. According to the first theoretical instance of Bourdieu’s analysis, we interpret Riley’s argumentation that Bourdieusian sociology could be ‘best understood’ ‘as an ideological formation’ that provides ‘a political project that can integrate the academic “Left” and “Right”’. The second theoretical instance concerns the splits that penetrate not only into the whole dominated fraction of the dominant class but also into its dominant sub-fraction contributing to the formation of two political poles, the ‘left hand of the state’ (where there belong the ‘bearers’ of the defence of the ‘social’, the socialists holders of cultural capital) and the ‘right hand of the state’ (where there belong the ‘bearers’ of liberals who constitute an alliance of the holders of economic capital with part of the higher-ranking holders of cultural capital), and ‘two states’, the ‘left-hand state’ and the ‘right-hand state’. It is in this second theoretical instance that the ‘reformist impulses’ of the ‘leftoriented academics’, to which Riley refers, are recorded. Since the hard core of a social theory is formed by its conception of the principal contradiction of capitalism, it is argued that Bourdieu’s theoretical system, which considers the holders of

economic and cultural capital as the principal competing poles of capitalism, is radically different from (and incompatible with) a theoretical system such as Marxism, which considers capital (as a relation of exploitation) and the working class as the principal competing poles of capitalism.

Bourdieu bases his theory of class determination mainly on the occupation of various species of capital (as ‘resources’ that give power) in relation to the quantity occupied, while he explicitly rejects the relations of production as a determining factor of class determination. The disconnection of the determination of social classes (of the ‘structural class positions’ or ‘class places’) from the relations of production and the absence of class criteria for class affiliation at the level of superstructure not contradicting the class definition on the economic level disconnect Bourdieu’s analysis from Marxism. In order to understand Bourdieu’s reasoning, the nature of the contradictions in which the social classes are involved or could be involved is examined. For this purpose, Bourdieu’s ‘class analysis’ is decoded in Marxist class analysis terms, and Bourdieu’s theoretical categories are submitted to Marxist concepts in an attempt to be, as much as possible, comparable. The emphasis of this class analysis is – from a Marxist perspective – on the classes of the capitalist mode of production (CMP) and superstructure, and especially on the new petty bourgeoisie and its sections and sub-sections (the new petty bourgeoisie of the CMP and the new petty bourgeoisie of the state, which is divided into the new petty bourgeoisie of the wider state and the new petty bourgeoisie of the ‘hard core’ of the state). The main subject of Chapter 3 is the decoding of Bourdieu’s ‘class analysis’ in Marxist class analysis terms, while the main subject of Chapter 4 is the potential ideological-political position of the new petty bourgeoisie (on the basis of distinction between structural class position and potential ideologicalpolitical class position). In relation to the research questions posed, it is investigated whether the new petty bourgeoisie (especially of the wider state) could be identified with (or be corresponded to) the ‘left hand of the state’ and ‘left-hand state’ in a matching of the Marxist analysis with Bourdieu’s analysis. Based on this investigation, we argue that there is a conscious limit of transformation of Bourdieu’s analysis which could be found in the context of a reformed capitalism of weakened neoliberalism, characterized by the existence, reproduction and mainly reinforcement – in the frame of capitalist reproduction – of anti-liberal sub-spaces located and limited within the state (the ‘left-hand state’). According to our approach, in Marxist political economy terms, this limit corresponds to the ‘delimited class strategy’ of the new petty bourgeoisie as a ‘class-for-itself’. In the frame of this strategy, the new petty bourgeoisie’s ‘anti-capitalism’ as ‘anti-capitalism’ within capitalism and the ‘reformist illusions’ of the new petty bourgeoisie are registered. However, there is also an implicit strategic direction in Bourdieu’s analysis that could expand the ‘reformist impulses’ and ‘reformist illusions’ of the intellectuals, especially of those of the ‘left hand of the state’ (i.e., of the new petty bourgeoisie, and in particular of the wider state). This implicit strategic direction – which is a historically exceptional class strategy corresponding to a ‘pseudo-autonomous class strategy’ of the new petty bourgeoisie in Marxist political economy terms – is the capitalist dictatorship of the mental labour and the ‘state capitalism’. This regime of ‘state capitalism’ is an extreme version of anti-neoliberal ‘anti-capitalism’ that reproduces capitalist exploitation.

Through this regime the ‘left-hand state’ expands to ‘occupy’ the entire state and the Bourdieusian ‘dichotomy’ of the ‘two states’ is abolished

Chapter 5 examines more specifically the Hegelian element of Bourdieu’s theoretical view of the state as the expression of ‘universal’ and his ambiguities concerning the class ‘bearer’ of this ‘universal’, that is, the ‘universal class’. In any case, Bourdieu’s theoretical view of the state as the expression and representation of the ‘universal’ as well as of the ‘universal class’ is at odds with the Marxist theory of the state as ‘a class state’.

The epilogue of this study searches for the elements of the class and political conjuncture in which a social-democratic (albeit peculiar) theoretical view emerged as far-left. It is concluded that Bourdieu’s theory has been regarded as a far-left theory – in conditions of retreat of the labour movement, devaluation of the anti-capitalist perspective and of the revolutionary role of the working class –since it offers an alternative to Marxism and an attractive perspective especially to the academics of the left (according to the second theoretical instance of his analysis), but also to the intellectuals in general (according to the first theoretical instance), as it gives them a prominent role in the historical process.

Notes

1 Riley (2017: 109 ff., 131 ff.), raises a broader question. As he argues, the influence of Bourdieu’s theory to academic sociology professionals (either Left or Right) is not justified by its validity as a macrosociology. ‘This imposes a serious puzzle. Since Bourdieu’s sociology does not offer a macrosociology, as it purports to, the attraction of his work must lie in a different direction’.

2 See, among other works on the 1995 French strikes, Howard 1998

References

Bourdieu, P. (1998) ‘Pour une gauche de gauche’, Le Monde, 08/04. Available online at le magasine de l’homme moderne, http://www.homme-moderne.org/societe/socio/bourdieu/ varia/pourgau.html

Howard, D. (1998) ‘The French Strikes of 1995 and their Political Aftermath’, Government and Opposition, 33(2): 199–220. Available online at: https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/44484090. pdf?refreqid=excelsior%3A655b6a3a8d498ac7bbd894540a779f64&ab_segments=&origin=. Loyal, S. (2017) Bourdieu’s Theory of the State: A Critical Introduction, New York: Palgrave – Macmillan.

Pallotta, J. (2015) ‘Bourdieu’s Engagement with Althusserian Marxism: The Question of the State’, Actuel Marx, 58(2): 130–43, English version: I–XV. Available online at: https:// www.cairn-int.info/journal-actuel-marx-2015-2-page-130.htm?WT.tsrc=cairnPdf .

Riley, D. (2017) ‘Bourdieu’s Class Theory: The Academic as Revolutionary’, Catalyst, 1(2): 107–36. Available online at: https://sociology.berkeley.edu/sites/default/files/faculty/ Riley/BourdieuClassTheory.pdf

Vandenberghe, F. (1999) ‘“The Real is Relational”: An Epistemological Analysis of Pierre Bourdieu’s Generative Structuralism’, Sociological Theory, 17(1): 32–67.

Wacquant, L. (2005) ‘Pointers on Pierre Bourdieu and Democratic Politics’, in L. Wacquant (ed.) Pierre Bourdieu and Democratic Politics: The Mystery of Ministry, Cambridge: Polity Press: 10–28.

1 ‘Capitals’, ‘fields’, dominant class, intellectuals and state

Aspects

of Bourdieu’s analysis

1.1 ‘Capitals’, ‘fields’ and classes

The concept of ‘capital’, in Bourdieu’s analysis, ‘refers to resources’ that a social ‘agent’ occupies, mainly in the forms of economic capital (income and ownership) and cultural capital (formal and informal education) (Riley 2017: 110).

The concept of ‘capital’ in Bourdieu’s analysis is related to the concept of ‘fields’.

Each power (or species of capital) dominates a specific field …; it can also be present in other fields but with less weight. … Within each field, agents may thus possess different species of capital, but the structure of the capital they possess varies between fields (employers have cultural capital, but less than intellectuals).

(Bourdieu 2020: 40)

As Bourdieu also argues,

The division into relatively autonomous fields is the outcome of a process of differentiation that … can be described as a process of institution of different spaces of play where specific forms of capital are engendered and actualized, and are both assets and characteristic stakes of each form of game. (ibid.: 33)

According to Riley (2017: 111), the concept of ‘fields’ in Bourdieu’s work refers to ‘agonistic social games in which agents struggle with one another over some socially defined stake, such as profit or prestige’, with the ‘economic field’, the ‘political field’,1 and the ‘field of cultural production’ to be among the most important.

‘Capital’ can be measured both as quantity (volume) and as structure. The ‘class position’2 is thus determined by ‘the volume and structure of capital’ that a social ‘agent’ occupies. According to Riley (2017: 110–11),

The primary class division in Bourdieu’s scheme is between those with high and low total capital, but within each of these classes there is a further difference between those with a greater proportion of either economic or cultural capital. The concept of capital is thus supposed to provide a map of the main social divisions in contemporary society.

DOI: 10.4324/9781003375401-2

Dominant class, intellectuals and state 7

However, Bourdieu (1996a: 106) maintains that

Social class is not defined by a property (not even the most determinant one, such as the volume and composition of capital) nor by a collection of properties … nor even by a chain of properties strung out from a fundamental property (position in the relations of production) in a relation of cause and effect, conditioner and conditioned; but by the structure of relations between all the pertinent properties which gives its specific value to each of them and to the effects they exert on practices.

This rather vague definition in Distinction (see Riley 2017: 113–4) which rejects the relations of production from the class determination,3 a point that underlines the sharp distinction between Bourdieu’s analysis and Marxism, as we will see in the following analysis, is simplified with an explanatory endnote, in which Bourdieu (1996a: 571) clarifies that

To construct the classes and class fractions on which the subsequent analyses are based, systematic account was taken not only of occupation and educational level … but also, in each case, of the available indices of the volume of the different sorts of capital, as well as age, sex and place of residence.

Therefore, class determination ‘bows’ to simplified criteria and statistically available data.

Besides these simplified criteria, and given that, according to Bourdieu, ‘class habitus, [is] the internalized form of class condition’ (ibid.: 101) – where ‘habitus’ is defined as ‘socially structured biological individualities’ – (Bourdieu 1996b: 53) it could be argued that ‘the structure of relations between all the pertinent properties’ is depicted in ‘habitus’,4 and thus, as Riley (2017: 111) argues,

habitus translates different class positions, specified by different forms of capital, into observable behavior.

Since ‘habitus translates’ (‘into observable behavior’) ‘different class positions, specified by different forms of capital’, it also follows, as Jameson (2008: 297) maintains, that

Cultural distinction then secures the recognition or acknowledgement of class position; and it is in this sense that Bourdieu proposes his most influential theoretical innovation, namely, the notion of cultural capital:5 what is accumulated as a result of the various practices of cultural distinction in education, clothing, tastes, and so forth.

A rather typical example of this ‘translation’ by ‘habitus’ is the relationship of the working class with fish-eating, according to Bourdieu (1996a: 190):

For example, in the working classes, fish tends to be regarded as an unsuitable food for men, not only because it is a light food, insufficiently ‘filling’, which

Dominant class, intellectuals and state

would only be cooked for health reasons, i.e., for invalids and children, but also because, like fruit (except bananas) it is one of the ‘fiddly’ things which a man’s hands cannot cope with and which make him childlike …; but above all, it is because fish has to be eaten in a way which totally contradicts the masculine way of eating, that is, with restraint, in small mouthfuls, chewed gently, with the front of the mouth, on the tips of the teeth (because of the bones).

As Wilkes (1990: 118) argues,

habitus … implies a logic of self-presentation tending towards a class habitus of social function. Thus, the shape of the male working-class body, at least in a modal sense, is orchestrated through the eating of certain foods … So, the relation between various forms of lifestyle and class practice at work has its links in the kind of manual work that the body is required to do. Failure to achieve that level of physical endeavour at work makes the individual marginal in the workplace.

However, such perceptions of ‘habitus’, according to Wilkes, do not exclude the quiche-eating intellectual carpenter, or the fish-eating ditch-digger, but at least require that such individuals pay attention sufficiently to their bodies to enable them to take their place in the economic world. (ibid.)

We overlook, at the moment, the implied identification of the working class with heavy manual labour. The problem is that arbitrary, stereotypical and non generalizable conceptions of the ‘habitus’ (tastes of the working class, in the above-mentioned example)6 are considered to be ‘unifying and generating principles’ with which classes are identified. Such an approach paves the way for a class determination, from ‘habitus’ (‘observable behavior’) to ‘different class positions’.

Thus, Bourdieu, considering the empiricism of ‘habitus’ as the basis of ‘an objectivist theory of class’, writes:

My goal in Distinction was to show that these habitus connected to positions in social space, and that these habitus, these tastes, were unifying and generating principles. For this I needed an objectivist theory of class, as in class theory.

(Honneth and Schwibs 1985, cited in Wilkes 1990: 113)

According to Wilkes (1990: 113), Bourdieu describes here his ‘objectivist conception of class in Distinction’. As Wilkes also argues, ‘habitus’, in Bourdieu’s ‘class analysis’, ‘is the link in the dialectic between objective and subjective components of class’ (ibid.: 116); while reviewing Bourdieu’s vague definition of social classes in Distinction, he maintains that,

Dominant class, intellectuals and state 9

there is no simple reading of dispositions from class here; rather, an ambiguous objectification of class … it is through ceaseless examples of the habitus, in its many elements – in its artistic components, in eating habits, in the dispositions of the body, in theatre-visiting (or not theatre-visiting), in a concern for music or no concern, in the political attitudes, the cars they drive, the men and women they marry, the sort of living rooms they construct – in all these ways, the lives of classes are drawn.

(ibid.: 130)

On the other hand, the ‘ambiguous objectification of class’ becomes a need ‘to be a break with the objectivism that goes hand-in-hand with intellectualism’. In this line of thought, Bourdieu rejects any economic determination of classes (the determination by the relations of production) and considering as ‘economism’ the determinant role of economy in ‘the social field’, he refuses the theoretical determination of classes, arguing that it leads to a ‘theoretical’ and not to ‘a real class’.

He writes:

the intellectualist illusion … leads one to consider the theoretical class, constructed by the sociologist, as a real class … there has to be a break with the economism that leads one to reduce the social field, a multi-dimensional space, solely to the economic field, to the relations of economic production, which are thus constituted as co-ordinates of social position … there has to be a break with the objectivism that goes hand-in-hand with intellectualism.

(Bourdieu 1985: 723)

The ‘break with the objectivism’ is interpreted by Wilkes (1990: 109–10) as a ‘fundamental break in the area of class analysis … with various forms of structuralism, in particular with Althusser and his formalistic conception of social class’. In this frame, ‘Bourdieu distinguishes his own approach to class apart from the categorising tendencies of Althusser’, while he also criticizes ‘conceptions of class determination predicated on economic domination, and, perhaps, at its limit, a conception of class which asserts the role of the “economic in the last instance”’. The issue of ‘economic in the last instance’ will be considered later in the analysis. As to Bourdieu’s ‘fundamental break’, we will see in the following analysis that it does not concern specifically ‘Althusserian structuralism’, but Marxism.

The ‘ambiguous objectification of class’ becomes open subjectivity when Bourdieu (1985: 741) argues that,

A class exists insofar – and only insofar – as mandated representatives endowed with plena potestas agenda [full power of action] can be and feel authorized to speak in its name – in accordance with the equation ‘the Party is the working class,’ or ‘the working class is the Party,’ … – and so to make it exist as a real force within the political field.

According to Wilkes (1990: 115),

Dominant class, intellectuals and state in this uneasy dialectic between subjectivity and objectivity, Bourdieu now moves to the subjectivist end by arguing … that it is in the naming of a class that a class is constituted. In this subjectivist parody, class and class action are taken to be a theatre, in which key vanguardist figures bring the play to life by asserting their right to ‘name a class’.

In the context of this ‘subjectivism’7 and ‘theatricalization’ of ‘class and class action’, the working class, as Bourdieu (1985: 742) argues,

is a ‘mystical body,’ created through an immense historical labor of theoretical and practical invention, starting with that of Marx himself, and endlessly re-created through the countless, constantly renewed, efforts and energies that are needed to produce and reproduce belief and the institution designed to ensure the reproduction of belief. It exists in and through the corps of mandated representatives who give it material speech and visible presence, and in the belief in its existence that this corps of plenipotentiaries manages to enforce, by its sheer existence and by its representations, on the basis of the affinities objectively uniting the members of the same ‘class on paper’ as a probable group.

Thus, according to Bourdieu’s ‘subjectivist’ determination of classes, the working class exists through the Party (obviously the Communist Party) and ‘through the corps of mandated representatives’; it is ‘a “mystical body”’ and a reproduction of a ‘belief’, which emanates from Marx’s analysis. Consequently, it is not ‘a real class’, but a ‘class on paper’ whose members are united as ‘a probable group’. Therefore, according to this line of thought, Bourdieu seems to deny that there is an objective structural class position, but only an illusory appearance of the working class ‘as a real force within the political field’.

Moreover, the ‘sighting’ of classes (and in particular of the working class) through the Party and ‘through the corps of mandated representatives’ brings to the fore the theoretical issue of determination of structural class positions (class places) by potential ideological-political class positions. The same problem arises, albeit indirectly and covertly, from the empiricism of ‘habitus’ as the basis of ‘an objectivist theory of class’.

Therefore in Bourdieu’s analysis, the objective class determination is obscured –either through the ‘ambiguous objectification of class’, in reality empiricism of ‘observable behavior’, as a supposed ‘dialectic between objective and subjective components of class’ (‘habitus’), or through the open ‘subjectivism’.

In The State Nobility, Bourdieu attempts to connect ‘habitus’ with ‘objective structures inherited from history’, arguing that – contrary to ‘the so-called “structuralist” view’, which ‘sees agents as being off on vacation and hence offside in the game in and through which structures are reproduced or transformed’ and ‘from the so-called “individualist” view that reintroduces agents into the picture, but agents who are reduced to the pure and interchangeable intentions of calculators

Dominant class, intellectuals and state 11

without a history’ – ‘the true logic of practices’ is to be found ‘in the relationship between habitus … and objective structures inherited from history’ (Bourdieu 1996b: 53). Wacquant (2005: 137) argues that: ‘It is this relation [between “habitus” and “objective structures”] that sociology must methodically construct anew by dissecting its terms as well as by reassembling their encounter in each of the various social games and sites it scrutinizes’. What is obscured here is that the former (‘habitus’) reveals the latter (‘objective structures’), concerning class determination – that is, the class determination is based on (the empiricism of) ‘habitus’. Inasmuch as ‘history’ and class ‘practices’ are not examined as a possible element of potential ideological-political class positions – which are structurally determined by the structural (objective) class positions – they will end up being considered as an element of absolute (historical) indeterminacy.

The relation of history, structural class positions and potential ideologicalpolitical class positions, as well as ‘the so-called “structuralist” view’ will be examined in the following analysis along with other important aspects of Bourdieu’s ‘class analysis’, which will be introduced later in the analysis and will be examined critically from the point of view of a Marxist theory of social classes. We will see then that it is Marxist political economy that breaks with both ‘individualist’ ahistoricality and historical indeterminacy. Thus, Bourdieu’s rupture with Marxism could be more understandable, for which he considers that

nowadays no doubt represents the most powerful obstacle to the progress of the adequate theory of the social world, to which it has, in other times, contributed more than any other.

(Bourdieu 1985: 742)

1.2 Dominant class and ‘field of power’

According to Bourdieu (1996a: 260),

the dominant class constitutes a relatively autonomous space whose structure is defined by the distribution of economic and cultural capital among its members, each class fraction being characterized by a certain configuration of this distribution to which there corresponds a certain life-style, through the mediation of the habitus.

Putting the issue briefly, it could be argued that the dominant class is ‘defined loosely’ by Bourdieu as the class whose members hold a relatively high amount of economic and/or cultural capital (Riley 2017: 113) – while the empiricism of ‘habitus’ reveals the exact positions of its members, and creates the distinctiveness of the dominant class, that is, its ‘relatively autonomous space’. The dominant class contains teachers, civil servants, professionals, engineers, managers and the heads of industry and of commerce (see Bourdieu 1977). It is divided into two fractions, or sections, or poles: the holders (predominantly) of economic capital (the heads of industry and commerce occupy the higher position of this fraction) and the holders (predominantly) of cultural capital (the higher civil servants of the state

Dominant class, intellectuals and state

bureaucracy and the professors in higher education occupy the higher position of this fraction) (see Weininger 2002: 94; Loyal 2017: 85–6). As Bourdieu (1977:501) argues, ‘the heads of industry’, that is, the holders of economic capital, constitute ‘the dominant section’. Consequently, the holders of cultural capital constitute the dominated fraction, or section, or pole of the dominant class. In general, there is a domination ‘of the richer fraction in economic capital over the richer fraction in cultural capital’ (Bourdieu 2020: 35). Therefore, economic capital is the dominant form of capital. However, this domination entails a dynamic of conflict.

Loyal (2017: 87) argues that,

According to Bourdieu, the opposition between economic and cultural capital is an old, almost quasi-universal binary part of a division of labour of domination. This division is … [depicted] in … [the] distinction between … temporal power and cultural power.

However, ‘“temporal powers”’ are ‘the state, the economy, the military, etc.’ (Steinmetz 2014: 3). These powers are not purely economic or cultural. There is, therefore, a permeation of cultural capital – and thus of ‘cultural power’ – to ‘temporal power’, rather than an absolute division between economic and cultural capital. This is why it could be only ‘predominance’ and not ‘exclusiveness’ in the holding of economic or cultural capital in the positions of domination. Besides, according to Bourdieu, as we have seen above, ‘Each power (or species of capital) dominates a specific field’ but ‘it can also be present in other fields but with less weight’ while ‘employers have [also] cultural capital, but less than intellectuals’.

Based on his notion that the dominant class consists of those who hold (‘possess’) a relatively high amount of economic and/or cultural capital, Bourdieu (2020: 34) argues that

[t]he field of power is defined as the space of the positions from which power is exerted over capital in its different species. One must indeed distinguish between the mere possession of (say, economic or cultural) capital and the possession of a capital conferring power over capital, meaning over the very structure of a field, and therefore, among other fields, over profit rates, and by extension, over all ordinary holders of capital. … As membership in the field of power is defined not by the personal possession of a parcel of capital … but by the possession of a sufficient quantity of capital to dominate in one field or another, the dominant class comprises all agents that in effect hold the positions of power over capital, meaning over the very functioning of a field or over that field’s system of instruments of reproduction.

Therefore, according to Bourdieu (1995: 215), in distinction to the various ‘fields’,

[t]he field of power is the space of relations of force between agents or between institutions having in common the possession of the capital necessary to occupy the dominant positions in different fields (notably economic or cultural).

The ‘field of power’ is constituted by the articulation of ‘dominant positions in different fields’ and ‘notably economic or cultural’. Since ‘[t]he field of power is the space of relations of force’ of the ‘dominant positions in different fields’, it is the ‘space’ of the dominant class, that is, the dominant class occupies the ‘field of power’. Since the state, as we will see below, is a specific ‘sector’ of the ‘field of power’, it is also the ‘space’ of the dominant class.

According to Loyal (2017: 86),

When viewed as a totality the field of power appears to include those social agents endowed with high levels of economic and cultural capital.

As Wacquant (2019: 18) maintains, on the basis of Bourdieu’s analysis, ‘the field of power’ ‘is really not a field’ but it is ‘a meta-field’

The ‘field of power’ is ‘structurally determined by the state’ (a critical position for the role that Bourdieu assigns to the state) and, in its totality, not only encompasses the dominant class, but it is also a field of struggles between its sections (Weininger 2002: 85–6).

According to Bourdieu (1996b: 264–5),

The field of power is a field of forces structurally determined by the state of the relations of power among forms of power, or different forms of capital. It is also, and inseparably, a field of power struggles among the holders of different forms of power, a gaming space in which these agents and institutions possessing enough specific capital (economic or cultural capital in particular) to be able to occupy the dominant positions within their respective fields confront each other using strategies aimed at preserving or transforming these relations of power. The forces that can be enlisted in these struggles, and the orientation given to them, be it conservative or subversive, depend on what might be called the ‘exchange rate’ (or ‘conversion rate’) that obtains among the different forms of capital, in other words, on the very thing that these strategies aim to preserve or transform.

Nevertheless, what is the object of the struggle, of ‘[t]he forces that can be enlisted in these struggles’, ‘over the “conversion’ or “exchange rate” between different forms of capital’?

As Bourdieu argues, there is a struggle over the power to dictate the dominant principle of domination, which leads to a constant state of equilibrium in the partition of power, in other words, to a division in the labor of domination … [which] is also a struggle over the legitimate principle of legitimation and, inseparably, the legitimate mode of reproduction of the foundations of domination.

(ibid.: 265)

As Loyal maintains,

Dominant class, intellectuals and state

The field of forces is … a space where those with high levels of economic, or cultural capital, or both struggle over the imposition of the dominant form of capital in social space – the ‘dominant principle of domination’, and simultaneously, the mechanisms aimed at maintaining or altering these forms of capital – the ‘dominant principle of legitimation’ – … There is thus a struggle within the dominant class fractions in social space, rather than between social classes – for example, the dominant class and working class, over the ‘conversion’ or ‘exchange rate’ between different forms of capital.

(Loyal 2017: 86; see also Weininger 2002: 94)

Given the above, rather ‘loosely’ defined theoretical notions, it could be inferred that:

• The principal contradiction of the social system (capitalism) is defined ‘within the dominant class fractions in social space’ (and thus within the ‘field of power’ and within the state). This principal contradiction is the opposition between economic and cultural capital.

• The opposition between economic and cultural capital is expressed in the struggles ‘over the imposition of the dominant form of capital in social space’ (‘over the power to dictate the dominant principle of domination’), therefore in the social system.

• These struggles ‘depend on what might be called the “exchange rate” (or “conversion rate”) that obtains among the different forms of capital’ (‘economic or cultural capital in particular’).

• The struggle ‘over the “conversion’ or “exchange rate”’ is a struggle over the ‘strategies’ or ‘mechanisms’ ‘aimed at preserving’ (‘maintaining’) or ‘transforming’ (‘altering’) the dominant form of capital in specific fields and, primarily, in ‘social space’, therefore in the social system, and depends on the correlation of power (of the ‘relations of power’), between different forms of capital (‘economic or cultural capital in particular’) ‘in the division of labour of domination’

• This struggle determines ‘the legitimate principle of legitimation’ or ‘the “dominant principle of legitimation”’, and thus ‘the legitimate mode of reproduction of the foundations of domination’.

• The ‘legitimate’ or ‘“dominant principle of legitimation”’ (that is, the legitimation of domination) is related to the question: What is the significant, the prominent form of capital (‘in the division of labour of domination’) for the preservation or transformation of the dominant form of capital in the social system?

Therefore, the ultimate object of the struggle, ‘over the “conversion’ or “exchange rate” between different forms of capital’ (‘economic or cultural capital in particular’) is the legitimation of domination – that is, the legitimation of ‘the imposition of the dominant principle of domination’ (see below) or the legitimation of ‘the imposition of the dominant form of capital in social space’ – which is related to the emergence of that form of capital which is the significant, the prominent form of capital (‘in the division of labour of domination’) for the preservation or transformation of the dominant form of capital in the social system. This issue is clarified and analyzed in the following analysis.

1.3 ‘Organic solidarity’ and the increasing importance of the ‘general bureaucratic training’

According to Bourdieu, as we have seen, the struggle ‘over the power to dictate the dominant principle of domination’ ‘leads to a constant state of equilibrium in the partition of power’. Therefore, the opposition between economic and cultural capital does not break the unity of the dominant class (‘the organic solidarity that unites’ its ‘fractions’).

Bourdieu (2020: 35) writes:

the organic solidarity that unites the fractions of the dominant classes insofar as they contribute to domination … does not preclude the permanent struggle for the imposition of the dominant principle of domination, and at the same time, for the conservation or transformation of the structure of power within the field of power (especially today, through the conservation or transformation of the structure of the field of educational institutions in charge of the reproduction of the dominant class).

As Loyal (2017: 87–8) points out,

Since Bourdieu believes that no power can be based on naked force alone, in modern … societies there operates an organic solidarity in the division of labour of domination whereby the dominant groupings in the social order must wield several different forms of power to consolidate their social position.

Bourdieu especially highlights today’s significance of the struggle within the field of educational institutions (as a part of the struggle within the ‘field of power’) indicating thus the significance for the dominant fraction of the dominant class (the holders of economic capital) of the alliance with the dominated fraction of the dominant class (the holders of cultural capital), for the legitimation of domination –that is, for the legitimation of ‘the imposition of the dominant principle of domination’.

In this connection Bourdieu (2020: 35–6) writes:

Since the dominant class has to reproduce, i.e., reproduce as dominant and as legitimate in dominating … and since … the question of the internal divisions of the dominant class cannot be separated from the question of the legitimization of power and of the division of the labour of domination, the holders of cultural capital … intellectuals, although they are inevitably dominated in the struggle for power … nevertheless have a significant advantage in the strictly symbolic struggle over the imposition of the dominant principle of domination.

Thus, there is ‘a dualist power structure’ which corresponds to the two fractions of the dominant class, since ‘force needs to be expended to produce law; economic capital must be expended to produce symbolic capital’ (or ‘symbolic

16 Dominant class, intellectuals and state power’) (ibid.: 36).8 ‘Symbolic capital’ (or ‘symbolic power’) is an ‘invisible power’ (Bourdieu 1984: 164) that could be understood – according to Loveman (2005: 1655) – as ‘the ability to make appear as natural, inevitable, and thus apolitical, that which is a product of historical struggle and human invention’ (see also Riley 2017: 120). This ability concerns the legitimation of domination through ‘consent’.

On this basis, Riley maintains that the notion ‘of symbolic power closely parallels the French Marxist Louis Althusser’s theory of ideology’ (ibid.). Since ‘symbolic capital’ (or ‘symbolic power’) aims to the legitimation of domination, the role of the holders of cultural capital, as the ‘agents’ who are the ‘bearers’ (or ‘carriers’) of ‘symbolic’ capital or power and thus of the legitimation of domination, ‘have a significant advantage’.

Higher education institutions, especially the Grandes Écoles in France, play a major role in ‘the disciplining of minds’ (Bourdieu 1996b: 11 ff.) and thus a key role in the reproduction of the dominated fraction of the dominant class – in terms of Bourdieusian analysis – and specifically of ‘the directing instances of capital’ (which, according to Poulantzas, belong to the ‘bourgeoisie’ in Marxist terms – see in the following analysis). This means that there is a predetermination of future structural class positions or class places by the educational system – along with class barriers in upward class mobility which reproduces class continuity, as we will see below.

According to Poulantzas (1976: 249, see also 264, 270),

the Grandes Écoles … prepare their students for what is considered ‘polyvalent’ work, requiring an overview of the economy; … most of them soon occupy managerial and administrative positions they then often belong to the directing instances of capital (to the bourgeoisie).

Within the ‘dualist power structure’ the correlation of power ‘in the division of labour of domination’ within the dominant class – and especially within the dominated fraction of the dominant class, that is, the holders of cultural capital – has shifted especially in favour of those of general bureaucratic training. This is a development which concerns and underscores the growing role of the legitimation of domination ‘in the division of labour of domination’, through ‘consent’.

As Bourdieu (1996b: 272) argues,

it can be posited at the outset that the entire logic of the struggle for power over forms of power was modified by the two great changes that affected the dominant modes of reproduction, which, already discernible within the field of establishment schools, must now be grasped within the field of power itself, that is, in the competitive struggles that set the holders of the different forms of capital against each other, particularly within the administrative and economic fields. They are, on the one hand, the increase in the relative importance of academic titles (whether coupled with property or not) with respect to property titles, even in the economic field; on the other hand, among the bearers of cultural capital, the decline of technical titles to the advantage of titles guaranteeing general bureaucratic training.

Dominant class, intellectuals and state 17

Thus, ‘[t]he contemporary struggle between businessmen (industrial knights) and intellectuals’ as it, according to Bourdieu’s analysis, ‘has … been shaped by two fundamental developments, especially within the administrative and economic field, that have taken place in the struggle “for power over power”’, results to alteration of ‘the exchange rate between the different forms of capital’ in favour of cultural capital, and specifically of the cultural capital of the state bureaucracy (Loyal 2017: 88). These ‘two great changes’, in Bourdieu’s terminology, ‘affected the dominant modes of reproduction’, having affected ‘the legitimate principle of legitimation’. This underlines the specific gravity of cultural capital, its prominent role in the preservation or transformation of the dominant form of capital, and thus the prominent role of the intellectuals, in (the ‘strategies’ or ‘mechanisms’ of) ‘preserving’ (‘maintaining’) or ‘transforming’ (‘altering’) the dominant form of capital in the social system.

Thus, except for ‘the “intellectual” schools (the École normale supérieure and, to a lesser extent, the École polytechnique) and, at the other end, the schools which groom for economic power (the École des hautes études commerciales and other graduate business schools) … a school like the École nationale d’administration, which opens the way to positions of leadership within state bureaucracies’ (Wacquant 1993: 22) obtains an increased specific gravity in the formation, according to Loyal, of ‘a state bourgeoisie’:9

The process of elite reproduction not only entails creating a ‘business bourgeoisie’ who will hold power over positions in large firms, but through the École nationale d’ administration, the generation of a state bourgeoisie, some of whom will undoubtedly hold positions in large state-owned businesses while others, will take up positions in the higher civil service or become central wielders of power in the administrative or bureaucratic field, that is, the state.

(Loyal 2017: 91)

The intervention of the state in the upgrading of the intellectuals and in the creation not only of an intellectual ‘business bourgeoisie’ but also of an intellectual ‘state bourgeoisie’ is crucial. In this connection, the state sets ‘the conversion rate between capitals’, that is, it intervenes to the ‘strategies’ or ‘mechanisms’ ‘aimed at ‘preserving’ (‘maintaining’) or ‘transforming’ (‘altering’) the dominant form of capital. Thus, as Loyal also argues,

It is here that the state, as the administrative field located between the two poles, plays a central role not only by setting the conversion rate between capitals but also through the provision of titles specifically viz-a-viz the grandes écoles, by consecrating individuals.

(ibid.: 88)

However, since ‘the conversion rate between capitals’ depends on the correlation of power (of the ‘relations of power’), between different forms of capital ‘in the division of labour of domination’, the state ‘setting the conversion rate between capitals’ intervenes also in the correlation of power between different forms of capital.

18

Dominant class, intellectuals and state

The ‘significant advantage’ of intellectuals, especially of the state bureaucracy intellectuals, in the ‘organic solidarity in the division of labour of domination’ – within the frame of the ‘dualist power structure’ – underlines, according to Bourdieu (2020: 40–1), that it is impossible for a single agent to possess all the properties that make domination possible; or, which boils down to the same thing, there is no such thing as a single hierarchy ranking agents in all respects.

The above highlights the important role of ‘consent’ – and therefore the prominent social role of the intellectuals, and especially of the state bureaucracy intellectuals, – in Bourdieu’s analysis.

1.4 The ‘priority’ of ‘consent’

The prominent role of cultural capital in the preservation or transformation of the dominant form of capital is expressed in the rising importance of intellectuals, especially of the state bureaucracy intellectuals of general bureaucratic training, in the ‘organic solidarity in the division of labour of domination’ which could be seen in Bourdieu’s analysis concerning the ‘priority’ of ‘consent’, generated by the ‘symbolic capital’ (or ‘symbolic power’), over ‘physical violence’.

According to Bourdieu (2014: 3–4), the ‘state’ is ‘the sector of the field of power which may be called the “administrative field” or the “field of public office”’ which ‘is defined by possession of the monopoly of legitimate physical and symbolic violence’. However,

the state is one of the principles of public order; and public order is not simply the police and the army … – monopoly of physical violence. Public order rests on consent.

(ibid.: 8, see also 52)

Although the formulation ‘the state is one of the principles of public order; and public order is not simply the police and the army’ is rather ambiguous, it could be inferred that, from the point of view that ‘[p]ublic order rests on consent’, the state is seen as the ‘“central bank of symbolic capital”’, ‘the state is a symbolic power’ (ibid.: 122–3; see also Loyal 2017: 119), it ‘is the site par excellence of the concentration and exercise of symbolic power’, since it ‘possesses the means of imposition and inculcation of the durable principles of vision and division that conform to its own structure’ (Bourdieu 1998a: 47).

Moreover, as Bourdieu (1996b: 383) argues,

in contrast to raw power, which acts according to mechanical efficiency, all genuine power acts as symbolic power.

The above means that ‘the state maintains relations of domination principally through cultural and symbolic rather than physical and material means’ (Loyal

Dominant class, intellectuals and state 19 2017: 110, see also 114–15), that is, there is a ‘priority’ of ‘consent’, generated by the ‘symbolic capital’ (or ‘symbolic power’) (ibid.: 68), over ‘physical violence’ in ‘the monopoly of legitimate physical and symbolic violence’. Moreover, according to Loyal, Bourdieu does not simply give a ‘priority’ to ‘symbolic violence’, but ‘downplays the significance of physical violence as an autonomous force in social life’ (ibid.: 129). As we have seen above, Riley maintains that ‘symbolic power’ is a notion that ‘closely parallels the French Marxist Louis Althusser’s theory of ideology’. Pallotta also argues that there is a resemblance of Bourdieu’s ‘symbolic power’ with Althusser’s ‘ideological power’, adding that ‘both stem from the same observation: that the reproduction of the social order cannot be explained by “fear of the gendarme,” but supposes the operation of a type of power other than the repressive’ (Pallotta 2015: V).10 Yet, despite any resemblance that Pallotta refers to, Althusser, as we will see in the following analysis, does not downplay ‘the significance of physical violence’ for the reproduction of the system of domination (as Pallotta rather suggests), as Bourdieu does.

1.5 The rejection of the ‘dichotomy’ between economic base and superstructure

On the basis of ‘priority’ of ‘symbolic power’ and opposed to ‘the tendency of Marxism to reduce forms of domination to the most brutal aspects of domination, to military force’ (Bourdieu 2014: 161), Bourdieu rejects the ‘dichotomy’ ‘between infrastructure and superstructure’ (ibid.: 193), introducing

the idea that there are forms of domination that are perfectly gentle, associated with the highest accomplishments of humanity. These forms of domination, which a certain philosophical tradition calls symbolic, are so fundamental that I find myself wondering whether a social order could function, even in its economic foundations, without the existence of these forms of domination. In other words, the old model of infrastructure and superstructure – a model that has done a lot of harm in social science – must be rejected, or, if you insist on keeping it, it must at least be turned upside down.

(ibid.: 161)

Thus, for Bourdieu, as Loyal (2017: 44) maintains, the base superstructure model where the ideological superstructure is determined by an economic base … needs to be rejected, or at least reversed so that the symbolic realm predominates, while Pallotta (2015: VII) argues that by defining symbolic capital as the ultimate foundation of power, as ‘last instance’ of the instances of the social whole … Bourdieu claims to distinguish himself from Marxism and its superstructure/infrastructure topic.

20

Dominant class, intellectuals and state

Thus, Bourdieu develops a theoretical scheme of replacement of the economic base by ‘symbolic’ capital or power. Furthermore, and on the basis of his rejection of base-superstructure ‘dichotomy’, Bourdieu (following a rather crude interpretation of ‘Marxist definition’ of the state) argues that the state ‘is not simply the universalization of the particular interest of the dominant, which manages to impose itself on the dominated (the orthodox Marxist definition). … The oppositions that the state produces are not a superstructure’ (Bourdieu 2014: 183), that is, the oppositions produced by the state are unrelated to the economic base. The issue of ‘universalization’ will be discussed later in the analysis.

1.6 The struggles within the dominated fraction of the dominant class: ‘left hand of the state’ and ‘right hand of the state’

Despite ‘the organic solidarity that unites the fractions of the dominant classes’, it occasionally happens that members of the dominant class act against their class interests (linked to their position in the field of power) when those contradict their fractional interests (linked to their position in a specific field); [thus] … the effects of the struggles for domination within the dominant class can come to threaten the foundations of their domination over other classes. This is the case when, in their struggle for domination within a specific field, some agents call for the support of an external force. Among holders of cultural capital, for instance, those who hold a dominated position within the field of cultural production can thus forge permanent or occasional alliances with members of the dominated classes, thereby placing their cultural capital at the service of struggles that they identify more or less completely and durably with their own struggles within the field of power.

(Bourdieu 2020: 39)

Thus, there are struggles ‘within the dominant class fractions’ against dominant class interests when the latter contradict fractional ones, which could ‘threaten’ the domination of the dominant class. Bourdieu’s argument highlights the division of the dominant class in two distinct fractions – each one with its particular interests. Bourdieu mentions specifically conflicts within the field of cultural production which could lead to social ‘subversive alliances’ between ‘agents’ of the ‘dominated positions’ of the dominated fraction of the dominant class – who ‘symbolically abandon the camp of the dominants’ – and dominated classes, when ‘agents’ of the former ‘call for the support of an external force’ – that is the dominated classes –‘placing’ or ‘engaging’ ‘their cultural capital at the service of struggles’ that they ‘identify with their own struggles in the field of power’.

Bourdieu (1996b: 387) specifically writes:

It thus may happen that the interests associated with the dominated positions in the field of cultural production lead to subversive alliances, capable of threatening the social order. This occurs when, in the cognitive struggles over the social world, the professional producers of principles of vision and

Another random document with no related content on Scribd:

whispering he was privileged to answer “Perfect.” Now, in fact, the pupils formed cliques and agreements to such an extent that they made almost a complete farce of this attempt at discipline. They lied with the greatest liberty and seemed to feel no restraint from their principal. He appeared not to know that they were guilty of deception and insubordination, and of course he became the butt of ridicule because of these and many other unwise acts.

The girls would be found by him crying over the low grades they received. Through their hands they joyously watched him as he marched back to his desk and silently changed the numerals. Occasionally he returned and reported, “After thinking over your work further I have decided to give you a better grade.” He was more than paid for his trouble as the smiles drove back the tears and the eyes of the poor, grieved ones hung for a moment on his.

He suffered from note-writing. Jim was a source of anxiety on this score. The unvarying procedure was the following:

“Where is the paper you had a moment ago?”

“It’s in my desk.”

“Is there any writing on it?”

“Yes, I think so.”

“Hand it to me.”

Silence on Jim’s part.

“Jim, aren’t you going to give me that note?”

“No, sir.”

“Jim, you go at once to Mr. Evans’ room,” or, “Take your books and go home.”

Not once, nor twice, but scores and scores of times this same routine was followed. Jim never handed him a note in the whole two years. Mr. Bradley never discovered the intense satisfaction that Jim had in drawing attention to himself, in defeating the principal and in thus creating a general sensation.

Mr. Bradley’s temper was easily aroused. At first his face would turn white; the pupils quickly noted his pallor and laughed at him; his anger then drove him to a few tears, which one by one trickled down his careworn cheeks.

In these moments of ill-temper he was more helpless than ever. He did not attempt to do much teaching for a short period, but marked time until he could recollect himself and get his pedagogical machine back on track again.

In the frequent, extreme cases of refractory pupils that he had to dispose of, his main resort was to send or accompany pupils to Mr. Evans, the superintendent of schools. In reporting the misdemeanor or in remarking on the items of a report of misconduct by the pupil himself he adopted the very poor method of exaggerating the circumstances insufferably. Often he interrupted a pupil’s account with single words or phrases that exaggerated the offense and so attempted to justify himself in referring the case to higher authority. These unfair methods enraged even a guilty pupil to an extent that all hope of his returning to the high school room with any little good will toward the principal was lost.

You at once inquire, How was it possible for a man of this sort to keep his position for two years? The answer is two-fold: his treatment of pupils and citizens generally outside of school hours was such as, in a way, to discredit the impressions reported by dissatisfied pupils; the superintendent was capable enough himself to neutralize, in part, the ill effects of the principal’s poor disciplinary methods and thus to enable him to retain a well informed instructor.

You want to know more about this remarkable superintendent, Mr. Evans? His personal presence was somewhat in his favor. He was a man of good height, but very slender. The look of his eye was direct and lingering. His hand-grasp was warm, kindly and reassuring. He was never in a hurry, but disposed of mountains of work. He always took time to hear all that pupils had to say—one of his strongest assets.

It was a valuable lesson in school discipline just to observe him in an interview with an offending pupil.

“Well, Jim, what is it this morning?”

“I suppose I’ve got to tell you about a little affair that occurred in the Latin class yesterday.”

“Come and have this chair over here by the desk. Excuse me until I pull down the shade a bit. Well, now, go on. What is it all about?”

But these cold words do not convey to the reader the impression that they made on Jim. There was a yearning in the voice that fairly drew Jim out of himself. He had just come from a fresh combat with Mr. Bradley and was in a mood to do battle; in fact, strange to say, this thought crossed his mind, “All right, I’ll go in to see Evans. If he has it in for me, I’ll show them both a new deal; I’ll give them the time of their lives in this town!”

How easy it would have been to set fire to this piece of tow and so produce an uncontrollable conflagration. But there was Mr. Evans’ voice, so suave and appealing. He assumed that Jim had something interesting to tell; that he had suffered some accident; that he was in search of a friend. Mr. Evans was that friend. He said, “You know, of course, that I’ll want to hear the other side of the story, but you go ahead and tell me everything just exactly as it is.”

Jim told his story. The superintendent nodded assent to the several statements, indicating that he had taken in their full significance and was laying the ground for a just disposition of the matter. About the time Jim finished, Mr. Bradley stepped in. He soon began his account of the affair. Mr. Evans listened with a judicial air, by no means disclosing any antagonism toward his principal, but very cautious not to give Jim any notion that the principal had the inside track in the mind and sympathy of his superior. There were no comments, no nodding of the head, no knowing smiles that meant, “We’ll fix this fellow, all right.”

Since Mr. Evans had previously frankly said that he would hear the principal’s story, in the first part of the interview, Jim was not surprised that it was given unremitting attention. But he was highly pleased to see that favoritism for the principal was not going to play any part in the final settlement of the matter.

In fact, every pupil expected to see Mr. Evans go the second mile in any case where he came intimately into contact with a pupil, either in the ordinary affairs of the school, or when disciplinary problems must be adjudicated. It was, in a way, a painful experience to meet Mr. Evans under circumstances such as these; he made one feel grieved to impose on him by wrenching his heart with disappointment. There was no fear of consequences, but an anguish over injuring the feelings of the superintendent.

When the facts were all before him, this friend of boys and girls would say:

“I don’t believe it would be right in this case to ...” and he would mention penalties that were severe, though perhaps often employed by other teachers, perhaps were even not condemned by the community. He would finally come to the conclusion of the matter by saying:

“I think we can fix this up in this way ...” a method that was almost without exception such as to strengthen the discipline of the school, to rescue the pupil from provoking circumstances and probably to serve as a deterrent to future misconduct.

At the conclusion of every case of discipline, Mr. Evans left the situation in a better status than before. The boy or girl who had to settle accounts with the superintendent, when all was said and done, knew that the issue was disposed of according to the principles of right and for the good of both the pupil and the school. Wisdom, sympathetic understanding, willingness to make concessions, positive devotion to the pupil’s comfort and welfare, were written all over the man’s actions so plainly as to disarm criticism and to bind every pupil to him as a life-long friend.

Throughout this Course for teachers, we have steadily laid emphasis on the need in the pupil for the cultivation of self-control as a basis for any satisfactory building of character. Scarcely less have we insisted that the same trait of character is essential in a successful teacher. Our survey of the blunders of disciplinarians leads to the conclusion that by far the larger part committed by school teachers can be traced back to an inexcusable lack of this central virtue of self-control.

The passionate, selfish teacher can not see the pupil’s point of view. The measureless transformations of the adolescent period throw a vast majority of people out of sympathy with the adolescent and still more with those of younger years.

The system of school discipline advocated in this Course for teachers, frankly rests on coöperation with the pupil, initiative being taken by the teacher in working out disciplinary problems in frank, wholehearted adjustment to pupil needs and characteristics. No teacher can adopt the policy represented by this principle without

attaining, in a measure, and further developing his own self-control. Our experience and observation, our fresh survey of all the facts while compiling the data presented in these volumes, have deepened immeasurably the conviction that the teacher who seeks the level of the life of the children whom he wishes to govern, assisting them, aiding them, guiding them according to the dictates of their natures rather than contrariwise, will cure himself of one of his own worst vices, namely, anarchy in mood, temper and judgment; and will develop in its place the basic element of a noble character, selfcontrol.

By presenting, as a final word, the contrast between these two teachers, we hope to heighten the impressions that have repeatedly been made as the reader has followed the narratives and discussions contained in the preceding pages. Remember that the two men here described worked under the same circumstances, during the same two years, with the same pupils, in the same building; that each had the benefit of consultation with the other, that both were well received in public and had many friends among the business men and in the homes of the city. The advantage in physical organization lay with him who failed. The essential difference between the two is found in the inner, basic attitude of each toward his pupils.

The one ruled by personality and broad, humane principles; the other was an apostle of force, fitfully administered, as, in fact, it must of necessity be administered. The one was conscious of his authority; the other forgot it and worked man to man with his pupils. The one exhausted his force and failed; the other scarcely ever drew upon his reserve and never lost a pupil friend. The one ground his teeth in rage at the perversity and rebellion of his pupils, the other enjoyed their friendship and reveled in the memories of sympathetic appreciation of his labors. In short, one was beloved by all, the other despised.

Of all the words from tongue or pen that explain the more desirable of the two methods described, none is better than the word Coöperation. This is the capstone of our five fundamental principles —Suggestion, Substitution, Expectation, Approval, Coöperation. Approval of good effort, in fact, turns out to be one mode of coöperation with the pupil. It ministers to his self-love and elicits further effort. A teacher can not exemplify this one principle of

coöperation without hitting upon or consciously employing all the others we have named and illustrated. “I work with my pupils,” is the highest self-praise a teacher can utter. It is a simple, modest, unassuming statement; if true in its deepest sense, he who thus speaks of himself is a perfect teacher and disciplinarian.

We commend this gospel to coöperative school-room discipline to every aspiring teacher who reads these volumes; we can only hope that every one may be converted heart and soul to this mode of action and with religious devotion set about remoulding his treatment and management of school children so that he truly may be a Friend to Man.

INDEX

Absences, 764

Acquisitiveness, 309

Adaptive instincts, 361

Adenoids, 58

Altruism, 586, 727

Anti-social tendencies, 672

Approval, 51, 55, 58, 61, 92, 103, 108, 132, 137, 139, 147, 161, 171, 181, 190, 201, 210, 213, 222, 235, 244, 266, 272, 277, 294, 303, 376, 388, 394, 401, 411, 415, 422, 440, 448, 450, 486, 507, 519, 588, 595, 662, 735, 774, 868

Athletics, aid in discipline, 96, 405, 530, 726, 737, 739, 740, 831

cheating for sake of, 284, 289 fights in, 249

Attention, desire to attract, 23, 50 in school work, 55, 368, 554

Authority, excessive use of, 81, 94, 95, 183, 220, 634, 644, 661, 697, 860

Awkwardness, 61, 141, 143, 148

Bluffing by teacher, cause of disobedience, 121, 536

Boy and girl question, 839

Bullying, 233

Card-playing, 115

Carelessness, 83, 562, 567, 765, 801

Cheating, on examination, 269 how provoked, 268 in recitation, 273 sentiment against, 269, 282

Chewing gum, 388

Choice and disobedience, 31

Church-going, 817

Cigarettes, 402

Class rivalry, 253

Cleanliness, 76, 449

Cliques, 471, 474, 717

Cloaks and overcoats, 79

Clumsiness, 140, 148

Collections of curios, 70, 209, 236, 310, 311, 502

Commands, how to give, attention to be secured, 55 be near child, 50 choose what child wants to do, 51 privately given, 60, 103 repetition to be avoided, 55 rights of pupil to be conserved, 93 speak intelligibly, 53, 753 time to be opportune, 72

Community, understanding conditions in, 43, 775

Companions, choosing, 321, 474, 812, 841, 843

Competition, leading to fighting, 249

Conceit, 192

Confession by pupil, 73, 101, 163, 212, 242, 294, 302, 308, 309, 340, 565, 568, 837 by teacher, 124

Confidence, 31, 32, 52, 60, 68, 71, 85, 89, 96, 105, 116, 121, 150, 167, 196, 201, 209, 212, 266, 299, 376, 406, 496, 499, 642, 667, 776

Conspiracy, 106, 378, 384, 464, 536, 695

Conventionalities, submission to, 803

Coöperation, initiative in, 45, 50, 60, 70, 74, 79, 81, 82, 87, 91, 96, 103, 108, 114, 119, 124, 142, 149, 158, 160, 162, 165, 171, 181, 190, 198, 201, 203, 209, 213, 222, 231, 241, 243, 256, 262, 265, 282, 313, 317, 320, 337, 372, 386, 392, 396, 397, 410, 416, 420, 424, 447, 467, 478, 492, 503, 508, 569, 637, 662, 711, 718, 738, 772, 797, 819, 824, 842, 866, 868

Coughing epidemics, 380

Crying, 257

Curiosity, 549

Dancing 111, 831

Defamation of a teacher, causing disobedience, 65

Defying a teacher 69, 70, 73, 99, 101, 106, 111, 118, 123, 168, 173, 180, 183, 189, 195, 199, 202, 208, 220, 762, 774, 809, 862

Desk order, 77

Destruction of property, 89, 254, 644, 647, 649

Disciplinarian, description of, a 17

Discipline, kinds of, 19

Discipline, what it is, 16 why necessary, 13

Dislike for school, 158, 162, 860

Disobedience, causes of, 41 community sentiment, contravened, 110 due to commands impossible to obey, 56

that are inopportune, 72 that infringe personal rights, 93 unintelligibly stated, 53 due to community conditions, 44 due to defective motor functions, 61 due to faultfinding, 89 due to imitation of others, 69 due to inattention, 55 and instincts, 41 due to parents, 42, 49, 65 due to pleasure-seeking, 117 due to pupils’ conspiracy, 106 due to teacher’s suspicious attitudes, 42, 59, 83 due to unregulated independence in the child, 86 nature of, 30 over-emphasized, 76 wilful, 49

Disputing with teacher, 123, 133, 199, 200, 211

Disrespect for teacher, 187, 366, 368, 370, 373, 490, 538

Dramatizing, 416, 417, 427, 435, 453, 490, 491

Drawing, 74, 303, 665

Dull children, 768

Eating at school, 59, 391, 392, 689

Examinations, cheating at, 269 correct view of, 271 fear of, 264 plans for, 277, 282 questions for, 270, 272 when to give, 271

Expectancy, 51, 58, 61, 62, 65, 68, 79, 80, 84, 85, 88, 92, 96, 104, 124, 133, 137, 183, 202, 231, 252, 392, 397, 411, 462, 479, 582, 585, 729, 772, 868

Explanation of commands, 35, 36, 79, 133, 143, 251, 282, 288, 333, 403, 404, 419, 429, 446, 596, 610, 626, 654, 663, 582, 729, 804, 805, 821, 823

Expressive instincts, 577

Failure and success, contrast between, 859

Falling in love with teacher, 847

Faultfinding, 62, 66, 78, 89, 100, 141, 159, 173, 183, 215, 225, 234, 250, 261, 329, 371, 374, 377, 382, 388, 395, 416, 418, 421, 433, 443, 485, 557, 571, 602, 626, 780

Fear, and cheating, 269 and discipline, 259 and examinations, 264, 284 instinctive, 255 and the lie, 297 in recitation, 264 and stubbornness, 180

Fidgets, 134, 142, 150

Fifth and Sixth grades, cleanliness, 412, 450, 456, 462 cliques, 717, 719 curiosity, 569 disrespect, 197, 367 eating at school, 395, 689 gambling, 315 giggling, 382 impudence, 206, 210 inattention to study, 554 jealousy, 707 leaving room, 378 lying, 307 manners, 418, 420, 442, 444, 803

Mimicry of speech, 366 mischief, 485, 494 obedience, 65

paper wad throwing, 219, 307 play, teaching how to, 525, 527 selfishness, 688 stealing, 638 stubbornness, 172, 178 studying aloud, 628 talkativeness, 607, 608, 611, 612 tattling, 638, 639 teasing tricks, 509 whispering, 592, 604

Fighting, due to accidental situation, 236 due to competition, 249 due to ridicule, 239 Thomas Hughes’ advice on, 96

Fire drills, 757

Firmness, 585

First and Second grades, absences, 764 altruism, 729 careless work, 765 cleanliness, 451, 453 crying, 257 dislike for study, 766 disobedience, 773 disrespect, 189 drawing, 665 drills, 752 dull children, 768 eating at school, 392, 393, 691 fighting, 236 first day in school, 748 first year in school, 747 ill-temper, 182, 187 impudence, 772 indifference to school, 159 laughing, 234 leaving room, 375

lying, 300, 301 making faces, 483 manners, 415, 428 mischief, 766 muscle training, 144 noise, 136 obedience, 49 passing quietly, 751 penmanship learning, 663 play, teaching how to, 524 quarreling, 225, 229, 231 refusal to recite, 256 ringleader, 782 scribbling, 659 selfishness, 677, 679, 781 sex hygiene, 832

sickness a cause of backwardness, 155 smartness, 770 stealing, 327, 330 stubbornness, 170 stuttering, 652 swearing, 651 talkativeness, 634 tardiness, 763 tattling, 633, 634 whispering, 581, 583

Flag salute, 809, 811

Gambling, 115, 312, 318

Games, certain objectionable, in acquiring motor control, 148, 829

Gesture, mimicry of, 368

Groups of pupils, enlisting, 79, 91, 97, 119, 540, 573, 574, 712, 715, 719, 722, 724, 726, 777, 782, 830, 838

Gymnasium, promoting use of, 149, 501

Habit of crying, 258 quarreling, 230 whispering, 583

Hair-pulling, 203

Helping pupil in study, 103, 105

High School, altruism, 736 athletics, supervision of, 532, 534, 537 boy and girl question, 839, 841, 843 cheating by pupil, 281 cheating by teacher, 284 cigarettes, 409 cliques, 720, 725 companions, choosing, 812, 815 curiosity, 571, 573 dancing, 831 destroying property, 561 eating in school, 397, 400 falling in love with teacher, 848, 852 fear, 264, 267 fighting, 249 gambling, 320 impudence, 214 indifference, 167 jealousy, 712, 713, 716 laughing, 193, 194, 497, 598 manners, 425, 427 marking books, 661 nervousness, 264 obedience, 89 passing quietly, 761 practical joke, 504, 513, 516, 519 race prejudice, 471 religion, 817, 819, 821, 823 ringleader, 788, 790, 793, 800 selfishness, 675, 699 sex attraction, unconscious, 831

stealing, 338 sororities, 720 talkativeness, 623, 624 tattling, 643, 647, 649, 661, 697 truancy, 157, 548 whispering, 598, 601

Home study, 77, 87

How to study, teaching, 626, 628

Humor and discipline, 215, 598

Ideals, false and perverted, 24

Ignoring misconduct, 142, 196, 200, 205, 238, 293, 372, 381, 444, 482, 484, 520, 635, 637, 662, 763

Ill-temper, 182

Imagination, aid in discipline, 184, 488 and lying, 295

Imitation, aid in discipline, 184, 361 and bodily action, 63 cause of misconduct, 23, 69, 361 provoking impudence, 206

Impartiality, 108

Impudence, 65, 190, 199, 206, 211, 213, 772, 795

Inattention, 55, 554

Independence in the child, causing disobedience, 86

Indifference as cause of disorder, 157

Inhibition and discipline, 21

Injured child, sympathy for, 258

Instincts, classification of, 129 relation to discipline, 13, 17, 19, 20, 21 disobedience, 30 fear, 255

function of, 129

Interviews, 34, 52, 60, 62, 63, 68, 84, 86, 87, 88, 92, 96, 101, 112, 113, 114, 119, 132, 155, 174, 175, 177, 191, 215, 222, 232, 242, 251, 288, 302, 313, 320, 322, 332, 336, 398, 410, 421, 423, 449, 457, 466, 472, 494, 499, 510, 520, 566, 586, 605, 641, 645, 682, 700, 864

Jealousy, 700

Jokes on teacher, 366, 368, 370, 373

Joking teacher, 205, 505, 507

Kindergarten. (See First and Second grades.)

Knowing the pupil, 51, 58, 60, 63, 87, 108, 131, 142, 151, 156, 176, 179, 186, 194, 200, 209, 212, 218, 226, 339, 241, 481, 566, 511, 584, 615, 620, 673, 706, 777

Laboratory as an instrument of discipline, 167

Laughing in school, 72, 74, 75, 99, 193, 194, 234, 382, 493, 494, 497

Laziness, clumsiness and fidgets as causes of disorders, 130

Leaving the room, 375

Lighting of a school-room, 154

Literary societies, troubles with, 106

Lunches, stealing of, 334

Lying to conceal, 301, 465, 594 enquiry into, 212 for fame, 506 for gain, 298, 300 and gambling, 313 and the imagination, 295 kinds of, 297 provoked by teacher, 67, 292, 303, 307

and stealing, 329, 335 teacher practices, 59, 288, 304, 863

Mannerisms of teacher, 102, 366, 370, 373, 368

Manners, 53, 191, 411, 672, 684, 695, 700, 715, 717, 736, 740, 803

Making faces, 482, 483, 487, 500, 781

Marbles, gambling with, 312

Marking desks, 301

Matching pennies, 319

Mimicry, 365

Mischief-maker, 98, 478, 485, 501, 504, 766

Money stolen, 337, 338, 340

Motor functions defective, causing disobedience, 61

Nervous child, 134, 447

Noise, 94, 135, 143, 443, 446, 463, 466, 589, 591, 602, 621, 622

Note-writing, 643, 834, 835, 836, 862

Obedience, factors making for, 38 Fifth and Sixth grades, 65 First and Second grades, 49 formal, 34, 746

High School, 89 intelligent, 36, 746 kinds of, 33, 186 public expects, 38 pupils expect to obey, 39 relation to character building, 29 relation to school efficiency, 27 Seventh and Eighth grades, 76 stages in development of, 33

Third and Fourth grades, 56

Oversensitiveness, of pupil, 214 of teachers, 189

Paper scattered, 49, 77, 80, 459

Paper wad throwing, 219, 307, 492

Parents, causing a boy to tease, 240 defaming teacher, a cause of disobedience, 65 leading families, dealing with, 70 provoking disobedience, 41, 86, 438, 770 provoking impudence, 206 provoking indifference to school, 159 provoking quarrels, 228 provoking selfishness, 684, 687 provoking stubbornness, 172 responsibility in keeping order, 110, 165, 323, 452, 457, 469, 745, 840 teacher conferring with, 67, 68, 158, 228, 322

Passing quietly, 137, 751, 756

Pencil, misuse of, 135, 187, 443

Penmanship, learning, 663

Personal right of pupils, infringement of, 93

Physical conditions, causing misconduct 131, 134, 141, 143, 148, 155, 236, 587

Picnic manners, 418

Play, 477, 671, 692, 829, 831 supervised, 226, 230, 317, 522, 692

Pleasure-seeking causing disobedience, 117

Poolroom, The, 641

Practical jokes, 504, 510

Preparation (to teach), defective, 121

Prohibitions, 99, 111, 362, 383, 390, 395, 398, 416, 451, 580, 754, 755, 591, 795, 839

Promise, making to pupils, 109

Public opinion disregarded, 110

Punishment, apology as, 321, 371 corporal, awkward position, 443, 483 boxing ears, 276 requesting right to use, 94 shaking, 50, 384, 603, 762 tying hands together, 562 whipping, 66, 68, 78, 89, 93, 163, 164, 172, 173, 195, 202, 211, 218, 261, 263, 319, 332, 485, 508, 706, 861 demotion, 502, 629

detention after school, 73, 151, 190, 230, 241, 260, 275, 336, 374, 588, 612, 710 discipline, not dependent upon 17 grade lowered, 277 ineffective, 135, 141, 161 loss of privileges, 321, 737, 780, 802 provoking disobedience, 89 ridicule, 206 school work, as 90, 599 suspension, 282, 317, 467, 513, 518, 839

Punning, 200

Quarreling from spite, 228 on school grounds, 225 way to school, 229

Quarrelsomeness, bullying and fighting, 223

Questioning pupils about misconduct, 73, 90, 99, 213, 234, 273, 275, 276, 292, 301, 307, 317, 321, 333, 335, 382, 389, 391, 393, 398, 410, 421, 443, 464, 466, 498, 499, 501, 506, 517, 543, 636, 661, 797, 862

Race prejudice, 471, 474

Reasons, failure to comprehend cause of misconduct, 22

Reform of teacher, 95, 102, 124, 228, 590, 612, 763

Refusal to do home work, 87, 88 to go to school, 87 to recite, 256

Regulative instincts, 745

Religious attitudes, 817 perplexities, 821 recluse, 823

Responsibility, 84, 86

Retardation of a pupil, 64, 67, 132, 150, 769

Ridicule provoking fighting, 239

Rights of child as to playthings, 313

Ringleader, dealing with a, 52, 70, 98, 113, 119, 367, 385, 405, 411, 529, 546, 574, 740, 776

Rivalry between student groups, 106, 713

Rules, overemphasis of, causing disobedience, 76, 81, 662, 750

Rural School

anarchy in, 217, 310 cheating, 273, 276, 281 clumsiness, 140 coaching pupil, 181 conceit, 192 defying teacher, 69 eating during school hours, 59 first day, 749 inattention, 55 indifference, 159 joking teacher, 205 mischief in, 99 paper scattered, 49 quarreling, 229

Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.
Marxist political economy and bourdieu: economic and cultural capital, classes and state 1st edition by Ebook Home - Issuu