Download full Being and not being 2nd edition richard iveson ebook all chapters

Page 1


Being and Not Being 2nd Edition

Richard Iveson

Visit to download the full and correct content document: https://textbookfull.com/product/being-and-not-being-2nd-edition-richard-iveson/

More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant download maybe you interests ...

Art of Being Human Richard Janaro

https://textbookfull.com/product/art-of-being-human-richardjanaro/

Ethical Practice in the Human Services From Knowing to Being Richard D. Parsons

https://textbookfull.com/product/ethical-practice-in-the-humanservices-from-knowing-to-being-richard-d-parsons/

Towards non-being : the logic and metaphysics of intentionality 2nd Edition Priest

https://textbookfull.com/product/towards-non-being-the-logic-andmetaphysics-of-intentionality-2nd-edition-priest/

The Pursuit of Human Well Being The Untold Global History 1st Edition Richard J. Estes

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-pursuit-of-human-well-beingthe-untold-global-history-1st-edition-richard-j-estes/

Speaking Being Werner Erhard Martin Heidegger and a New Possibility of Being Human 1st Edition Bruce Hyde

https://textbookfull.com/product/speaking-being-werner-erhardmartin-heidegger-and-a-new-possibility-of-being-human-1stedition-bruce-hyde/

Being Hindu Being Indian Lala Lajpat Rai s Ideas of Nationhood Vanya Vaidehi Bhargav

https://textbookfull.com/product/being-hindu-being-indian-lalalajpat-rai-s-ideas-of-nationhood-vanya-vaidehi-bhargav/

Being Digital Citizens Engin Isin

https://textbookfull.com/product/being-digital-citizens-enginisin/

The Greatest Possible Being Jeff Speaks

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-greatest-possible-beingjeff-speaks/

Well being Sustainability and Social Development Harry Lintsen

https://textbookfull.com/product/well-being-sustainability-andsocial-development-harry-lintsen/

Being and Not Being

Being and Not Being

End Times of Posthumanism and the Future Undoing of Philosophy

ROWMAN & LITTLEFIELD

Lanham • Boulder • New York • London

Published by Rowman & Littlefield

An imprint of The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc. 4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200, Lanham, Maryland 20706 www.rowman.com

86-90 Paul Street, London EC2A 4NE, United Kingdom

Copyright © 2024 by Richard Iveson

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems, without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote passages in a review.

British Library Cataloguing in Publication Information Available

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Available

ISBN 978-1-5381-8822-4 (cloth: alk. paper)

ISBN 978-1-5381-8824-8 (ebook)

ISBN 978-1-5381-8823-1 (paperback: alk. paper)

The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992.

For Maoki, the best of us

Acknowledgements

Introduction: Relative Reason

Chapter 1: Ends of Life: Death of Socrates

Chapter 2: Ends of Nature: The Question Concerning Posthuman Technology

Chapter 3: Ends of the Future: Contingency and the Life of Machines

Chapter 4: Ends of Thought: Mad Times, Hyper-Chaos and Difference More Radical Than Différance

Chapter 5: End Times: Physics and Ignorance

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful to all those who have helped with the writing and publishing of this book, particularly given the extreme patience such support ultimately involved. I began this project while a postdoctoral research fellow at the University of Queensland in 2014, initially in the Centre for Critical and Cultural Studies and later as part of the Institute for Advanced Studies in the Humanities. I would also like to thank Lynn Turner and Stefan Herbrechter for their ongoing support of my work, as well as Sarah Campbell, Natalie Mandziuk, Yu Ozaki, and Lynn Zelem at Rowman & Littlefield.

I want to thank too my brother Greg Hainge for his friendship, unwavering support and constant belief throughout the nine years of writing, without whom this book would never have been written. I remember (of course) your comment all those years ago about the rarity of genuine minds, and at last I have the chance to thank you properly.

Finally, my thanks go to my family. In particular, my sincere thanks and gratitude go to Jo for her help and support that went well beyond all reasonable limits, and to Makiko and Maoki for everything they do and everything they are.

Parts of this book originally appeared in the following publications, which have graciously allowed them to be reprinted here:

A slightly shorter version of the reading of Leibniz’s principle of reason in the introduction can be found in my chapter ‘Posthumanism and the Ends of Technology,’ in Palgrave Handbook of Critical Posthumanism, ed. S. Herbrechter, I. Callus, M. Rossini, M. Grech, M. de Bruin-Molé, and C. John Müller (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2022), 1021–1043.

An earlier version of chapter 3 was originally published as ‘Of Times before Tomorrow: Contingency and the Life of Machines,’ Culture, Theory and Critique 61, no. 1 (2020): 37–63.

x Acknowledgements

Part of the conclusion originally appeared in the chapter entitled ‘Technology,’ in Edinburgh Companion to Animal Studies, ed. Ron Broglio, Lynn Turner, and Undine Sellbach (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2018), 504–517.

Introduction

Relative Reason

Modern technology pushes toward the greatest possible perfection. Perfection is based on the thoroughgoing calculability of objects. The calculability of objects presupposes the unqualified validity of the principium rationis. It is in this way that the authority characteristic of the principle of reason determines the essence of the modern, technological age.

—Martin Heidegger, The Principle of Reason

Speaking in 1956, philosopher Martin Heidegger poses what he calls the world-question of thinking, the answer to which will ultimately decide ‘what will become of the earth and of human existence on this earth’ (The Principle of Reason, 129). Are we, he asks, to remain in thrall to the mindless enchantment of calculative thinking, or are we instead ‘obliged to find paths upon which thinking is capable of responding to what is worthy of thought’ (129)? We thus find ourselves situated at a fundamental crossroads with regards to the future, tasked with the enacting of a decision unlike anything that has gone before. Long before the concept of the Anthropocene became common academic currency, Heidegger here correlates the instantiation of this world-question of thinking with the advent of a new historical epoch founded for the first time upon the rapacious procurement of any and all potential resources. Given the recklessness of calculative thinking that is the driving force behind the globalizing project of postindustrial capitalism, it should come as no surprise that the urgency of this call to cognitive arms has only increased over the course of the intervening decades. In parallel with this increase in urgency, however, developments in digital technologies have further transformed globalizing processes of consolidation out of all recognition and thus, if we are to hope to respond to Heidegger’s world-question today,

it is necessary also to move beyond Heidegger’s existential analytic with its basis in the privileged form of the uniquely human Dasein.

The history of reason in the West tells the story of the quest for a perfect accounting of the world around us, one that, once properly codified, will disclose a perfectly ordered and orderly future, at which point this future becomes available to human knowledge and thus subject in its entirety to human control. From Plato to Descartes and from Leibniz to Einstein, to truly accede to the universe of reason is to erase all possibility of chance, to resolve fundamental uncertainty and to restrict the role of indeterminacy to that of a simple heuristic impulse signaling only that the grand narrative of reason is not quite yet complete. This is the normative ideology of causal determinism in a nutshell, and I would like to think that this is a vision of the world and of the future that very few of us would wish to inhabit. Despite this, however, and despite Heidegger’s warning shot all those years ago, we remain to this day in thrall to the very same ideology of the future, bewitched by the promise of control over the calculable.

To break free of the spell of reason is no simple task, however, and this brings us to a second major challenge facing us today. In what is perhaps something of a kneejerk reaction to the underlying problem identified by Heidegger’s world-question of thinking, it has become a commonplace of contemporary posthumanist and new materialist discourse to decry the simplistic human–animal binary, while at the same time maintaining an absolute and constitutive disjunct between living beings and nonliving things.1 Indeed, the reductive reasoning of this latter pairing is not infrequently celebrated as proof of the overcoming of liberal humanism and anthropocentrism both, thus playing its own part in what today is a largely triumphal discourse built around the defining role of autopoiesis—a role predicated upon the reduction of infinite ways and forms of being to that of a single ‘life.’ While the importance of the ongoing deconstruction of the human–animal dichotomy is undeniable, when considered in isolation or when taken as an end in itself it is nonetheless rendered toothless for the most part. The reason for this is simple insofar as, just as deconstruction discloses the illegitimacy of the traditional human–animal antonym, so too it necessarily discloses the illegitimacy of the normative structuring of simple ontological dualism in all of its myriad forms of exclusion. Hence, it is important to stress from the start the incommensurability of what follows with the vitalisms and animisms that carry aloft recent theories of vibrant matter and affective embodiment. The deconstruction of the traditional human–animal binary is, in other words, but a first step and wholly insufficient on its own.

As we shall see, moving beyond the reductive metaphysical blueprint that decrees as both absolute and undeniable the division between embodied lifeforce and its absence brings along with it a profound shift in the ways we

xiii engage critically and ethically both with the world around us and with the future. No longer distracted by the chimera of the élan vitale, we inevitably find ourselves occupying a very different terrain and a very different landscape, one in which all physical processes retain the chance of giving rise to novel emergence, and which in so doing disclose an inhuman and mutilating formal power at work at the very heart of being.

RISKING IT ALL

The future, Heidegger tells us, is in the balance. More specifically, the balance of futures rests with the question of risk as productive of exclusion. The promise that is the chance of a future, in other words, requires us to collectively refute such manifold delusions of safety constructed upon an entirely baseless ideology and policed by a politics of exclusion. As with the contemporary resurgence of vitalisms, to fail to address the posthumanist ‘world-question’ of thinking in this manner risks failing to address the corresponding reduction of the practically infinite array, disarray and diversity of inclinations to that of a single inclination as definitive of the peerless triumph of global capitalism today and tomorrow. This is the risk that we know by the name of the Anthropocene: a vision of the world ordered up and down and front to back by calculative thinking in the guise of a promise to safeguard the present from the vagaries of the future by way of predictions based upon naïve causal calculus. Ultimately, however, such promises to keep our present safe from future risk are simple ideological fictions, sleight of hand productions of a fabricated need that, in the end, puts everything at risk.

Contrary to all such appearances, contingency is definitive of the structure of being itself, from which it follows that any predictions about the future founded upon present or habitual states of being are necessarily subject to possible error. As we shall see, to be is to be fundamentally unsafe; subject to a profound structural unpredictability from which nothing is ever safe and which inscribes a prior ethical demand common to biological and technological systems alike. As a result, the ‘rules’ of critical and ethical engagement are transformed insofar as we can no longer lay claim to the legitimacy and the usefulness of decisions made today and tomorrow on the back of predicted futures that erroneously presume the absolute determinability of all beings unilaterally deemed to lack the alchemical privilege definitive of life.

If we are to escape from this normative logic of life, one of the first hurdles to be overcome concerns our general anxiety about the speed and complexity of technological innovation. In this regard, the perceived potential of biotechnologies makes very clear exactly what, if anything, remains of ethical choice today insofar as it explodes the myth of linear causality considered as

Introduction

fully determining in the case of any entity we care to classify as lacking the ephemera of a lifeforce. Instead, contemporary notions of living technologies and technological lifeforms mean that we are now obligated—philosophically, ethically and politically—to recognize that the future effects of animate and inanimate causes alike can by definition never be predicted with absolute surety.

THE LONG SLEEP OF REASON

In Before Tomorrow: Epigenesis and Rationality (2014), philosopher Catherine Malabou seeks to address three urgent questions that reveal within contemporary Continental philosophy the outlines of three areas of ‘incomprehensible silence’ (1). Notably, the first of these questions concerns time: ‘Why has the question of time lost its status as the leading question of philosophy?’ (1).2 In the wake of Martin Heidegger’s late decree in On Time and Being that time ultimately ‘vanishes’ as a question, writes Malabou, ‘no one asks this question anymore, no one has taken up the problem by developing afresh a decisive concept of temporality, be it with or against Heidegger’ (1). While strictly speaking Malabou’s claim is of course hyperbole, she is nonetheless correct in bringing to light the recent disappearance of time as the fundamental question of philosophy. Whether this silence can be described as incomprehensible, however, remains to be seen.

If we are to respond to Malabou’s challenge and engage anew with the question of time today, we must first of all ask after the status of the principle of reason. Fittingly perhaps, Heidegger delivered a lecture course and summary standalone address on precisely this question in 1955–56. Entitled Der Satz vom Grund or The Principle of Reason (1991), the address begins in a somewhat belligerent mood:

The principle of reason reads: nihil est sine ratione. One translates this with: nothing is without reason. What the principle states can be paraphrased as follows: everything has a reason, which means each and every thing that is in any manner. Omnes ens habet rationem. Whatever happens to be actual has a reason for its actuality. Whatever happens to be possible has a reason for its possibility. Whatever happens to be necessary has a reason for its necessity. Nothing is without reason (117).

In fact, continues Heidegger, ‘what the principle of reason states is commonplace, and because it is commonplace, it is immediately illuminating’ (117).3 What the principle of reason states, in other words, is so obvious as to be perceived immediately and with utmost clarity by everyone. So much so,

Introduction xv

however, that just what, exactly, the principle states is not expressly posited as a principle or law until the seventeenth century, when Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz “recognized the long-since commonplace idea ‘nothing is without reason’ was a normative principle and described it as the principle of reason” (118). So, asks Heidegger, what of the two thousand three hundred years of philosophical endeavor in the West that preceded Leibniz’s eventual validation of the principle of reason? What is it about ‘this little principle [that it] needed such an extraordinarily long incubation period’ and, more to the point, why have we ‘scarcely thought at all about this curious fact’ (118)? Perhaps, suggests Heidegger with heavy irony, this unusually long incubation period is preparation for an equally unusual awakening, ‘a quickening to a wakefulness that no longer admits of sleep, least of all, an incubation’ (118). Mirroring Malabou’s question of time, Heidegger’s question addressed to the long sleep of reason here similarly resounds as a negative or paradoxical echo that reveals the outlines of a further area of incomprehensible silence within contemporary Continental philosophy in response to both the possibility and the plausibility of the principle of reason as a reasoned and reasonable principle. Moreover, as we shall see when addressing the death of Socrates in the first chapter, with this analogous pairing of reason with wakefulness and unreason with sleep, Heidegger in fact calls time on the entire metaphysical tradition in the West.

With this in mind, we can now elucidate a brief overview of the project embarked upon here. In subjecting itself to profound critique through its absence of rational foundation, it will be argued, reason must then decree that the existence of an immutable law, concept or cause is necessarily impossible. Based initially upon these two interlinked proclamations—that reason subjects itself to profound transformation and that no law, concept or cause is absolute and therefore invariable—it then becomes possible to address anew the conditions of unprecedented emergence into being and which, in turn, pose significant challenges to normative ethical practice as traditionally conceived in the West. Notably in this regard, the operative categories of ‘living’ and ‘natural’ remain with us only under extreme duress, yet the exclusive taxonomies to which these outmoded categories give rise continue to blindly justify the uses to which ‘things’ are being put with little or no ethical consideration. In order to remedy this ethical blinding that both enables and inheres within the categories and taxonomies of life and nature, a philosophical analysis of the machinery and machinations of novel emergence is indeed overdue. Furthermore, it will be argued that there exists a preliminary constitutive relation between the ethical and technological domains insofar as the process of emergence into being also orders an ethics of technological innovation.

THE RENDERING OF REASON

Staying for the moment with the belatedly staged principle of reason, Heidegger notes that for Leibniz this new principle is not simply one among many, but is rather ‘one of the supreme fundamental principles, if not the most supreme one’ (118). As to why this is so, continues Heidegger, we must look to the complete formulation of Leibniz’s supreme new principle, that of the principium reddendae rationis sufficientis, which Leibniz glosses as ‘nothing exists for which the sufficient reason for its existence cannot be rendered’ (cit. 120). Clearly there is a lot more going on here than an as yet unexpressed but nonetheless immediately self-evident claim that ‘everything has a reason.’ Ironically, a significant part of this ‘lots more’ concerns the possibility or otherwise of immediacy itself. For Leibniz, truth describes the correctness of judgement, and it is reason alone that renders an account [reddendae rationis] of the truth of judgement. By its rendering of accounts, in other words, reason justifies the correctness of this or that judgement and, as such, declares this or that judgement to be true and, inversely, that any and all judgements are therefore untrue until such time as they are accounted for by reason. However, the need to justify judgement by the rendering of accounts raises a further question: To whom or what must these accounts be rendered? Heidegger’s elegant answer is simple but nonetheless crucial: reasons are rendered ‘to humans who determine objects as objects by way of a representation that judges’ (119). From this point onward, writes Heidegger, all of ‘modern thinking’ experiences the human ‘as an I that relates to the world such that it renders this world to itself in the form of connections correctly established between its representations—that means judgements—and thus sets itself over against this world as to an object’ (119). As the newly appointed custodian of reason and arbiter of what does and does not count, the human thereafter establishes itself amid and against a world of objects that is now literally of no account but which exists solely for a representing subject.

This brings us to the fourth term in Leibniz’s complete principle of reason, the sufficientis. Here, the question of sufficiency serves as a final check and balance imposed by reason upon otherwise all too human accounts of judgement. It rules, in short, as to the legitimacy or otherwise of accounts that lay claim to truth status. As such, it is better understood as a test of adequation insofar as it determines whether this or that account can be considered as adequate for the secure establishing of objects. From this moment forth, it is not only truth but also existence itself that now entirely depends upon human cognition. Only the completeness of the account, writes Heidegger, ‘hereafter vouches for the fact that every cognition everywhere and at all times can include and count on the object and reckon with it. . The principle now says

Introduction xvii

that every thing counts as existing when and only when it has been securely established as a calculable object for cognition’ (120). We can therefore paraphrase Leibniz’s grand principle as follows: Every thing in the world exists only insofar as we (humans) have reasoned it so. The principle of reason thus betrays the profound idealism of its founding, while the supposedly objective ‘test’ of sufficiency is shown to be nothing other than a blunt yet supremely effective ideological tool.

Leibniz’s principle of reason thus serves to establish the ‘objectness’ or ‘thingness’ of everything else that exists as constitutively excluded from ‘the human’ and therefore wholly calculable by ‘the human.’ At the same time that the world of objects is pressed into being, in other words, every object in that world is declared fully comprehensible and thus entirely predictable. As the condition of their existence, reason now thoroughly determines the inhuman realms of matter, nature and artifice—and all this despite the fact that the principle of reason is not in the strict sense a causal principle. Less obvious, however, is that the determinist constraints introduced and maintained by the principle of reason are inevitably put to work on both sides of the human–nonhuman divide. As Heidegger writes:

When Leibniz first expressly and completely formulated the principle of reason as such a Principle, what he thereby articulated is the fact that human cognition, in a decisive and unavoidable manner, had come to be taken up into the claim of the principium rationis and held in the sway of its power. The principium rationis, the principle of reason, becomes the fundamental principle of all cognition. This means: dominated by the principium rationis (120).

Put simply, in expressly formulating the principle of reason as a rigid and universal Principle, Leibniz inevitably constrains cognition itself to the dictates of its own fundamental principle. Hence, in the very process of constituting human cognition as ontologically distinct from the fully comprehensible and calculable objects that populate the natural, material and artificial realms, Leibniz in the same moment subjects human cognition to the demands of reason. Both despite and because of its exalted ontological difference, cognition must thereafter render reasons sufficiently adequate to justify its own existence. Human cognition, in other words, must now securely establish itself as a calculable object in order to account for its existence as singularly incalculable. The paradoxical circularity quickly becomes dizzying.

Nevertheless, since its formulation Leibniz’s supreme principle has proven incomparably powerful. ‘In the history of humanity,’ writes Heidegger, ‘the authority of the powerful fundamental principle becomes more powerful the more pervasively, the more obviously, and accordingly the more inconspicuously the principle of reason determines all cognition and behavior’ (121).

Introduction

This, he continues, “brings to fruition nothing less than the innermost, and at the same time most concealed, molding of the age of Western history we call ‘modernity’” (121). Moreover, it does so through the machines, myths and contrivances of what we know today as modern technology. This is because the perfection to which technology tends above all consists ‘in the completeness of the calculably secure establishing of objects, in the completeness of reckoning with them and with the securing of the calculability of possibilities for reckoning’ (121). In its triumph of unqualified validity, the principium rationis thus determines the essence of our modern technological age.

In one respect, as Heidegger notes, Leibniz’s translation of a ‘barely thought’ notion into an all-conquering fundamental principle marks the end of a curiously extended period of incubation. In another, however, this marks but one more somnambulist stage in the continuing incubation of reason in the West. Rather than a decisive step—be it causal, dialectical or teleological— along the way to a perfect accounting of the world and thus of its perfectly predictable future, this continuing incubation of reason serves only itself inasmuch as it serves ultimately to demonstrate its own absent foundation. In other words, and as I will endeavor to show over the course of this book, reason subjects itself to a profound and profoundly uncertain transformation. Just as reason at the close of the nineteenth century ultimately decrees the death of the God it was initially constructed to slavishly serve, so too reason ultimately decrees the death of life as a distinct—and distinctly privileged— ontological category today.

EINSTEIN’S INSANITY: THE RECIPROCITY OF THE RATIONAL, THE INSTRUMENTAL AND THE PREDICTABLE

Recalling Malabou’s provocative allegation about the contemporary loss of primacy accorded to the concept of time, we follow in detail here Heidegger’s challenge to the normative adequation of reason when he asks whether we should ‘give up what is worthy of thought in favor of the recklessness of exclusively calculative thinking and its immense achievements’ (The Principle of Reason, 129). For Heidegger, as for us, the stakes clearly could not be any higher insofar as it is the future itself that is at stake. In order to ‘enter on a path of reflection,’ writes Heidegger, we must first try to reflect on the principle of reason in such a way as to ‘come to terms with the distinction that holds before our eyes the difference between mere calculative thinking and reflective thinking’ (122). Moreover, he continues, such reflection begins by attending to that which, as the herald of the Anthropocene, conceals itself in the naming of the ‘atomic age’: namely that, for the first time in its history,

‘humanity interprets an epoch of its historical existence on the basis of the rapacity for, and the procuring of, a natural energy’ (122).

Thinking as calculation and the rapacity for procuring natural energy are for Heidegger the indissociable markers of modernity, and the tyrannical governance of the calculable is nowhere more in evidence than in the commonplace definition of insanity—famously if erroneously attributed to Albert Einstein—as ‘doing the same thing over and over again and expecting a different result.’ Of course, the authority accruing to the name Einstein in the modern era is unparalleled, making it somewhat ironic therefore that this authority should be usurped here in defence of pre-modern—i.e., Newtonian—physics insofar as the corollary definition of the rational entailed by this claim consists therefore in knowing the effect of every cause in advance.4 The rationale of calculation, in short, demands an entirely deterministic and thus wholly predictable universe in order to function. In this way, perfection becomes synonymous with the absolute calculability of objects and, insofar as modern technology is perceived as coming closest to this engineered perfection, ‘the authority characteristic of the principle of reason’ thereafter comes to ‘determine the essence of the modern, technological age’ (121).

At base, Leibniz’s principle of reason thus serves to instrumentalize the entire universe insofar as it is deemed as existing outside of human reasoning and as such is subject to the singularly unambiguous dictates of causal determinism. Moreover, as a corollary of this fundamental determinism by calculable relations of cause and effect, time and temporal affects abruptly vanish from our mechanist universe, which runs just as well backward as it does forward. The consequences of the symmetrical conception of existence are far from innocuous. Not least, if we also keep with tradition in supposing that we can never approach being except through time, then essential timelessness inevitably renders being itself as essentially timeless, that is, as fully determined stasis. In short, the stalled reciprocity of the rational, the instrumental and the wholly predictable condemns the universe to a moribund state of profound immobility.

Enchanted by the abstraction of calculative ratio, we forget to ask what for Heidegger is the ‘world-question’ of thinking and instead remake the earth in our image: as a material repository, a world of nature configured as mere ‘stock’ in solitary service to our rapacity for the material, and then we forget that too. While we will address the various roles—moral and political as well as metaphysical—attributed to the concept of nature along with the insidiousness of its violence in detail in the second chapter, it is sufficient at this early stage to simply gain a sense of ‘the force of the demand that threatens to overpower us through the principle of rendering sufficient reasons’ (123). Such is the dominance of Leibniz’s commonplace little principle, that is, of modernity itself.

And what, we must ask, of the future? Can we really afford to forget that also? Here, we stay with Heidegger insofar as we too must ask: What is the instrumental itself? ‘Wherever ends are pursued and means are employed,’ writes Heidegger in The Question Concerning Technology (1954), ‘wherever instrumentality reigns, there reigns causality’ (6). At this point, Heidegger addresses a crucial coda to the principle of reason: ‘But suppose that causality, for its part, is veiled in darkness with respect to what it is?’ (6). Returning to the logic of insanity mistakenly attributed to Einstein, it is not by chance that this logic specifically defers to the (already insane) expectation or anticipation of a breakdown of determined causal relationships. However, what concerns us here—and what still today remains largely veiled in darkness—is that of a causality more insane than insane, insofar as the effective event is precisely that which cannot be expected or anticipated—an unpredictable break with determinist causality that is not however the breakdown of causal relations. While this will be addressed in detail over the course of this book, we already have a sense of how the potential inscription of irreversible and unpredictable formal events at the structural level of being inevitably requires philosophy to once again turn its attention to the question of time. Moreover, as both existential possibility and prior condition, time in this way ceases to be in slavish service to superlative human folly, no longer available for expropriation as a uniquely human property (whether real or irreal) and no longer a simple accident of existence (human or otherwise).

EXISTENCE WITHOUT PRECEDENCE: QUESTIONS OF TIME AND TECHNOLOGY

Time, it will be argued, is real and inclusive, meaning that nothing, including all physical and natural laws, stands outside of time. The question of time is thus a question of relation, key to which are the concepts of immediacy and mediation. Tightly bound up with the concept of timeless being, immediacy was long deemed the exclusive property of Nature understood as the set of all living entities other than the human, with the loss of immediacy being considered the (bargain) price paid by humankind upon its constitutive Epimethean secession into the sociotechnological realm of Culture. Today, however, this concept of immediacy is in the process of being radically reworked.

One key aspect of this reworking of immediacy concerns the prior conditions of novel emergence. Put another way, what things have to happen and what conditions must be met in order for some radically ‘new’ being to emerge into existence? Whatever its form may become in time, for an innovation to be truly innovative the very possibility of its existence must, everywhere prior to its material emergence, be literally unthinkable. It must,

in other words, be in being without precedent. But does it necessarily follow that ‘being without precedent’ is the same as ‘being without condition’? We have to be careful on this point. Prior to its timely emergence, such a being is by definition impossible and inconceivable (the latter terms being in a strict sense synonymous in this instance). Furthermore, the sense of this previous impossibility and inconceivability only comes into being alongside the (impossible and inconceivable) emergence of novel being—and this, it should be noted, holds regardless of whether we are talking about cultural objects, natural things or lively technologies and everything in between.

To exist without precedent. Can we really conclude from this that only true novelty, alone among beings, exists without condition? And if so, are we also to conclude from this definitive lack of determining historicity that the process of its emergence into being is therefore uniquely and paradoxically immediate? Clearly, such a claim is counterintuitive in the extreme, not least because the very concept of ‘process’ is defined in the first instance by a ‘taking up’ of time. That said, however, the concept of process already presumes a particular conception of causality that either gives rise to temporal succession or, at the very least, functions in tandem. Hence, if causality indeed remains veiled in darkness with respect to what it is, then so too must the process of ‘process’ be veiled in darkness with respect to what it is also.

So where does this leave us today? As will be argued at length in the first chapter, in order to even begin to respond to such questions, it is necessary first of all for us to move beyond the normative metaphysical sophistry that opposes biological life to inanimate matter. This is not intended as a particularly provocative statement, although some readers will likely deem it to be so based on what they perceive as the inherent danger of any theory founded upon an ontological ‘flattening’ that seeks to erase the absolute distinction that constitutes life via the exclusion and negation of matter. Such uneasiness is not surprising in the least insofar as the presumed existence of a secure distinction dividing life from nonlife—together with its correlates subject from object and being from thing—is not only a staple throughout Western philosophy, but also serves as the ground upon which the entire edifice of liberal morality, ancient and modern, is constructed. While counterintuitive perhaps, it will be argued here that the production and reproduction of this simple distinction in fact serves to necessarily exclude the possibility of ethics. Ethical possibility, in short, can begin only following the collapse of the living-nonliving binary, just as ethical accountability therefore begins only on the condition that we are done with life entirely.

As a preliminary theoretical and ethical step, the extension of formal processes of individuation as constitutive of all forms of being—irrespective of whether such forms are labeled living, dead or nonliving—can be seen to

accord very closely with contemporary research being proposed from within the physical sciences. Of these, most important are the realist arguments for pilot wave theory and spontaneous wave function collapse in quantum theory along with—and often overlapping—theories posed by proponents of far-from-equilibrium thermodynamics, all of which refute the timelessness of classical physics in favor of contingency and irreversibility on both microscopic and macroscopic levels of being. However, while the strange temporalities described by dissipative structures serve as privileged examples in what follows, they must nonetheless await the final chapter before being addressed directly and in detail. That said, Dorian Sagan and Eric Schneider’s definition of metastable flow systems provides us with a very useful introduction. Metastable processes, they argue, ‘underlie the things we mistake for things. Selves are not closed or isolated but arise as metastable open systems in a sea of energy and flows. . . . [W]e too are metastable flow systems with billions of years of history as dissipative structures’ (Into the Cool, 112). Neither simple being nor simple thing, every given form of being instead describes an open energy-driven processual structure, at once product and producer of material cycles and self-reinforcing networks. Only on this basis, it will be argued, does it become presently possible to address the concept of immediacy as it pertains to the emergence of entirely novel forms of being. Before we move on, however, there is a critical coda to this claim that should be recalled throughout. Whereas metastable systems are constitutively open, this does not mean they are open to an infinite polymorphism. Rather, the emergence of novel forms or patterns must nonetheless remain always dependent upon prior historical states. Formal plasticity, in other words, inscribes the potential for unpredictable transformation as a constitutive condition of metastable systems but, insofar as this potential is a consequence of the material cycles that structure forms of being through iterative feedback loops, this transformation—while discontinuous and nonlinear—is nonetheless constrained by historicity, that is, by the memory of prior states of being. While this will be further clarified over the course of the chapters to follow, for the moment it suffices for us to note both that the a priori potential for any metastable system to become wholly other to itself is a defining property of being, and that this potential is dependent upon prior forms of being. As Sagan and Schneider write, ‘the emergence of whirling energy-dependent systems, their path-dependent growth and history, and even a sort of reproduction to make use of increased energy flux, are not just properties of life’ (130).

SIMULTANEITY IS INDISTINGUISHABLE FROM MAGIC

Returning to the role of immediacy as it relates to the emergence of novel forms of being, by turning to the physical sciences we discover that the functioning of both spatial and temporal simultaneity is in fact indistinguishable from magic. While I will introduce several such examples of problematic immediacy in what follows, for now it is helpful to pay particular attention to Sagan and Schneider’s discussion of the fluid systems of Taylor vortices, the process and significance of which will be explored at length in later chapters. Put simply, Taylor vortex flow refers to the regular yet unpredictable patterns that emerge when a thin layer of fluid is trapped between two rotating cylinders. Most interesting here are the terms by which Sagan and Schneider describe the emergence of these new states (patterns) of being.

In a section entitled ‘Evolution and Memory,’ they note how the ‘rotated fluid progresses through a series of near-instantaneous jumps, from one pair of flow patterns to the next. . . . As the rotation rates increase or decrease, different numbers of vortex pairs and/or number of waves appear. Near-magical jumps from state to state are observed’ (Into the Cool, 129). While we can likely assume that the notion of ‘progress’ as it is used here refers only to a chronology of observed events and not to a willed or externally determined teleology, the question of proximity nonetheless gives rise to a number of significant concerns. On two occasions within a single paragraph Sagan and Schneider employ the same hyphenated prefix in describing the transformation from one state to another, first as ‘near-instantaneous’ and then again as ‘near-magical.’ Just what is meant by this somewhat clunky prefix inevitably remains obscure: How close must one thing or one state of being have to be to another, exactly, in order for them be considered ‘near’? By simply changing the scale of reference, this problematic becomes even clearer when we ask just how near is near in the nanoscopic realm of subatomic quanta.

In describing an abrupt replacement of one metastable state or form of being with another in the same physical location, Sagan and Schneider are clearly referring to proximity in time rather than proximity in space. At the same time, their idiosyncratic use of the hyphen in this case is telling. Serving to bind the two terms closer than close in a defiance of formal convention, the hyphen visually and grammatically reenacts the very sense it is meant to convey, that of a closeness in time that goes so far beyond mere proximity as to border on the magical. More precisely, it is the apparent simultaneity of the supplemental form of being with that which it supplements that bestows upon these transitions and transformations their apparent magic. Instantaneity, in other words, is synonymous with magic insofar as it describes a formal

dislocation in space but not in time, and as such breaks with all traditionally accepted rules of causality. The magic of the instantaneous and the simultaneous—that is to say, of the immediate—thus inheres not in the speed or the timeliness of its coming, nor in the brevity of its appearing, but is rather to be found in its paradoxical timelessness. Magic, in other words, describes the impossibility of atemporal emergence. We can now better understand the role played by the qualifying prefix ‘near-’ in Sagan and Schneider’s account of fluid dynamics. Something akin to an involuntary stutter, it serves to paper over what would otherwise be a far more serious breach of formal convention—that of classical causality—with the hyphen serving to further guard against its decoupling at some time down the line.

Change takes time: as a principle, this seems at least as immediately obvious as ‘nothing is without reason.’ Ironically then, it is the apparent immediacy of the statement that again marks out its normative function as an unqualified success. Regardless of how quickly or how slowly a transformation is effected, the transformation of one form into another must necessarily occur both in time and over time—this all seems eminently reasonable, an incontrovertible fact and as such unworthy of mention. On this, Sagan and Schneider would clearly agree, and yet equally clearly, they nonetheless do feel it to be worthy of mention. In this instance, however, ‘near-’ does not in fact signify a determined relation of forms, but instead attests only to an unquestioned faith in the sufficient adequation of the governing laws of classical physics with the actual functioning of external reality. Stated simply, the normative principle of reason decrees that whatever appears contrary to scientific law cannot therefore be that which it nonetheless appears to be.

That said, however, the temporal simultaneity of forms of being cannot be so easily dismissed as a mere illusion awaiting its time of sufficient adequation or as a consequence of constraints inherent in the current state of technological progress. What, in other words, if the simultaneity of forms is neither an error of perception nor an error of measurement, the resolution of which in the future requires only time in the present? Even without the obvious irony of any claim to have sidestepped the question of simultaneity by deferring it to the future, the problematic of temporal simultaneity has long occupied, and continues to occupy, a fundamental place in quantum theory since its inception at the start of the twentieth century. Most notably, temporal simultaneity is at the core of two of its strangest and most contested concepts: superposition and entanglement. The former refers to the simultaneous ‘stacking’— i.e., superpositioning—of two or more differently configured states of being, while the latter refers to entangled states of being that instantaneously affect each other despite any amount of physical distance between them. This ‘spooky action at a distance’ of entangled states thus demonstrably refutes

the causal principle of contiguity, which claims that states of being can only be directly influenced by other states of being that are nearby in both space and time. Ignoring for the moment the severe conflict with special relativity that results, we can nonetheless summarize this very simply: simultaneity is nonlocal both in time (superposition) and in space (entanglement).

Theoretical physicist Lee Smolin offers a more nuanced account of entanglement, describing it as a ‘property of a quantum state of two or more systems, where the state indicates a property shared by those systems that is not just the sum of properties held by the individual particles’ (Einstein’s Unfinished Revolution, 299). In addition to the problem of faster than light interactions presupposed by nonlocal entanglement, Smolin here highlights the further crucial point that, insofar as they are entangled, the sum of such states is always greater than that of its parts. Entanglement, in other words, describes a relational property and state that always exceeds the determinable properties and states of an individual system, which, insofar as it is without relation, thus remains constrained by the principle of locality. Hence, to be entangled is to be indeterminate.

Recalling the ‘near-magical’ phase states occupied by Taylor vortex patterns in fluid mechanics, it will be argued in what follows that such patterns may in fact serve, if not as an indubitable example of macroscopic superposition per se, then at least as a macroscopic model of superposition insofar as the micro- and macroscopic distinction necessarily breaks down as we attempt to close in on a simple line of demarcation, only to disclose instead a continuum of metastable systems and configuration spaces or, in the language of thermodynamics, energetic forms of negentropic decoherence.

In order to better understand this, Smolin’s account of the restricted principle of precedence provides a particularly useful setting from which to begin our analysis of novel emergence. According to classical mechanics, the laws of physics are entirely deterministic and as such preclude any possibility of genuine novelty emerging anywhere in the Newtonian universe. As Smolin writes, all that ever happens is ‘rearrangements of elementary particles with unchanging properties by unchanging laws’ (Unger and Smolin, The Singular Universe, 466). However, continues Smolin, determinism is in fact only necessary in a very limited set of circumstances wherein multiple iterations of the same in the past make it possible for us to reliably predict the outcome of multiple iterations of the same in the future. This predictive reliability is thereafter taken as proof of the existence of universal timeless laws of nature that ultimately order all change. But this, writes Smolin, is ‘an over-interpretation of the evidence’ (466). Reliability, in other words, is not the same as certainty. Rather than providing empirical proof of the existence of underlying and unchanging physical laws, the reliability of prediction requires

only that there be a principle that measurements which repeat processes which have taken place many times in the past yield the same outcomes as were seen in the past. Such a principle of precedence would explain all the instances where determinism by laws works without restricting novel processes to yield predictable outcomes (466).

Put more simply, the principle of precedence states only that the probability of correctly predicting the future outcome of a given process increases significantly following many successful iterations of a particular process all yielding the same outcome. While this probability may indeed approach 100 per cent, it cannot, however, ever be 100 per cent insofar as no state or process of being can ever exist in sovereign fashion outside of its relations with other states and processes of being. Echoing the challenges posed to classical causality by Humean empiricism in the eighteenth century, Smolin here argues that quantum mechanics demands a different way of thinking about causality, one that compels us to let go of illusory certainties. This difference takes two forms. First, prior iterations of a state or system can no longer be assumed to offer ‘unique predictions for how the future will resemble the past’ but rather ‘only a statistical distribution of possible outcomes in the future’ (466). Second, insofar as entanglement ‘involves novel properties shared between subsystems which are not just properties of the individual subsystems,’ the future forms of entangled individuals cannot therefore be predicted by any knowledge of the past (467).

So, what does this all mean from the perspective of novel emergence? In contrast to the absolute preclusion of novelty described by Newtonian mechanics, the probabilistic distributions and entangled states of quantum theory describe instead a universe that can never be wholly constrained by its prior states of being. Rather, as Smolin writes, quantum mechanics discloses at the atomic level ‘the possibility that novel states can behave unpredictably because they are without precedent’ (467). The restricted principle of precedence, in other words, ultimately makes space for the possibility of novel emergence. Hence, writes Smolin,

we can have a conception of a law which is sufficient to account for the repeatability of experiments without restricting novel states from being free from constraints from deterministic laws. In essence the laws evolve with the states . . . Only after sufficient precedent has been established does a law take hold, and only for statistical predictions. Individual outcomes can be largely unconstrained (467, italics added).

Clearly, the potential for emergence without precedent in Smolin’s account cannot be reserved as the defining property of biological or organic forms of life. Rather, as an indeterminate property arising from relational entanglement,

the potential for unprecedented emergence becomes instead the property of all forms of existence. While the material functioning of this formal power as yet remains obscure, we nonetheless begin to gain a sense of how ethics may indeed have a fundamental role to play with respect to the emergence of genuine technological innovation.

In beginning to make connections between emergence without precedent, the historicity of technicity and the creative evolution of forms of being, we are better able to understand how it is that reason must subject itself to profound transformation and, in the process, return the concepts of time and causality to the forefront of contemporary philosophical concerns by ensuring that the operative categories of life and nature cease to serve as blinds behind which exploitation is left to run rampant in the absence of all ethical regulation.

Another random document with no related content on Scribd:

CHAPTER X.

The duels between the sharpshooters of the two armies were fierce and deadly. All of us like heroes. There were many heroes beside the great Generals. Here is one from the ranks. John Battle Harrison was wounded at Shiloh and again at Champion Hills. When told by the surgeon to go to the hospital, he refused and remained fighting in the ranks with a wound that would have taken hundreds of others to the hospital. This brave soldier was killed in one of the sharpshooter duels. Our company was on duty on the skirmish line all day, and we could not bury him until night; then during the dark hours of the night we dug a grave on the hillside, and wrapping his blanket around him, we left him to sleep until the great reveille is sounded. I thought that night of the lines I used to speak in school when a boy: “Not a drum was heard, not a funeral note

As his corpse to the rampart we hurried; Not a soldier discharged his farewell shot O’er the grave where our hero we buried.”

But we must not falter if our comrades do fall, but take up our duty of the soldier on the morrow and battle for the right. Now we are digging trenches and making breastworks, as well as running a sap toward the enemy’s lines by using the sap-roller. My young friends may ask what a sap-roller is. We boys used to call it a “bulletstopper.” Suppose we take two empty barrels and lash them together, one on top of the other, then wrap them ’round and ’round with willow saplings, fill them with earth, put a cover on, lay them down, and you have a sap-roller. By keeping this in front of a couple of men, they could dig a trench directly toward the enemy’s lines, and still be protected from the deadly minie-balls. We dug trenches and moved towards the enemy until the two picket lines were within hail of each other. One of the “Johnnies” made an agreement with one of our boys that they should lay down their guns and have a talk, which they did. The Confederate said our guns had killed many in the trenches. Sometimes there was a richness in the repartee between the Union and Confederate pickets that is worth repeating.

One day a “Johnnie” calls out: “What are you men doing over there?” and quick comes the answer: “Guarding 30,000 Johnnies in Vicksburg, and making them board themselves.” Another picket asks the question: “Why don’t you come and take Vicksburg?” and the Union replied: “Oh, we’re in no particular hurry; Gen. Grant is not yet ready to transfer you North.” The pickets of both armies were good natured and used to brag of their ability to whip each other. The gunboats and mortars from the river side make things lively for the people inside the city. Day after day the sharpshooters are at work; the cannonading is kept up; the saps are approaching the enemy’s stronghold still nearer and nearer. The bursting of shells over our heads, while resting in our camps, tended to make things lively, in many instances causing wounds and death. One day the boys of my regiment were cooking a mess of beans for dinner (beans were on the bill of fare every day). The beans were being cooked in one of those large camp kettles that were hung from a pole resting on two upright sticks driven into the ground. The beans were supposed to be done. The dinner hour was near at hand; two of the boys took hold of the pole and lifted the kettle from its resting place to put it to one side. Just then the sharp whirr of a piece of shell from overhead was heard and the next instant it went crashing through the bottom of that kettle, carrying beans and all with it, burying it in the earth. The two soldiers, still holding the pole in their hands, looked at each other in disgust for a moment, and then one of them, turning around, called out to the waiting hungry soldiers: “Boys, your beans have gone to h—l.”

The boys in the ranks had no use for a “dude” officer. Gen. McPherson, who commanded our corps (a braver or finer gentleman never breathed), had on his staff a fine officer, but who was very fond of dress, and when he would ride along the line of march, in his velvet suit, the boys would guy him unmercifully. One day this Colonel came into the trenches, and, stopping opposite where I stood on the embankment behind the gabions, addressed one of our boys thus: “Sergeant, do you see the enemy from this point?” The Sergeant replied: “Yes, sir, by looking through this hole in the log, down that ravine you will occasionally see the enemy crossing.” The Colonel got up, looked through the hole, and saw some

Confederates crossing the ravine, and then he was moved to take a hand in the game, and turning ’round, said: “Sergeant, load your rifle and let me have a pop at those fellows.” “All right, Colonel,” and while he was still looking, the Sergeant at his rear, loaded the musket. The gun had been in use most of the day, and was pretty foul and if not held just right, would kick fearfully. Well, wicked sinner that the soldier was, he took two cartridges, using two charges of powder and one bullet, and loaded the Enfield rifle, put the percussion cap on and handed it to the Colonel and, stepping back into the trenches, awaited developments. The Colonel got ready, saw his man, pulled the trigger and—tumbled back into the trench. He handed the gun back, remarking: “Your gun, Sergeant, recoils considerable,” and the innocent (?) soldier said, “Does it?” The Colonel did not ask for a second shot. I’ll warrant he had a black and blue shoulder for a month. The poor Colonel has passed away and the Sergeant never had the opportunity to apologize to him.

The sap-roller with the boys in blue behind it are gaining every day in digging trenches toward Fort Hill. The men of Gen. Logan’s division are employed in this work, and the plan is to undermine the enemy’s Fort Hill and blow it up. While we had to be under fire from the enemy constantly, we were better off than they; not only did they suffer from a continuous shelling by the cannons and mortars, and the incessant rattle of musketry, but they had to do it on pretty empty stomachs, for toward the last they were reduced to a very meager diet, while we were having plenty of bacon, hard tack, coffee, etc. The price of food inside the city at that time was a little higher than in Chicago. How do these prices please you: Flour, $1,000 a barrel; meal, $140 a bushel; beef, $2.50 per pound, and mule meat, $1 per pound.

What could you expect when there was a continuous siege of 47 days; a city surrounded by an army that neither permits any one to go into or come out of it; an army that slowly but surely is creeping up by its sap-rollers and approaches, getting closer and closer each day? I said we did not let any one into the city and none to come out of it; still, notwithstanding all our watchfulness there were a few who succeeded in getting through the lines, and a few that made the

attempt but failed. Permit me to give one instance. In front of the line of the 15th Illinois Regiment, near the picket line, was a low marshy sink, of about an acre in size, covered by brush and dense cane brakes. One night a boy of about 10 years of age came out of the brush towards the picket line, holding up his handkerchief as a sign that he wished to surrender. The sentinel told him to come in; he did, and the little fellow told a pitiful story; that he had been in Vicksburg visiting his aunt who was sick; that his mother lived in Jackson, and he wanted to go home. The story seemed plausible and he was allowed to go through the lines. Not long after, one night, the pickets in that same locality, heard a rustling in the bushes in the same swampy hole, and surmising that something was wrong, surrounded it, demanding the surrender of any one there on pain of being shot at once. To their surprise out came a half-dozen men, each with a bag over his shoulder containing 10,000 percussion caps. Gen. Johnston had sent the men and caps back, led by the same little boy, and they were trying to get into Vicksburg. They were marched to Gen. Grant’s headquarters, and while waiting to be ushered into the General’s presence, one of the prisoners said to the boy: “What do you suppose they will do with you, for you are the fellow that got us into this fix?” The little fellow, cocking one eye in a comical manner, replied: “Oh, I guess they won’t hurt me much, coz I’se so little.” The little fellow was not hurt much, but kept a prisoner until the surrender and then with the soldiers sent home.

The siege continues day after day; the bombardment from land and water is incessant; the beleaguered army is reduced to quarter rations, living on mule meat and thinking it good fare; the inhabitants of the city hiding and living in caves, to escape the storm of shells from the Union army and navy, which are exploding day and night in their streets. The enemy are brave and fight valiantly for their city and cause; neither the scorching sun nor the drenching rain keep them from their posts. They suffer for water; they are pinched with hunger; still they fight and hold the fort. However, the end is near. That persistency and determination, so characteristic of our commander, Gen. Grant, will surely win. It is related of Gen. Grant that one day during the siege he was riding around the lines, and stopped at a house to get some water. The only occupant was a

woman who tauntingly asked him if he expected to get into Vicksburg. “Certainly,” he replied. “But when?” she said. “I cannot tell exactly when I shall take the town, but I mean to stay here till I do, if it takes me 30 years.” The reply was too much for the old lady, and her heart sank within her, as she rushed back into the house to hide her anger. That reminds me of an incident that passed between Gen. Grant and myself, the relating of which I may be pardoned inasmuch as I am relating reminiscences. One hot day in June I was in the trenches with my company, behind the gabions, on duty as sharpshooters, when Gen. Grant, attended by one of his staff, came along. He had climbed the hill and when he arrived opposite me was perspiring and puffing greatly. We turned and saluted the General as he walked along the trench. When he came opposite to me he said: “Sergeant, is there any water convenient?” I replied, “None, General, except what is in my canteen,” and taking my canteen from my shoulder, half filled with pretty warm water, I handed it to him. He took it, offered it to the officer, who declined, and then Gen. Grant took a hearty drink from my canteen. He then handed it back, thanking me for it, and passed on. So in the words of Miles O’Reilly’s poem—

“There are bonds of all sorts in this world of ours, Fetters of friendship and ties of flowers, And true lovers’ knots, I ween;

The girl and the boy are bound by a kiss, But there’s never a bond, old friend, like this— We have drank from the same canteen.”

Although we are relieved often in our daily duty of sharpshooters, and return to the ravines and hollows where we are bivouacked, still we are constantly threatened with death; the soldiers wrote songs, and the jest went around, fun actually being coined from the danger which some comrade escaped, or attempted to nimbly dodge. There was no shirking or quailing; danger had long since ceased to cause any fear. Exploding shells and whistling bullets attracted but little notice. Even death had become so familiar that the fall of a comrade was looked upon with almost stoical indifference; eliciting, perhaps, an expression of pity, and most generally the remark: “I wonder who

will be the next one?” Men are not naturally unmindful of danger, nor do their hearts usually exhibit such indifference to human agony and suffering; yet the occurrence of daily scenes of horror and bloodshed, through which they passed, the shadow of the angel of death constantly hovering over them, made them undisturbed spectators of every occurrence, making the most of today, heedless of the morrow.

CHAPTER XI.

Let us go back to the “White House” and Fort Hill in our front. The Shirley or White House was not far from Fort Hill, and being on a hill overlooked much of the field of operations, and was the frequent resort of Gen. Grant and other commanders during the siege. Several officers and men were shot in this house. A Lieutenant of Battery L went to Colonel Maltby of the 45th Illinois (whose camp was along the “White House”) and asked permission to use a room in the house for making out the battery pay rolls. “Why, certainly,” promptly answered Colonel Maltby, “walk right in; it’s a splendid place. I was shot in the leg here yesterday.”

It is of peculiar interest to the writer, as he was wounded in this house while in the line of duty on July 2, 1863. Mr. Shirley and family were living in this house when on May 18, 1863, the skirmishers of the Union army advanced along the Jackson road, pressed back those of Pemberton’s army into their main defensive line, so close at hand that the salient fort, known as Fort Hill to the Union army, but to the Confederates known as the Third Louisiana Redan, nearly west of the house and immediately north of the road, was not over 350 yards distant. As the building was an obstruction to the fire from the Confederate line, it was to have been destroyed; but, according to the story of Mrs. Eaton, the presence of her mother delayed carrying the order into execution so long that the Confederate soldier who came to do so, while holding a ball of blazing cotton to the building, fell under the fire of the advancing vanguard and was buried the next day upon the spot. As for Mrs. Shirley, she first had a sheet attached to a broomstick and hung from an upper window, which gave some respite from the fire of the Union troops. But their line soon reached the house itself and practically rested there, so that a steady firing upon it from the other side was inevitable. Notwithstanding this, Mrs. Shirley remained there for three days, much of the time sitting behind the large chimney for shelter. Having in the meantime learned of the situation of the Shirley’s, orders came from Gen. McPherson for their removal. They went accordingly, into a shallow cave hastily

prepared in a nearby ravine. Here the family remained for a time, Mrs. Shirley having sickened from exposure and poor fare, but were soon after, by Gen. Grant’s personal direction, removed to a plantation three miles in the rear, where a negro cabin afforded temporary shelter. The Shirley’s were Union people and Mr. Lossing, the historian, says: “That the accomplished daughter kept a diary during the siege, each day’s record closing with the prediction that success would crown the efforts of the Union army.” The wish was father to the thought; her patriotism was rewarded with the heart and hand of the gallant Gen. Eaton of the United States army, and they were married about the close of the war. They now reside in Washington, and if the facts of their courtship and betrothal, conducted amidst the exciting scenes of a terrible siege, were known, it would no doubt be a very interesting romance. But what of the ladies who are in the besieged city? Many of them have left their fine mansions and taken up their abode in the holes and caves of the hills in and around the city, and so universal was this mode of living that the city in its desolation looked like a “prairie dog’s village.” One of the residents of the city afterwards said: “It got to be Sunday all the time; seven Sundays in the week to us anyway. We hadn’t anything to do and the time hung heavy. Seven Sundays, and all of them broken up at one time or another in the day or in the night by a few hours of the awful storm of fire and thunder and iron and lead.” The caves were sometimes fearfully crowded, always hot and close. Oftentimes a cave had from twenty to twenty-five people packed in it; no turning room for anybody, and the air so foul, sometimes, you could not have made a candle burn. A child was born in one of these caves one night during the siege. Generally, there is considerable noise around when a baby is born, but this fellow was welcomed with the booming of cannon and the fierce shriek of the screaming shell. I’ll warrant, if he was like most boys, he tried to make all the noise he could. But he is no longer a baby, at least let us hope he is not, for he is old enough now to be a man all through, being at this time over 50 years of age. I have his picture and a fine-looking man he is. He writes on his picture: “I was born 12 feet under ground.” One night a shell burst in front of one of these caves and stopped up the hole to

such an extent the occupants came near smothering, and for a time there was some lively scratching of dirt for a breathing hole.

Fort Hill is said to be the key to Vicksburg. We have tried often to turn this key, and have as often failed—in fact, the lock is not an easy one, but we soon shall try the burglar’s plan, and with the aid of powder blow the lock to “smithereens.” The sap or trench is run to the fort and the fort is mined, the boys digging the dirt and carrying it out in boxes. Great holes are dug underneath the fort, and miners from the Lead Mine, 45th Illinois Regiment, who understand tamping, have charged the 2,200 pounds of powder, and all is ready to light the fuse. June, the 25th, a heavy artillery fire opened all along the line, and at 2:30 p. m., the explosion takes place. Huge masses of earth were thrown in the air, and the ground was shaken as by an earthquake. As soon as the earth was rent, a bright glare of fire issued from the burning powder, but quickly died away, as there was nothing combustible in the fort. A few Confederate soldiers were hurled into the air, one or two of whom came down inside our lines, and some were buried in the fort, as was proven a few years after the war, when the fort was dismantled and turned into a cotton field, a few skeletons were found buried underneath. One negro boy fell among the men of our company. He gathered himself together, and looked around as though he thought the day of judgment had surely come. One of our boys asked him how far up he thought he had gone, and he replied: “Don’t know, Massa; ’bout free miles, I guess.” He believed it, for I never saw such a frightened look on any one’s face, and his eyes stood out and looked unnatural. When the smoke and dust had cleared away partly, a great saucer-shaped crater was seen, where before was the A-shaped Fort Hill. It was large enough to hold about 60 or 80 men. The 23rd Indiana and the 45th Illinois were in the trenches ready to charge; the command was given before the dust had fully settled; the 23rd Indiana charging to the left of the crater to the top of the works; the 45th Illinois up and into the crater. The enemy had come up behind the big pile of earth thrown out by the explosion, and as we went into the crater, they met us with a terrible volley of musketry, but on the boys went, up and over the embankment with a cheer, the enemy falling back a few paces to an inner or second line of breastworks, where are placed cannon

loaded with grape and canister, and these cannon belched forth their death-dealing missiles, in addition to the heavy musketry fire, with such telling effect that many of the brave boys fall to rise no more; the line wavers, staggers, and then falls back into the crater. The enemy charge on us, but we repel them at the west bank of the crater, and a hand-to-hand conflict rages for hours; hand grenades and loaded shells are lighted and thrown over the parapet as you would play ball. These shells and hand grenades carry death, as many as a dozen men being killed and wounded at one explosion. It seems to me, in looking back, a wonder that any one in that hot place was left to tell the story. I have witnessed our men grab these shells, at the risk of their exploding, and fling them back. Many a brave hero laid down his life in that death hole, or, as we most appropriately called it, “Fort Hell.” The Chicago Tribune had its correspondent in the field and, in the issues of that paper on July 3 and 6, 1863, he speaks of the charge and fighting in the crater, saying: * * * “A wide embrasure in the embankment was made into which the noble Lead Mine Regiment, led by Colonel Maltby, rushed in and at once planted our banner amid a terrific fire from the enemy. The conduct of the 45th Illinois Regiment was grand in the extreme. Universal commendation is bestowed for the gallant manner that regiment performed the duty assigned it, and in no small degree upon the field officers who so nobly inspired the men by taking the advance and marching up to the muzzles of the enemy’s guns, so near that for a time it was a hand-to-hand fight. The colors of the regiment planted on the parapet of the fort are literally torn to pieces by the shots of the enemy. Two of the field officers, Lieut. Col. Smith and Major Fisk, are no more. Col. Maltby is still suffering from a severe wound.”

The 23rd Indiana and 45th Illinois Regiments charging Fort Hill after the explosion of the mine June 25th, 1863, at the siege of Vicksburg.

We fought at close range with the enemy over that embankment of earth, many of the men receiving bayonet wounds. A cypress log, with port holes cut on the under side, was brought into the crater, and in helping to place it on the parapet, Col. James A. Maltby was severely wounded by splinters from the log. A solid shot from a cannon hit the log, hurling it with terrific force against the Colonel and his small command. Gen. John A. Logan said of Col. Maltby, at the siege of Vicksburg: “He is the bravest man I ever saw on the field of battle.” He was in the Mexican War, badly wounded at Chapultepec, then at Fort Donelson in 1862 and then at Vicksburg. He was justly promoted to be a Brigadier General for his bravery. A detail of about two companies would hold the crater for two hours or more, their rapid firing causing the rifles to become hot and foul, and the men weary and worn out, when two other companies would slip in and take their places. Badeau, in his history of Gen. Grant, says: “Details from Leggett’s brigade relieved each other all night long, in their attempt to hold the crater.” I want to correct his history and say, as I have a right to say, for I was there and speak from what I know to be the facts, it was no “attempt,” it was an accomplished fact that we held it, but to our great loss, until the order was received to give it up. What a terrible sacrifice it was to hold that little piece of ground. It probably was all right to have made the charge into the crater after

the explosion and try to make a breech inside the enemy’s lines, but it surely was a serious mistake, either of Gen. Grant or Gen. McPherson, to cause that crater to be held for over 48 hours with the loss of brave men every hour. I remember, upon returning to the trenches, after having been relieved in the crater, of passing Gen. John A. Logan, surrounded by some of his aid-de-camp, and as they bore past him some wounded hero, he broke forth with vehemence, saying: “My God! they are killing my bravest men in that hole.” Some one suggested that the place be given up. He said in reply: “I can’t; my commanding officer orders me to hold every inch of ground.” The crater was at last given up and we resumed the ordinary duties of everyday life in the trenches and in camp.

CHAPTER XII.

The army was without tents, yet very comfortable. They were encamped along the steep hillside, mostly sheltered from the enemy’s shot. A place was dug against the hill, and in many cases, into it, forming a sort of cave. Poles were put up and covered with oil cloths, blankets or cane rods, of which an abundant supply was near at hand. For fuel, the farm fences were laid under contribution, in some cases being hauled for two or three miles. The work of slaughter and destruction went on day and night. The roar of cannon, the rattle of musketry, the sharp crack of the rifle in the hands of the sharpshooters, reached the ear from all sides. There was no cessation, no Let up.

“Cannon to right of them; Cannon to left of them; Cannon in front of them; Volleyed and thundered.”

Stormed at with shot and shell, the beleaugered garrison and the inhabitants of Vicksburg must have felt, as surely as day follows night, that the end could not be much longer delayed. Mines and countermines were dug and sprung. Not a man in the trenches on either side could show his head above the breastworks without being picked off by the sharpshooters. A hat held out for two minutes at a port hole was riddled with minie-balls. Shells searched out all parts of the city, with direful results. Several women and children were killed and wounded during the siege. There were about 1,300 women and children in the city during the bombardment, who, during the greater part of the time, had been obliged to live in caves, cut in the hard clay hills in the city, of which there were several hundred. At this day it may seem to some of my readers that it was cruel and inhuman for the Union forces to fire on defenseless women and children, but what could we do; they were in the city and preferred to remain there to cheer on their husbands and brothers in their work of trying to destroy the Union. To show my readers with what feeling these Southern women showed their hatred of the North and the

boys in blue, let me give a simple extract from a letter written by a Southern wife to her husband in the Confederate army, which letter was captured near Vicksburg. Speaking of the Yankees she says: “If there is an hereafter, a heaven or hell, I pray to go to perdition ere my soul would be joined to rest in heaven with the fiendish foe. It would be some solace to us, when we love our husbands, fathers, sons and friends, to know they were fighting an enemy, civilized or refined in a great degree. But, oh! the thought is killing; is too painful, to see our men, the choicest, most refined specimens of God’s work, destroyed and even forced to take up arms against the offscourings, outcast dregs of creation, for every man they lose is a blessing, a Godsend to humanity and society.” These are strong words, and a woman that could harbor such feelings would have the courage to stay in the doomed city and take her chances with her husband and friends.

To offset this, let me tell you of a romance of the war, which has never been published, and was given me by Comrade Searles, late of Chicago. Gen. Elias E. Dennis, in command of a brigade of our troops during the siege, made his headquarters at a farm house (the home of a widow and family), occupying one portion of it. The General was very kind to the widow and orphans, often providing for them from his own means. One of these children, a bright, winsome little girl of some eight years, took a deep interest in all that transpired, remembering many events of those stirring times, but above all, retaining a most kindly recollection of the General who occupied the house. About twelve years ago a reunion of some old veterans was held at Vicksburg. Comrade Searles, of Chicago, was there, and among the Southern ladies who welcomed them was this little girl, now, of course, grown to womanhood. Accepting her kind invitation to visit her home, the next day found our comrade in the same house where Gen. Dennis had made his headquarters during the siege. Naturally, the conversation turned to the days of 1863. The lady, recalling the many kindnesses of Gen. Dennis, inquired if he were alive, to which Comrade Searles replied: “Why, bless you, I know him personally; he lives at Omaha.” She then asked her comrade if he would be the bearer of a letter to the General, and he replied, “Most gladly.” In due time this was delivered. What its

contents were, none save the writer and the General ever knew, but as he read the letter, his lips quivered and his eyes filled with tears. The General was alone in the world, his wife and only daughter having passed away. Soon after he journeyed south. We know not what the greeting was; no doubt the lady awakened in the mind of the old veteran memories of his own lost, loved child, for shortly after this, he adopted the lady as his daughter. He lived the remainder of his days in Vicksburg, and but recently passed over to the eternal camping ground. When the General’s will was proven, it was found that all his property had been left to his daughter of the Southland.

Another romance that commenced shortly after the surrender of the city is worth recording. A Miss Mary E. Hurlburt, of Danbury, Conn., a Northern girl, was visiting at the Lunn Mansion in the city of Vicksburg at the outbreak of the war, and tarrying too long, was compelled to remain there until the Union forces opened up the Mississippi River. When Gen. Grant captured the city, the officers of those commanding the troops in the city domiciled themselves at different houses. Gen. Leggett and his staff located their headquarters at the Lunn residence. Gen. John A. Rawlins, chief of Gen. Grant’s staff, had occasion to visit the headquarters of Gen. Leggett and naturally met Miss Hurlburt and their acquaintance soon ripened into a love affair, which in a few months culminated in a wedding and the young lady became the wife of Gen. John A. Rawlins, and shared with him in all the honors conferred upon the General as the closest advisor of Gen. Grant, and afterwards as Secretary of War

The month of June, 1863, was rolling by and the glorious 4th of July drew near The Union lines were getting closer and closer, and the question was passed around among the boys, “Shall we spend the Fourth in Vicksburg or in the trenches?” On June 28, the Confederates threw over to our men a small biscuit made of corn meal and peas. To this was attached a very small piece of meat and a note stating that it was one day’s rations. The note went on: “We are pretty hungry and dreadful dry. Old Pemberton has taken all the whisky for the hospitals and our Southern Confederacy is so small just now that we are not in the manufacturing business. Give our

compliments to Gen. Grant and say to him that grub would be acceptable, but we will feel under particular obligations to him if he will send us a few bottles of good whisky.”

Shall I give you the experience of a wounded soldier? Towards the close of the siege, while in the line of duty, a minie-ball from a Confederate sharpshooter went crashing through his right lung. His comrades bore him back a short distance; the surgeon came and seeing where the soldier had been shot, shook his head and said, “he cannot live.” Comrades gathered around, saying in undertones, “poor fellow, he’s got his discharge.” The soldier closed his eyes, and although gasping for breath, as the warm life blood flowed from his wound and gushed from his mouth, saw something—his past life came before him like a living panorama; the good deeds and the evil of his life appeared in a few moments; he thought he was soon to be ushered into eternity, and how would it stand with him there. He breathed one little prayer: “O, Lord, spare my life and I will serve thee all my days.” Presently the ambulance came and he was lifted tenderly into it, to be conveyed two miles to the rear to the brush hospital. The boys said “good-bye.” He was but a youth, not twenty years of age; had been promoted to First Sergeant after the battle of Shiloh and had endeared himself to all in his company, many of whom were old enough to be his father. Louis LaBrush, a Sergeant of the company, a Frenchman by birth, but a true lover of his adopted country, loved this smooth-faced boy, so badly wounded, and begged permission of the Captain to go with the wounded soldier and watch over him. The Captain, seeing the yearning Look in the eyes of the Sergeant, granted permission, and the ambulance started with the old Sergeant watching with a tender care over the little Orderly Sergeant pillowed on his knee. The sun was just sinking to rest when they reached the hospital, which was only a brush shed covered with branches from the trees, in which were long lines of cots upon which the wounded soldiers lay. As the ambulance drew near the surgeon in charge came out, and looking at the wounded man, said: “Put him out there under that tree; he’ll die tonight,” and the old Sergeant put his darling boy out under the tree, laying him tenderly on the ground. The Sergeant and another comrade of his company, Henry Winter, who was a nurse in the hospital, watched by

the boy’s side during the weary hours of the night. At midnight, as the doctor was making his rounds, he observed the Sergeant still under the tree, and went to see if the boy was yet living. Finding that he was, he then made an examination by probing with his fingers into the wounds. The splintered bones pierced the tender flesh and made the boy writhe in pain, although the only protest was the gritting of his teeth. To cause his boy such suffering, after the treatment he had received, was more than the old Frenchman could stand, and he burst forth in a volley of oaths, commanding the doctor to take his hands off immediately or he would kill him, saying, “If he is going to die, let him die in peace; you shall not kill him.” Seeing the fire in the old Sergeant’s eyes, the doctor went away, muttering, “Well, the boy will die anyway.” I want to say right here, that as a rule our surgeons were men of sympathy and did all they could for the soldiers. The example I speak of is one of the exceptions. The next morning the surgeon did not come, but sent word that if the soldier under the tree was still alive, to dress his wound, give him clean clothing and place him on a cot in the hospital. He was alive and that boy recovered, even after the surgeon in the army and the doctors at home said he couldn’t live. That wounded boy lives today and is able to write this book in the year 1915, and he is ever grateful in remembrance of the old French Sergeant and Comrade Henry Winter, whose tender care aided in saving his life.

CHAPTER XIII.

The trite saying of Gen. Sherman that “war is hell” cannot be fully appreciated by the people of this generation; only those who have been through the horrors of war on the battle field and in the hospitals, can fully realize the horrors of war. Let me tell you how one brave man of my company lost his life through the most reckless foolishness. One day during the siege he succeeded in procuring some whisky from some unknown source and drank enough of it to make him half drunk. While in this condition he took it into his head to go out in the open and march out towards Fort Hill, and finding something of interest in the open field, he brought it to camp and boasted to the boys where he got it. Some one went and reported to the First Sergeant that E—— was drunk and had said that he was going to walk right up on top of Fort Hill. The Sergeant detailed a Corporal to watch E—— and keep him in camp, but the soldier having enough whisky in him to make him reckless and without reason or sense, escaped his watch and went boldly up to Fort Hill and climbed the fort, but when on top a bullet from the enemy laid him low. As we boys got the body of our comrade that night and buried it, we could not help but say, that if poor E—— had let the accursed whisky alone he would have been living, and we then declared that liquor was a greater enemy than the men who opposed us with their muskets.

On the 3rd day of July, 1863, a white flag was seen, nearly opposite to the “White House.” Firing ceased in that vicinity and presently several Confederate officers approached our lines to confer with Gen. Grant. The General declined meeting them, but sent word he would meet Gen. Pemberton at 3 o’clock in front of Gen. McPherson’s lines. Soon after Gen. Pemberton came out and met Gen. Grant under a big tree, about midway between the two lines, where they had a conference as to the surrender of Vicksburg, “The Gibralter of America.” After a talk of an hour, possibly, Gen. Pemberton returned inside the fortifications, and then after correspondence lasting until the next day, terms of surrender were

finally agreed upon, and on Saturday, July 4, 1863, the anniversary of American Independence, the garrison of Vicksburg marched out of the works it had defended so long, and stacking their arms, hung their colors on the center, laid off their knapsacks, belts and cartridge boxes, and thus shorn of the accoutrements of the soldier, marched down the road into the city. They went through the ceremony with that downcast look, so touching on a soldier’s face. Not a word was spoken, save the few words of command necessary to be given by their officers, and these were given in a subdued manner. What an army it was—30,000 men and 172 cannon. Gen. J B. McPherson, commanding the 17th Army Corps, addressed a letter to Col. Rawlins, chief of staff to Gen. Grant, saying, “If one regiment goes in advance to the court house to take possession, I respectfully request that it be the 45th Illinois. This regiment has borne the brunt of the battle oftener than any other in my command and always nobly.” Col. Rawlins endorsed this letter, stating that it was left to Gen. McPherson to designate such regiment as he saw proper to go forward and take possession of the court house. Gen. McPherson then sent a letter to Gen. John A. Logan, commanding the third division: “I suggest that the 45th Illinois take the advance in going into the city.” Now the boys in blue take up their line of march into the city. Gen. Badeau, in his history of Gen. Grant says: “Logan’s division was one of those which had approached nearest the works, and now was the first to enter the town. It had been heavily engaged in both assaults and was fairly entitled to this honor. The 45th Illinois Infantry marched at the head of the line and placed its battle-torn flag on the court house in Vicksburg. Gen. Grant and Gen. Logan rode into the town at the head of Logan’s division.”

When inside the works, and in the city, the men of the two armies affiliated at once. Groups of Union and Confederate soldiers could be seen wherever there was a shady place; the Union soldier pumping the rebel and giving him in return for the information hard tack and bacon, which the poor famished fellows accepted with a grateful look. The Confederates reclined on the glass and while munching their hard tack, tell what they “reckon” is their loss; how long they “allowed” to hold out; how our sharpshooters killed “right smart” of their men and they wish “we’uns” and “you’uns” could have

this war ended and all live together in peace. Many of the Union and Confederate soldiers were seen walking arm in arm; they felt they were countrymen. Five days’ rations were issued to the prisoners, consisting of bacon, hominy, peas, coffee, sugar, soap, salt and crackers.

Here is what one of the Confederates wrote about it: “How the famished troops enjoyed such bounteous supplies, it is needless to state. For once the brave boys were now objects of their enemy’s charity. They grew jovial and hilarious over the change in their condition. The Yankees came freely among them and were unusually kind. They asked innumerable questions and were horrified at the fact of the men eating mules and rats.” After feeding and paroling this large army of men, for it took several days to parole them, they silently and sadly marched out and off to their homes, while the boys in blue and the people of the North were full of rejoicing. Here is a few lines, composed by one of the boys in blue at the time:

“The armies of the Union ’Round Vicksburg long had lain, For forty-seven days and nights, Besieging it in vain. Then came the morning of the Fourth, Our nation’s jubilee.

Ah, could the news this hour go forth, In Vicksburg soon we’ll be. The siege is done, the struggle past, On this eventful day; Glad tidings crown us as at last Our thanks to God we pay.”

Yes, Old Glory floated over Vicksburg on July 4, 1863, and what rejoicing there was throughout the North when the news came to your homes that Vicksburg had fallen. Yes, Old Glory still floats there, and may we earnestly hope it will continue to wave as long as the city remains. We can rejoice today that we live to see a reunited people with one country and one flag. But while rejoicing, let us not forget those who have died on fields of honor, and while the years

Turn static files into dynamic content formats.

Create a flipbook
Issuu converts static files into: digital portfolios, online yearbooks, online catalogs, digital photo albums and more. Sign up and create your flipbook.